Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic (Part II) Reading: R&N Chapters 8, 9.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic
Advertisements

First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic CS 271: Fall 2007 Instructor: Padhraic Smyth.
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic
Artificial Intelligence Lecture No. 10 Dr. Asad Ali Safi ​ Assistant Professor, Department of Computer Science, COMSATS Institute of Information Technology.
First-Order Logic Syntax
Logic. Propositional Logic Logic as a Knowledge Representation Language A Logic is a formal language, with precisely defined syntax and semantics, which.
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic (Part II) Reading: Chapter 8, First lecture slides read: Second lecture slides read:
Logical Agents Chapter 7. Why Do We Need Logic? Problem-solving agents were very inflexible: hard code every possible state. Search is almost always exponential.
Logical Agents Chapter 7. Why Do We Need Logic? Problem-solving agents were very inflexible: hard code every possible state. Search is almost always exponential.
FIRST-ORDER LOGIC FOL or FOPC
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Problem of Propositional Logic  Propositional logic has very limited expressive power –E.g., cannot say "pits cause breezes.
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic (Part III) This lecture: R&N Chapters 8, 9 Next lecture: Chapter 13; Chapter (Please read lecture.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Outline Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Wumpus world in FOL Knowledge engineering in FOL.
Predicate Calculus.
CE An introduction to Artificial Intelligence CE Chapter 8: First Order Logic Ramin Halavati In which we notice that.
First-Order Logic Knowledge Representation Reading: Chapter 8, , FOL Syntax and Semantics read: FOL Knowledge Engineering read:
Reading: Chapter 8, , FOL Syntax and Semantics read:
Artificial Intelligence Building Knowledge Base Chapter 8.
Propositional Logic: Logical Agents (Part I) This lecture topic: Propositional Logic (two lectures) Chapter (this lecture, Part I) Chapter 7.5.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
First-Order Logic Semantics Reading: Chapter 8, , FOL Syntax and Semantics read: FOL Knowledge Engineering read: FOL.
1 Logical Agents CS 171/271 (Chapter 7) Some text and images in these slides were drawn from Russel & Norvig’s published material.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Outline Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Wumpus world in FOL Knowledge engineering in FOL.
1 First-Order Logic Chapter 8. 2 Why FOL? –How do you say “All students are smart?” –Some students work hard –Hardworking students have good marks –If.
© Copyright 2008 STI INNSBRUCK Intelligent Systems Predicate Logic.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Outline Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Wumpus world in FOL Knowledge engineering in FOL.
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic 부산대학교 전자전기컴퓨터공학과 인공지능연구실 김민호
Limitation of propositional logic  Propositional logic has very limited expressive power –(unlike natural language) –E.g., cannot say "pits cause breezes.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Outline Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Wumpus world in FOL Knowledge engineering in FOL.
CS 666 AI P. T. Chung First-Order Logic First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
1 Logical Agents CS 171/271 (Chapter 7) Some text and images in these slides were drawn from Russel & Norvig’s published material.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Outline Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Wumpus world in FOL Knowledge engineering in FOL.
Artificial Intelligence First-Order Logic (FOL). Outline of this Chapter The need for FOL? What is a FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL.
For Wednesday Read chapter 9, sections 1-3 Homework: –Chapter 7, exercises 8 and 9.
For Friday Read chapter 8 Homework: –Chapter 7, exercises 2 and 10 Program 1, Milestone 2 due.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8 (not 8.1). Outline Why FOL? Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Using FOL Wumpus world.
First-Order Logic. Outline Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Knowledge engineering in FOL.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Outline Why FOL? Syntax and semantics of FOL Using FOL Wumpus world in FOL Knowledge engineering in FOL.
5/16/2005EE562 EE562 ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE FOR ENGINEERS Lecture 12, 5/16/2005 University of Washington, Department of Electrical Engineering Spring.
First-Order Logic Semantics Reading: Chapter 8, , FOL Syntax and Semantics read: FOL Knowledge Engineering read: FOL.
LOGIC Heng Ji Feb 19, Logic Knowledge-based agents Knowledge base (KB) = set of sentences in a formal language Declarative approach.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8. Problem of Propositional Logic  Propositional logic has very limited expressive power –E.g., cannot say "pits cause breezes.
CPSC 420 – Artificial Intelligence Texas A & M University Lecture 7 Lecturer: Laurie webster II, M.S.S.E., M.S.E.e., M.S.BME, Ph.D., P.E.
© Copyright 2008 STI INNSBRUCK Intelligent Systems – Predicate Logic Florian Fischer Partially based on CS188,
Propositional Logic: Logical Agents (Part I)
First-Order Logic Knowledge Representation
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
First-Order Logic.
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
Artificial Intelligence First Order Logic
Notes 8: Predicate logic and inference
First-Order Logic Knowledge Representation
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic
Artificial Intelligence 1: First-Order Logic
First-Order Logic Knowledge Representation
First-Order Logic Knowledge Representation
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
Artificial Intelligence: Agents and First-Order Logic
Introduction to Artificial Intelligence
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic (Part III)
First-Order Logic Knowledge Representation
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic
Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
First-Order Logic Chapter 8.
Presentation transcript:

Knowledge Representation using First-Order Logic (Part II) Reading: R&N Chapters 8, 9

Outline Review: KB |= S is equivalent to |= (KB  S) –So what does {} |= S mean? Review: Follows, Entails, Derives –Follows: “Is it the case?” –Entails: “Is it true?” –Derives: “Is it provable?” Review: FOL syntax Finish FOL Semantics, FOL examples Inference in FOL Next Tuesday (1 June) is Review/Catch-up; Homework#7 is due Next Thursday (3 June) NO CLASS; I’m reviewing grants for NIH Next Friday (4 June) PROJECT REPORTS & CODE is due Following Thursday (10 June) FINAL EXAM; 1:30-3:30pm

Review: KB |= S means |= (KB  S) KB |= S is read “KB entails S.” –Means “S is true in every world (model) in which KB is true.” –Means “In the world, S follows from KB.” KB |= S is equivalent to |= (KB  S) –Means “(KB  S) is true in every world (i.e., is valid).” And so: {} |= S is equivalent to |= ({}  S) So what does ({}  S) mean? –Means “True implies S.” –Means “S is valid.” –In Horn form, means “S is a fact.” p. 256 (3 rd ed.; p. 281, 2 nd ed.) Why does {} mean True here, but False in resolution proofs?

Review: (True  S) means “S is a fact.” By convention, –The null conjunct is “syntactic sugar” for True. –The null disjunct is “syntactic sugar” for False. –Each is assigned the truth value of its identity element. For conjuncts, True is the identity: (A  True)  A For disjuncts, False is the identity: (A  False)  A A KB is the conjunction of all of its sentences. –So in the expression: {} |= S We see that {} is the null conjunct and means True. –The expression means “S is true in every world where True is true.” I.e., “S is valid.” –Better way to think of it: {} does not exclude any worlds (models). In Conjunctive Normal Form each clause is a disjunct. –So in, say, KB = { {P Q} {Q R} {} {X Y Z} } We see that {} is the null disjunct and means False.

Side Trip: Functions AND, OR, and null values (Note: These are “syntactic sugar” in logic.) function AND(arglist) returns a truth-value return ANDOR(arglist, True) function OR(arglist) returns a truth-value return ANDOR(arglist, False) function ANDOR(arglist, nullvalue) returns a truth-value /* nullvalue is the identity element for the caller. */ if (arglist = {}) then return nullvalue if ( FIRST(arglist) = NOT(nullvalue) ) then return NOT(nullvalue) return ANDOR( REST(arglist) )

Review: Schematic for Follows, Entails, and Derives If KB is true in the real world, then any sentence  entailed by KB and any sentence  derived from KB by a sound inference procedure is also true in the real world. Sentences Sentence Derives Inference

Schematic Example: Follows, Entails, and Derives Inference “Mary is Sue’s sister and Amy is Sue’s daughter.” “Mary is Amy’s aunt.” Representation Derives Entails Follows World MarySue Amy “Mary is Sue’s sister and Amy is Sue’s daughter.” “An aunt is a sister of a parent.” Sister Daughter Mary Amy Aunt “Mary is Amy’s aunt.” Is it provable? Is it true? Is it the case?

Review: Models (and in FOL, Interpretations) Models are formal worlds in which truth can be evaluated We say m is a model of a sentence α if α is true in m M(α) is the set of all models of α Then KB ╞ α iff M(KB)  M(α) –E.g. KB, = “Mary is Sue’s sister and Amy is Sue’s daughter.” –α = “Mary is Amy’s aunt.” Think of KB and α as constraints, and of models m as possible states. M(KB) are the solutions to KB and M(α) the solutions to α. Then, KB ╞ α, i.e., ╞ (KB  a), when all solutions to KB are also solutions to α.

Review: Wumpus models KB = all possible wumpus-worlds consistent with the observations and the “physics” of the Wumpus world.

Review: Wumpus models α 1 = "[1,2] is safe", KB ╞ α 1, proved by model checking. Every model that makes KB true also makes α 1 true.

Review: Syntax of FOL: Basic elements ConstantsKingJohn, 2, UCI,... PredicatesBrother, >,... FunctionsSqrt, LeftLegOf,... Variablesx, y, a, b,... Connectives, , , ,  Equality= Quantifiers , 

Syntax of FOL: Basic syntax elements are symbols Constant Symbols: –Stand for objects in the world. E.g., KingJohn, 2, UCI,... Predicate Symbols –Stand for relations (maps a tuple of objects to a truth-value) E.g., Brother(Richard, John), greater_than(3,2),... –P(x, y) is usually read as “x is P of y.” E.g., Mother(Ann, Sue) is usually “Ann is Mother of Sue.” Function Symbols –Stand for functions (maps a tuple of objects to an object) E.g., Sqrt(3), LeftLegOf(John),... Model (world) = set of domain objects, relations, functions Interpretation maps symbols onto the model (world) –Very many interpretations are possible for each KB and world! –Job of the KB is to rule out models inconsistent with our knowledge.

Syntax of FOL: Terms Term = logical expression that refers to an object There are two kinds of terms: –Constant Symbols stand for (or name) objects: E.g., KingJohn, 2, UCI, Wumpus,... –Function Symbols map tuples of objects to an object: E.g., LeftLeg(KingJohn), Mother(Mary), Sqrt(x) This is nothing but a complicated kind of name –No “subroutine” call, no “return value”

Syntax of FOL: Atomic Sentences Atomic Sentences state facts (logical truth values). –An atomic sentence is a Predicate symbol, optionally followed by a parenthesized list of any argument terms –E.g., Married( Father(Richard), Mother(John) ) –An atomic sentence asserts that some relationship (some predicate) holds among the objects that are its arguments. An Atomic Sentence is true in a given model if the relation referred to by the predicate symbol holds among the objects (terms) referred to by the arguments.

Syntax of FOL: Connectives & Complex Sentences Complex Sentences are formed in the same way, and are formed using the same logical connectives, as we already know from propositional logic The Logical Connectives: – biconditional – implication – and – or – negation Semantics for these logical connectives are the same as we already know from propositional logic.

Syntax of FOL: Variables Variables range over objects in the world. A variable is like a term because it represents an object. A variable may be used wherever a term may be used. –Variables may be arguments to functions and predicates. (A term with NO variables is called a ground term.) (A variable not bound by a quantifier is called free.)

Syntax of FOL: Logical Quantifiers There are two Logical Quantifiers: –Universal:  x P(x) means “For all x, P(x).” The “upside-down A” reminds you of “ALL.” –Existential:  x P(x) means “There exists x such that, P(x).” The “upside-down E” reminds you of “EXISTS.” Syntactic “sugar” --- we really only need one quantifier. – x P(x)   x P(x) – x P(x)   x P(x) –You can ALWAYS convert one quantifier to the other. RULES:    and    RULE: To move negation “in” across a quantifier, change the quantifier to “the other quantifier” and negate the predicate on “the other side.” – x P(x)   x P(x) – x P(x)   x P(x)

Existential Quantification  Existential quantification is equivalent to: –Disjunction of all sentences obtained by substitution of an object for the quantified variable. Spot has a sister who is a cat. –x Sister(x, Spot)  Cat(x) Disjunction of all sentences obtained by substitution of an object for the quantified variable: Sister(Spot, Spot)  Cat(Spot)  Sister(Rick, Spot)  Cat(Rick)  Sister(LAX, Spot)  Cat(LAX)  Sister(Shayama, Spot)  Cat(Shayama)  Sister(France, Spot)  Cat(France)  Sister(Felix, Spot)  Cat(Felix)  …

Combining Quantifiers --- Order (Scope) The order of “unlike” quantifiers is important.  x  y Loves(x,y) –For everyone (“all x”) there is someone (“exists y”) whom they love y  x Loves(x,y) - there is someone (“exists y”) whom everyone loves (“all x”) Clearer with parentheses:  y (  x Loves(x,y) ) The order of “like” quantifiers does not matter. x y P(x, y)  y x P(x, y) x y P(x, y)  y x P(x, y)

De Morgan’s Law for Quantifiers De Morgan’s Rule Generalized De Morgan’s Rule Rule is simple: if you bring a negation inside a disjunction or a conjunction, always switch between them (or  and, and  or).

FOL (or FOPC) Ontology: What kind of things exist in the world? What do we need to describe and reason about? Objects --- with their relations, functions, predicates, properties, and general rules. Reasoning Representation A Formal Symbol System Inference Formal Pattern Matching Syntax What is said Semantics What it means Schema Rules of Inference Execution Search Strategy This lectureNext lecture

Semantics: Worlds The world consists of objects that have properties. –There are relations and functions between these objects –Objects in the world, individuals: people, houses, numbers, colors, baseball games, wars, centuries Clock A, John, 7, the-house in the corner, Tel-Aviv –Functions on individuals: father-of, best friend, third inning of, one more than –Relations: brother-of, bigger than, inside, part-of, has color, occurred after –Properties (a relation of arity 1): red, round, bogus, prime, multistoried, beautiful

Semantics: Interpretation An interpretation of a sentence (wff) is an assignment that maps –Object constant symbols to objects in the world, –n-ary function symbols to n-ary functions in the world, –n-ary relation symbols to n-ary relations in the world Given an interpretation, an atomic sentence has the value “true” if it denotes a relation that holds for those individuals denoted in the terms. Otherwise it has the value “false.” –Example: Kinship world: Symbols = Ann, Bill, Sue, Married, Parent, Child, Sibling, … –World consists of individuals in relations: Married(Ann,Bill) is false, Parent(Bill,Sue) is true, …

Truth in first-order logic Sentences are true with respect to a model and an interpretation Model contains objects (domain elements) and relations among them Interpretation specifies referents for constant symbols → objects predicate symbols → relations function symbols → functional relations An atomic sentence predicate(term 1,...,term n ) is true iff the objects referred to by term 1,...,term n are in the relation referred to by predicate

Semantics: Models An interpretation satisfies a wff (sentence) if the wff has the value “true” under the interpretation. Model: A domain and an interpretation that satisfies a wff is a model of that wff Validity: Any wff that has the value “true” under all interpretations is valid Any wff that does not have a model is inconsistent or unsatisfiable If a wff w has a value true under all the models of a set of sentences KB then KB logically entails w

Models for FOL: Example

Using FOL We want to TELL things to the KB, e.g. TELL(KB, ) TELL(KB, King(John) ) These sentences are assertions We also want to ASK things to the KB, ASK(KB, ) these are queries or goals The KB should return the list of x’s for which Person(x) is true: {x/John,x/Richard,...}

FOL Version of Wumpus World Typical percept sentence: Percept([Stench,Breeze,Glitter,None,None],5) Actions: Turn(Right), Turn(Left), Forward, Shoot, Grab, Release, Climb To determine best action, construct query:  a BestAction(a,5 ) ASK solves this and returns {a/Grab} –And TELL about the action.

Knowledge Base for Wumpus World Perception –s,b,g,x,y,t Percept([s,Breeze,g,x,y],t)  Breeze(t) –s,b,x,y,t Percept([s,b,Glitter,x,y],t)  Glitter(t) Reflex action –t Glitter(t)  BestAction(Grab,t) Reflex action with internal state –t Glitter(t) Holding(Gold,t)  BestAction(Grab,t) Holding(Gold,t) can not be observed: keep track of change.

Deducing hidden properties Environment definition: x,y,a,b Adjacent([x,y],[a,b])  [a,b]  {[x+1,y], [x-1,y],[x,y+1],[x,y-1]} Properties of locations: s,t At(Agent,s,t)  Breeze(t)  Breezy(s) Squares are breezy near a pit: –Diagnostic rule---infer cause from effect s Breezy(s)   r Adjacent(r,s)  Pit(r) –Causal rule---infer effect from cause (model based reasoning) r Pit(r)  [s Adjacent(r,s)  Breezy(s)]

Set Theory in First-Order Logic Can we define set theory using FOL? - individual sets, union, intersection, etc Answer is yes. Basics: - empty set = constant = { } - unary predicate Set( ), true for sets - binary predicates: x  s (true if x is a member of the set x) s 1  s 2 (true if s1 is a subset of s2) - binary functions: intersection s 1  s 2, union s 1  s 2, adjoining {x|s}

A Possible Set of FOL Axioms for Set Theory The only sets are the empty set and sets made by adjoining an element to a set s Set(s)  (s = {} )  (x,s 2 Set(s 2 )  s = {x|s 2 }) The empty set has no elements adjoined to it x,s {x|s} = {} Adjoining an element already in the set has no effect x,s x  s  s = {x|s} The only elements of a set are those that were adjoined into it. Expressed recursively: x,s x  s  [ y,s 2 (s = {y|s 2 }  (x = y  x  s 2 ))]

A Possible Set of FOL Axioms for Set Theory A set is a subset of another set iff all the first set’s members are members of the 2 nd set s 1,s 2 s 1  s 2  (x x  s 1  x  s 2 ) Two sets are equal iff each is a subset of the other s 1,s 2 (s 1 = s 2 )  (s 1  s 2  s 2  s 1 ) An object is in the intersection of 2 sets only if a member of both x,s 1,s 2 x  (s 1  s 2 )  (x  s 1  x  s 2 ) An object is in the union of 2 sets only if a member of either x,s 1,s 2 x  (s 1  s 2 )  (x  s 1  x  s 2 )

Knowledge engineering in FOL 1.Identify the task 2.Assemble the relevant knowledge 3.Decide on a vocabulary of predicates, functions, and constants 4.Encode general knowledge about the domain 5.Encode a description of the specific problem instance 6.Pose queries to the inference procedure and get answers 7.Debug the knowledge base

The electronic circuits domain One-bit full adder Possible queries: - does the circuit function properly? - what gates are connected to the first input terminal? - what would happen if one of the gates is broken? and so on

The electronic circuits domain 1.Identify the task –Does the circuit actually add properly? 2.Assemble the relevant knowledge –Composed of wires and gates; Types of gates (AND, OR, XOR, NOT) –Irrelevant: size, shape, color, cost of gates 3.Decide on a vocabulary –Alternatives: Type(X 1 ) = XOR (function) Type(X 1, XOR) (binary predicate) XOR(X 1 ) (unary predicate)

The electronic circuits domain 4.Encode general knowledge of the domain –t 1,t 2 Connected(t 1, t 2 )  Signal(t 1 ) = Signal(t 2 ) –t Signal(t) = 1  Signal(t) = 0 –1 ≠ 0 –t 1,t 2 Connected(t 1, t 2 )  Connected(t 2, t 1 ) –g Type(g) = OR  Signal(Out(1,g)) = 1  n Signal(In(n,g)) = 1 –g Type(g) = AND  Signal(Out(1,g)) = 0  n Signal(In(n,g)) = 0 –g Type(g) = XOR  Signal(Out(1,g)) = 1  Signal(In(1,g)) ≠ Signal(In(2,g)) –g Type(g) = NOT  Signal(Out(1,g)) ≠ Signal(In(1,g))

The electronic circuits domain 5.Encode the specific problem instance Type(X 1 ) = XOR Type(X 2 ) = XOR Type(A 1 ) = AND Type(A 2 ) = AND Type(O 1 ) = OR Connected(Out(1,X 1 ),In(1,X 2 ))Connected(In(1,C 1 ),In(1,X 1 )) Connected(Out(1,X 1 ),In(2,A 2 ))Connected(In(1,C 1 ),In(1,A 1 )) Connected(Out(1,A 2 ),In(1,O 1 )) Connected(In(2,C 1 ),In(2,X 1 )) Connected(Out(1,A 1 ),In(2,O 1 )) Connected(In(2,C 1 ),In(2,A 1 )) Connected(Out(1,X 2 ),Out(1,C 1 )) Connected(In(3,C 1 ),In(2,X 2 )) Connected(Out(1,O 1 ),Out(2,C 1 )) Connected(In(3,C 1 ),In(1,A 2 ))

The electronic circuits domain 6.Pose queries to the inference procedure What are the possible sets of values of all the terminals for the adder circuit? i 1,i 2,i 3,o 1,o 2 Signal(In(1,C_1)) = i 1  Signal(In(2,C 1 )) = i 2  Signal(In(3,C 1 )) = i 3  Signal(Out(1,C 1 )) = o 1  Signal(Out(2,C 1 )) = o 2 7.Debug the knowledge base May have omitted assertions like 1 ≠ 0

Syntactic Ambiguity FOPC provides many ways to represent the same thing. E.g., “Ball-5 is red.” –HasColor(Ball-5, Red) Ball-5 and Red are objects related by HasColor. –Red(Ball-5) Red is a unary predicate applied to the Ball-5 object. –HasProperty(Ball-5, Color, Red) Ball-5, Color, and Red are objects related by HasProperty. –ColorOf(Ball-5) = Red Ball-5 and Red are objects, and ColorOf() is a function. –HasColor(Ball-5(), Red()) Ball-5() and Red() are functions of zero arguments that both return an object, which objects are related by HasColor. –… This can GREATLY confuse a pattern-matching reasoner. –Especially if multiple people collaborate to build the KB, and they all have different representational conventions.

Summary First-order logic: –Much more expressive than propositional logic –Allows objects and relations as semantic primitives –Universal and existential quantifiers –syntax: constants, functions, predicates, equality, quantifiers Knowledge engineering using FOL –Capturing domain knowledge in logical form Inference and reasoning in FOL –Next lecture Required Reading: –All of Chapter 8 –Next lecture: Chapter 9