1 III Animal Rights. 2 Background This paper is a condensed version of the central argument presented in Regan’s 1983 book, The Case for Animal Rights.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 19 Regan & The Case for Animal Rights
Advertisements

Animal Rights.
The Human Conscience in Animal Rights “Discrimination on the basis of sex, it has been said, is the last universally accepted form of discrimination, practiced.
1 Is Abortion Wrong? I I. 2 Some Background 1 st Mo.2 nd Mo.3 rd Mo.4 th Mo.5 th Mo.6 th Mo.7 th Mo.8 th Mo.9 th Mo. Conception “Zygote” “Embryo” “Fetus”
How to Talk About Rights. What is a right? “What people are entitled to have or do or receive.” -- John Mackie “To have a right is to be in a position.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 20 Cohen & The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research By David Kelsey.
The Moral Status of the Non- Human World: Matheny
HUMANS AND NON-HUMANS A Spectrum “ Western ” paradigm emphasizes gulf between humans and animals ■ Religious traditions: humans as “the crown of creation”,
The moral importance of agency Frederike Kaldewaij Philosophy Department, Utrecht University Expert Meeting Fish welfare:
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
The Moral Status of Animals Kant, Singer, Steinbock.
Ethical Issue Animal Rights. Ethical Issue: Animal Rights What do you think about the following practices? Shooting live animals with bullets to study.
The Case for Animals Singer’s Utilitarian Argument  What is morally relevant?  What makes someone/somethi ng worthy of moral consideration?  What.
Different Ethical Approaches Contractarianism Rules “signers” of the contract agree to abide by. We have a direct duty to respect the rights of “signers.”
Do Animals Have Rights? Regan vs. Warren. Steve Jobs Joe Blow BDO / Chimp Dolphin Dog Tuna Clam Equal inherent value Equal right to be treated with respect.
The Moral Status of the Non-Human World: Cohen and Warren
Animals and Society: An Introduction to Human-Animal Studies
Phil 160 Kant.
1 II Animal Rights. 2 Note: Cohen’s paper was published in the New England Journal of Medicine; his primary audience consisted of doctors, not philosophers.
The Moral Status of the Non- Human World: Singer and Cohen.
Philosophy 220 The Moral Status of the Non-Human World: Cohen and Warren.
Animal Rights Broad View - Animals have the same moral worth that humans have, and the moral obligations we have to animals are the same that we have.
360 Business Ethics Chapter 4. Moral facts derived from reason Reason has three properties that have bearing on moral facts understood as the outcomes.
1 III Is it Wrong to Kill Non-Human Animals?. 2 Narveson’s Project Narveson argues that Regan’s claims against Contractarianism fail. Narveson argues.
World Hunger and Poverty: Sen and O’Neill
COMP 381. Agenda  TA: Caitlyn Losee  Books and movies nominations  Team presentation signup Beginning of class End of class  Rawls and Moors.
1 I I Animal Rights. 2 Singer’s Project Singer argues we should extend to other species the “basic principle of equality” that most of us recognize should.
Animal Rights.
Animals and Persons (cont.). Tom Regan Contemporary American Philosopher Deontologist, in the tradition of Kant Specialist in animal rights The Case for.
The treatment of animals Michael Lacewing
Is Same-Sex Marriage Wrong?
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 19 Regan & The Case for Animal Rights By David Kelsey.
Why Philosophy?. Philosophy: A study of the processes governing thought and conduct. A system of principles for the conduct of life. A study of human.
1 III World Hunger & Poverty. 2 Arthur’s Central Argument John Arthur: “World Hunger and Moral Obligation” 1)Ignores an important moral factor: entitlement.
Highlights of the UN Convention On the Rights of the Child
Business Ethics Lecture Rights and Duties 1.
Kant Good Will –Morally praiseworthy actions are done from a sense of duty. Our duty is to follow the right moral rules.
Peter Singer: “All Animals are Equal ”
The Moral Status of the Non-Human World: Regan, Warren and Curnutt
Our Interpretation of 6 Articles From the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 20 Cohen & The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research By David Kelsey.
Abortion and Moral Considerability
Animal Rights Are you a speciesist?. Animal Rights in the News.
Philosophy 220 Animal Rights. Regan and Animal Rights Tom Regan makes clear his commitment to the animal rights movement. As he articulates it, that movement.
Animals and Persons. Ethical status for animals Kantian and utilitarian ethics traditionally extended to all people, but only people Kant: all rational.
Kant and Kantian Ethics: Is it possible for “reason” to supply the absolute principles of morality?
Arthur’s Criticism of Singer Entitlements and “Realistic Morality”
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
MNU Five Other Ethical Systems Dr. Judy Martin Session 7 – February 18, 2014.
MODERN UTILITARIANISM AND GENETIC ENGINEERING IS IT WRONG TO INTERFERE WITH NATURE? CAN WE JUSTIFY THE SACRIFICE OF A FEW LIVES TO SAVE MANY? DO ANIMALS.
WEEK 2 Justice as Fairness. A Theory of Justice (1971) Political Liberalism (1993)
Chapter 8: The Ethical Treatment of Animals Gaverick Matheny, “Utilitarianism and Animals” – Matheny's main 2-part argument (part 1): 1. Being sentient.
Philosophical approaches to animal ethics
Chapter 9: The Ethical Treatment of Animals
Michael Lacewing Eating animals Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
It is unclear exactly what counts as a benefit or a cost
universalizability & reversibility
Animals and Persons.
Kant and Kantian Ethics:
On Whiteboards: Do animals have any moral status (should they be considered when making moral decisions)? Whether you answered yes or no, say why. On what.
All animals are equal.
Lecture 09: A Brief Summary
Kant’s view on animals is ‘anthropocentric’ in that it is based on a sharp distinction between humans and non-human animals. According to Kant, only.
Kat Angelini & Miranda Chapman
Kant, Anderson, Marginal Cases
Lecture 06: A Brief Summary
Animal Suffering and Rights
All Animals are Created Equal
Kant and Regan.
Speciesism and the Idea of Equality
Presentation transcript:

1 III Animal Rights

2 Background This paper is a condensed version of the central argument presented in Regan’s 1983 book, The Case for Animal Rights. Tom Regan: “The Case for Animal Rights ” Regan’s Central Argument P1Typical human beings have the right not to be treated as mere resources for others. P2If typical human beings have the right not to be treated as a mere resource for others, then the individual that is the experiencing subject of a life has a right not to be treated as a mere resource for others. P3Many nonhuman animals are the experiencing subjects of a life. CTherefore, many nonhuman animals have the right not to be treated as a mere resource for others.

3 Goals of the Animal Rights Movement (1)The total abolition of the use of animals in science; (2)The total dissolution of commercial animal agriculture; (3)The total elimination of commercial and sport hunting and trapping. The animal rights movement calls for (or should call for) no less than the following:

4 What’s the Problem? The problem with the way animals are treated (whether as potential food, or as subjects of experimentation) is not a case-by-case problem, but a problem with the whole system of how we treat animals.  The problem isn’t the pain.  The problem isn’t the suffering.  The problem isn’t the deprivation.  These only compound what’s wrong.  The fundamental problem is that the system allows us to view animals as our resources, to be eaten, surgically manipulated, or exploited for sport or money. A veal calf raised “free range” to be killed is treated in this way just as much as is one raised in close confinement to be killed.

5 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? We have duties regarding animals, but not duties to animals. We have duties regarding animals insofar as: i.they are the property of people, and we have duties to their owners not to harm their property; or ii.they are beloved by people, and we have duties to the such people not to harm what they love. I. Indirect Duty Views If I kick your dog, then I have done something wrong to you, but not to your dog. I no more harm your dog than I would harm your car if I smashed its windshield. Rather, I harm you.

6 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? Not on the basis that the dog feels no pain. Not on the basis that the dog’s pain doesn’t matter, that only the human’s does. Rather, we need some underlying moral theory. How Would We Justify Indirect Duty Views? Morality consists of assent to rules that individuals voluntarily agree to abide by, as we do when we sign a contract. Those who understand and accept the terms of the contract are covered directly – their rights are created by, and protected under, the contract. Beings who lack the necessary level of understanding (children, animals, the mentally retarded) cannot enter into the contract, and so have no rights of their own. (i) “Crude” Contractarianism

7 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? But they may be protected by others who can because of their sentimental value to them. Where humans have little-to-no sentimental attachment to some animals (farm animals, lab rats, crab lice…), our duties regarding them are weaker and weaker. If no one cares about them, their pain and deaths simply do not matter.

8 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? According to Contractarianism, morality consists in rules that people agree to abide by. Problems with Crude Contractarianism :  What people? The ones with the power to enforce them, apparently. This isn’t very good for those who don’t agree. As a result, this approach could sanction blatant forms of social, economic, moral, and political injustice

9 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? A more subtle form of Contractarianism, set forth in A Theory of Justice. Contractors are forced to ignore the “accidental” features of being a human being. (ii) John Rawls’ Contractarianism  Race  Sex  Intelligence Despite the obvious improvements to “Crude” Contractarianism, it still systematically excludes those without any sense of justice, and so claims we have no duties to them.  Children  The Mentally Retarded

10 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? It seems reasonable that, were I to torture a child or a mentally-retarded adult, I would be doing some wrong to that individual. If Rawls’ Contractarianism does not work for children and the mentally retarded, it will not work for animals.

11 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? We have a direct duty to be kind to animals and a direct duty not to be cruel to them.  Problem 1: That an act is kind does not necessarily show that it is a right act, nor does an act have to be kind in order to be right.  Problem 2: The absence of cruelty in an act does not show that the act is not wrong. II. Direct Duty Views (i) Cruelty-Kindness View

12 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? The Utilitarian Maxim: An action is right insofar as it brings about (or tends to bring about) the most good on aggregate. Utilitarianism implies two moral principles: (ii) Utilitarianism i.Everyone’s interests count (recall Singer’s argument) ; ii.One should do the act that will bring about the best balance between satisfaction and frustration for everyone affected by the outcome. What makes Utilitarianism so appealing is that everyone’s interests count as much as the like interests of everyone else.

13 How are the Rights of Animals Traditionally Denied? Problem 1: Utilitarianism has no room for the equal moral rights of different individuals because it has no room for their equal inherent value or worth. Problem 2: It appears not only that it is not wrong to kill an innocent person to benefit a number of others, but moreover that it is our duty to do so.  What has value for the Utilitarian is the individual’s interests, not the individual himself.

14 Human Value The value of individuals is inherent value – we are something more than mere receptacles of valuable things. All who have inherent value have it equally, regardless of sex, race, religion, birthplace, etc. As such, all who have inherent value have equal right to be treated with respect, not as resources for others. Your value as an individual is not dependent on your usefulness to others. To fail to treat someone in ways that show respect for their independent value is to act immorally: to violate their rights. In principle, then, racial, sexual, and social discrimination are immoral. It would, as such, be wrong to kill an innocent person to benefit a number of others: that would be to sanction the disrespectful treatment of the individual in the name of a social good.

15 Animal Value Non-human animals lack the abilities that humans possess, like rationality. Of course, so do many humans, and we don’t, or shouldn’t, say that they therefore lack inherent value. “It is the similarities between those human beings who most clearly, most non-controversially have such value […], not our differences, that matter most. And the really crucial, the basic similarity is simply this: we are each of us the experiencing subject of a life, a conscious creature having an individual welfare that has importance to us whatever our usefulness to others.” (149) It is also true of many non-human animals that they must be viewed as the experiencing subjects of a life, with inherent value of their own.

16 Animal Value How might one deny that animals have inherent value?  That only humans have the requisite intelligence, autonomy, or reason? Clearly, we view children as having inherent value, so this can’t be the basis.  That only humans belong to the right species, i.e. Homo sapiens? This is blatant speciesism, so this can’t be the basis.  Perhaps animals have some inherent value, only less than we have? Seemingly, we would have to make such an argument on the basis that they have less intelligence, autonomy, reason, or some other capacity. But, again, if that is the case, then the same would be true for some humans, and there seems no reason to think so.

17 Animal Value Rather, it seems that all beings with inherent value have it equally, whether they are human or not. Since the vast majority of animals qualify as subjects of a life, they have inherent value. Thus, we must recognize the equal inherent value of animals, and treat them with this respect.

18 Repercussions “The theory that rationally grounds the rights of animals also grounds the rights of humans. Thus those involved in the animal rights movement are partners in the struggle to secure respect for human rights—the rights of women, for example, or minorities, or works. The animal rights movement is cut from the same moral cloth as these.” (150) The respect we owe animals is routinely ignored when we raise them, hunt them, eat them, and use them in experimentation. This view categorically implies that we should cease all such practices.