Quantum Measurements: some technical background “Measurement postulate” “Projection postulate” The two aspects of measurement Density matrices, environments,

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Quantum One: Lecture 1a Entitled So what is quantum mechanics, anyway?
Advertisements

Quantum One: Lecture 6. The Initial Value Problem for Free Particles, and the Emergence of Fourier Transforms.
Quantum measurements and quantum erasers
What really happens upon quantum measurement?[n eeds revision] References are more fully listed in my Phys Rev A paperPhys Rev A paper Art Hobson Prof.
Copyright © 2007 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley Chapter 18 Sampling Distribution Models.
Chapter 15: Duality of Matter Did you read chapter 15 before coming to class? A.Yes B.No.
Quantum Information Stephen M. Barnett University of Strathclyde The Wolfson Foundation.
Integrals over Operators
1 quantum teleportation David Riethmiller 28 May 2007.
Quantum One: Lecture 3. Implications of Schrödinger's Wave Mechanics for Conservative Systems.
Quantum mechanics for Advaitins
Wavefunction Quantum mechanics acknowledges the wave-particle duality of matter by supposing that, rather than traveling along a definite path, a particle.
DENSITY MATRICES, traces, Operators and Measurements
Introduction to Quantum Information Processing Lecture 4 Michele Mosca.
Advanced Computer Architecture Lab University of Michigan Quantum Noise and Distance Patrick Cassleman More Quantum Noise and Distance Measures for Quantum.
Quantum Mechanics from Classical Statistics. what is an atom ? quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum field theory.
Chapter 3 Formalism. Hilbert Space Two kinds of mathematical constructs - wavefunctions (representing the system) - operators (representing observables)
4. The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics 4A. Revisiting Representations
Introduction to Quantum Theory of Angular Momentum
Quantum theory and Consciousness This is an interactive discussion. Please feel free to interrupt at any time with your questions and comments.
Philosophical Interpretations of
Alice and Bob’s Excellent Adventure
Quantum Information, Communication and Computing Jan Kříž Department of physics, University of Hradec Králové Doppler Institute for mathematical physics.
In 1887,when Photoelectric Effect was first introduced by Heinrich Hertz, the experiment was not able to be explained using classical principles.
The Copenhagen interpretation Born, Heisenberg, Schrödinger, Bohr ( ) Even though the Copenhagen interpretation is supposed to be the “orthodox”
Too Many to Count.
Lecture 2. Postulates in Quantum Mechanics
It’s all done with Mirrors Many of the predictions of quantum mechanics are verified with ordinary matter particles (like electrons), but these experiments.
Quantum entanglement and Quantum state Tomography Zoltán Scherübl Nanophysics Seminar – Lecture BUTE.
MODULE 1 In classical mechanics we define a STATE as “The specification of the position and velocity of all the particles present, at some time, and the.
The Quantum Theory of Atoms and Molecules The Schrödinger equation and how to use wavefunctions Dr Grant Ritchie.
Quantum Two 1. 2 Evolution of Many Particle Systems 3.
Gerard ’t Hooft, quant-ph/ Erice, September 6, 2006 Utrecht University 1.
Physics 2170 – Spring Some interesting aspects of quantum mechanics The last homework is due at 12:50pm.
Phase space, decoherence and the Wigner function for finite dimensional systems. James Yearsley Superviser: Prof. JJ Halliwell. See: Gibbons et. al. quant-ph/
Quantum Mechanical Cross Sections In a practical scattering experiment the observables we have on hand are momenta, spins, masses, etc.. We do not directly.
Quantum Theory of What? What does quantum theory describe?
Solvable Model for the Quantum Measurement Process Armen E. Allahverdyan Roger Balian Theo M. Nieuwenhuizen Academia Sinica Taipei, June 26, 2004.
1 Introduction to Quantum Information Processing CS 467 / CS 667 Phys 467 / Phys 767 C&O 481 / C&O 681 Richard Cleve DC 3524 Course.
The EPR Paradox, Bell’s inequalities, and its significance By: Miles H. Taylor.
The Quantum Mechanical Model of the Atom. Niels Bohr In 1913 Bohr used what had recently been discovered about energy to propose his planetary model of.
Lecture 10 Reprise and generalized forces The Lagrangian Holonomic constraints Generalized coordinates Nonholonomic constraints Euler-Lagrange equations.
Basic Concepts Absolute Size The Superposition Principle Copyright – Michael D. Fayer, 2007 Size Classical MechanicsQuantum Mechanics RelativeAbsolute.
Density matrix and its application. Density matrix An alternative of state-vector (ket) representation for a certain set of state-vectors appearing with.
Chapter 3 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics. Questions QM answers 1) How is the state of a system described mathematically? (In CM – via generalized coordinates.
Phy107 Fall From Last Time… Today Superposition of wave functions Indistinguishability Electron spin: a new quantum effect The Hydrogen atom and.
1 HEINSENBERG’S UNCERTAINTY PRINCIPLE “It is impossible to determine both position and momentum of a particle simultaneously and accurately. The product.
SCHLC- 1 S CHRÖDINGER ’ S C AT AND H ER L ABORATORY C OUSINS A.J. Leggett Dept. of Physics, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign 1 st Erwin Schrödinger.
Week VIII Quantum Mechanics
Quantum One.
The Quantum Theory of Atoms and Molecules
Postulates of Quantum Mechanics
Quantum theory and Consciousness

Quantum mechanics from classical statistics
Quantum One.
4. The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics 4A. Revisiting Representations
Quantum One. Quantum One So what is quantum mechanics, anyway?
Quantum One.
Quantum One.
Quantum One.
Double Slit Experiment
Account given by quantum mechanics: Each possible process is represented by a probability amplitude A which can be positive or negative Total amplitude.
Heisenberg Uncertainty
Schrödinger Equation Outline Wave Equations from ω-k Relations
MESO/MACROSCOPIC TESTS OF QM: MOTIVATION
Time and Quantum from Correlations
Does the Everyday World Really Obey Quantum Mechanics?
Computational approaches for quantum many-body systems
Quantum One.
Presentation transcript:

Quantum Measurements: some technical background “Measurement postulate” “Projection postulate” The two aspects of measurement Density matrices, environments, et cetera von Neumann measurements (entanglement and decoherence) Slides, and some other useful links, to be posted: 14 Oct 2003 (AKA: the boring lecture)

The measurement postulate

...measurement outcomes... “Collapse of the wavefunction” Future measurements of A will of course agree with this a i MeasurementState preparation

What are the effects of measurement? Suppose we have two pawns, one black and one white, and I put one in each hand – we can write this state as something like = + Obviously, if I open my left hand and measure the colour of its pawn, I find either black or white, not both – from that point on, I describe the left pawn as one colour eigenstate, or. Is the other pawn still in a state of uncertain colour? No – obviously, its state has also been “affected” by this measurement.

More refined version: the “projection postulate” When a i is found, the state Of course, this is not normalized, so the final state is actually Finding the left pawn to be black leaves the system in a state where the right pawn is known to be white (unsurprisingly).

Two effects of measurement 1.One thing happens, as opposed to all other possibilities 2.Interference between the different possibilities becomes impossible. 100% 50% What’s the state of the particles before the final beam-splitter? If no bomb was present, half the particles are in path A and half are in path B. If the bomb “measures” which path each is in... then still, half are in path A and half are in path B. The measurement didn’t change the probabilistic description of the state... but without the bomb, interference caused all particles to interfere at the final beam splitter and go left; with the bomb, there is no such interference. Measurement destroyed phase information, but left the probabilities unchanged. |A  + e i  |B   |A  “OR” |B . A B det. 1 det. 2

How does the bomb cause the other detector to fire? The probability is given by the absolute square of this inner product, which is 1/4 + 1/4 = 1/2 (because the orthogonality of "peace" and "BOOM" cause the cross-terms to vanish).

Sneaky fact... No one knows why one thing happens instead of many simultaneous things... in fact, no one knows whether this is true (cf. “relative-state”, “many-worlds”, “many-minds” interpretations). We can try (a) to understand what measurements do to coherence and/or(b) to search for a real “collapse” process, supplementary to quantum mechanics as we know it. No “collapse” process has ever been observed – i.e., no case where we would make the wrong predictions if we didn’t assume collapse. Yet to make sense of probabilities, one typically assumes that by the time you measure something, it’s one thing or another. (But how do you know that when I measured it, I wasn’t still in a probabilistic state? “Wigner’s friend.”)

We need a formalism for this... Note that in that interferometer, |A   |det. 1  and |det. 2  ; |B   |det. 1  and |det. 2  ; but |A  + |B   |det. 2  only (because of interference). The state "|A  OR |B  " might be |A  (and get to det. 1 half the time)... or it might be |B  (and get to det. 1 half the time). It's not |A  + |B , |A  – |B , etc. Any QM wave function you write down which is half A and half B will exhibit some interference; no wave function can describe the state after such a measurement. Technical example: there is no spin-1/2 state with = = 0. "Pure states"individual QM wave functions "Mixed states"probabilistic mixtures of QM states. (e.g., results of measurements) "Density Matrices"

Intro to density matrices...

Interpretation of matrix elements Diagonal elements = probabilities Off-diagonal elements = "coherences" (provide info. about relative phase)

Connection to observables

And what about mixed states? The essential property of a statistical mixture is that all expectation values are just the weighted averages of those for the individual pure states. Our expression for expectation values is linear in the density matrix – i.e., we can keep using that expression with mixed states, if we define the mixed-state density matrix itself as a weighted average.

Density matrices for mixed states Note: probabilities still 50/50, but no coherence.

What happens if you don't look at part of your system? When you calculate expectation values, you trace over the system. If your operators depend only on a subsystem, then it makes no difference whether you trace over other systems before or after:

Decoherence arises from throwing away information Taking this trace over the environment retains only terms diagonal in the environment variables – i.e., no cross-terms (coherences) remain if they refer to different states of the environment. (If there is any way – even in principle – to tell which of two paths was followed, then no interference may occur.)  s when env is   s when env is     

... There is still coherence between  and , but if the environment is not part of your interferometer, you may as well consider it to have "collapsed" to  or . This means there is no effective coherence if you look only at the system. coherence lost

Decoherence: the party line When a particle interacts with a measurement device, the two subsystems become entangled (no separable description). Coherence is still present, but only in the entire system; if there is enough information in the measurement device to tell which path your subsystem followed, then it is impossible to observe interference without looking at both parts of the system. The effective density matrix of your system (traced over states of the measuring apparatus) is that of a mixed state. Coherence is never truly lost, as unitary evolution preserves the purity of states. In principle, this measurement interaction is reversible. In practice, once the system interacts with the "environment", i.e., anything with too many degrees of freedom for us to handle, we cannot reverse it. Just as in classical statistical mechanics, it is the approximation of an open system which leads to effective irreversibility, and loss of information (increase of entropy). Loss of Information = Loss of Coherence

So, how does a system become "entangled" with a measuring device? First, recall: Bohr – we must treat measurement classically Wigner – why must we? von Neumann:there are two processes in QM: Unitary and Reduction. He shows how all the effects of measurement we've described so far may be explained without any reduction, or macroscopic devices. [Of course, this gets us a diagonal density matrix – classical probabilities without coherence – but still can't tell us how those probabilities turn into one occurrence or another.] To measure some observable A, let a "meter" interact with it, so the bigger A is, the more the pointer on the meter moves. P is the generator of translations, so this just means we allow the system and meter to interact according to H int  A P.

An aside (more intuitive?) Suppose instead of looking at the position of our pointer, we used its velocity to take a reading. In other words, let the particle exert a force on the pointer, and have the force be proportional to A; then the pointer's final velocity will be proportional to A too. F = g A U(x) = g A X H int = g A X This works with any pair of conjugate variables. In the standard case, H int = g A P x, we can see The pointer position evolves at a rate proportional to.

A von Neumann measurement H int =gAp x System-pointer coupling Initial State of Pointer x A Initial State of System x A Final state of both (entangled)

Back-Action In other words, the measurement does not simply cause the pointer position to evolve, while leaving the system alone. The interaction entangles the two, and as we have seen, this entanglement is the source of decoherence. It is often also described as "back-action" of the measuring device on the measured system. Unless P x, the momentum of the pointer, is perfectly well-defined, then the interaction Hamiltonian H int = g A P x looks like an uncertain (noisy) potential for the particle. A high-resolution measurement needs a well-defined pointer position X. This implies (by Heisenberg) that Px is not well-defined. The more accurate the measurement, the greater the back-action. Measuring A perturbs the variable conjugate to A "randomly" (unless, that is, you pay attention to entanglement).

Summary We have no idea whether or not "collapse" really occurs. Any time two systems interact and we discard information about one of them, this can be thought of as a measurement, whether or not either is macroscopic, & whether or not there is collapse. The von Neumann interaction shows how the two systems become entangled, and how this may look like random noise from the point of view of the subsystem. The "reduced density matrix" of an entangled subsystem appears mixed, because the discarded parts of the system carry away information. This is the origin of decoherence of the measured subsystem.