WEEK 2 Justice as Fairness. A Theory of Justice (1971) Political Liberalism (1993)

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Justice & Economic Distribution (2)
Advertisements

Rawlsian Contract Approach Attempts to reconcile utilitarianism and intuitionism. Attempts to reconcile utilitarianism and intuitionism. Theory of distributive.
John Rawls A Theory of Justice.
Roderick T. Long Auburn Dept. of Philosophy
Justice as Fairness by John Rawls.
2 H i g h e r E d u c a t i o n © Oxford University Press, All rights reserved. Chapter 3: Political theory: Social justice and the state Barr: Economics.
Lecture 6 John Rawls. Justifying government Question: How can the power of government be justified?
"... reason accepts no authority above itself and is necessarily subversive." - Allan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (1987), p. 258.
Justice as Fairness/Justice as Holdings: Rawls/Nozick
PHIL 104 (STOLZE) Notes on Heather Widdows, Global Ethics: An Introduction, chapter 4.
Chapter Three: Justice and Economic Distribution
Justice as Fairness by John Rawls.
Ethics and Morality Theory Part 2 11 September 2006.
Ethics and ethical systems 12 January
COMP 381. Agenda  TA: Caitlyn Losee  Books and movies nominations  Team presentation signup Beginning of class End of class  Rawls and Moors.
Egalitarians View Egalitarians hold that there are no relevant differences among people that can justify unequal treatment. According to the egalitarian,
RAWLS 1 JUSTICE IS FAIRNESS. John Rawls Teachers: H. L. A. Hart Isaiah Berlin Students: Thomas Nagel Martha Nussbaum Onara O’Neill.
John Rawls, Who? GETTING TO THE ASSIGNED ARTICLE: A THEORY OF JUSTICE (1971) HOW WERE PEOPLE THINKG ABOUT ETHICS AND JUSTICE? – Utilitarian.
THE PRINCIPLE OF UTILITY: Bentham
Ethical Principle of Justice principle of justice –involves giving to all persons their "rights" or "desserts" –the distribution of various resources in.
RAWLS 2 CRITIQUES OF RAWLS.
Deontological tradition Contractualism of John Rawls Discourse ethics.
A Theory of Justice. “What is justice?” The Code of Hammurabi (Babylon, 18 th c. BCE) Judaism, Christianity, Islam: scales (balance, regulation, harmony),
Rawls John Rawls ( ): A Theory of Justice (Harvard UP, 1971) -and other books, notably Political Liberalism (1990) -and Justice as Fairness Restated.
January 20, Liberalism 2. Social Contract Theory 3. Utilitarianism and Intuitionism 4. Justice as Fairness – general conception 5. Principles.
Equality and Inequality: Perspectives from Political Theory
Ethics Theory and Business Practice
“To be able under all circumstances to practise five things constitutes perfect virtue; these five things are gravity, generosity of soul, sincerity, earnestness.
Liberalism Michael Doyle Lecture 3 Kaisa Ellandi.
Ethical Theories Presentation LP 5 Melissa Sweet, Tara Guelig, Katherine Norton April 9 th,2009.
Business Ethics Lecture Rights and Duties 1.
Distributive Justice II: John Rawls Ethics Dr. Jason M. Chang.
Moral Issues In Policing. Moral Issues in Policing Should police be held to the same or higher standards than other members of society? – Courage? – Fairness?
Rawls on justice Michael Lacewing co.uk.
Contractualism and justice (1) Introduction to Rawls’s theory.
Justice Paradox of Justice Small volcanic island has two villages, “South Town” (Pop 300) and “North Village” (Pop 500). Threat of devastating volcanic.
Ideas about Justice Three big themes Virtue Ethics Utilitarianism
January 20, Liberalism 2. Social Contract Theory 3. Utilitarianism and Intuitionism 4. Justice as Fairness – general conception 5. Principles.
Distributive Justice John Rawls. Which is better? MusicCheese 65.
Justice as Fairness John Rawls PHL 110: ETHICS North Central College.
Arguments against the Market  Engels complains that free market is completely wasteful.  This is also a utilitarian argument. It leads crisis after crisis.
Justice and Economic Distribution
Three Modern Approaches. Introduction Rawls, Nozick, and MacIntyre Rawls, Nozick, and MacIntyre Have significant new approaches Have significant new approaches.
Rawls & Nozick Liberalism & Libertarianism Warwick Debating Society Training, 11/05/2011.
Justice as Fairness by John Rawls. Rawls looks at justice. Kant’s ethics and Utilitarianism are about right and wrong actions. For example: Is it ethical.
Justice/Fairness Approach Learning Plan #5 Sara Deibert, Sara Roxbury, Allie Forsythe, Robert Phillips March 31,2008.
John Rawls Theory of Justice. John Rawls John Rawls (February 21, 1921 – November 24, 2002) was an American philosopher and a figure in moral and political.
Rationality in Decision Making In Law Nisigandha Bhuyan, IIMC.
Phil 2265: Social / Political Philosophy Introducing Rawls.
The System of Social Justice Principles in the Contemporary Law Tradition of the West dr. Jolanta Bieliauskaitė Brno, 2015.
DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS (CH. 2.0) © Wanda Teays. All rights reserved.
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
Deontological Approaches Consequences of decisions are not always the most important elements as suggested by the consequentialist approach. The way you.
Kantian Ethics Good actions have intrinsic value; actions are good if and only if they follow from a moral law that can be universalized.
Rawls’ Justice Srijit Mishra IGIDR, HDP, Lectures 5, 6 and 7 13, 18 and 20 January 2012.
Social Ethics continued Immanuel Kant John Rawls.
Philosophy 219 Rawls, A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism.
Ethics Topic 3.
Political theory and law
PHIL 104 (STOLZE) Notes on Heather Widdows, Global Ethics: An Introduction, chapter 4.
Deontological tradition
History of Philosophy.
Political theory and law
Rawl’s Veil of Ignorance
Rawls, A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism
Rawls’ Theory of Justice
Theories of justice.
Chapter 5 Ethical Decision Making
Rawls, A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism
Professional Ethics (GEN301/PHI200) UNIT 3: JUSTICE AND ECONOMIC DISTRIBUTION Handout #3 CLO#3 Evaluate the relation between justice, ethics and economic.
Presentation transcript:

WEEK 2 Justice as Fairness

A Theory of Justice (1971) Political Liberalism (1993)

Justice as fairness is primarily concerned with ‘the way in which major social institutions distribute fundamental rights and duties and determine the division of advantages from social cooperation’. As such, justice as fairness is a theory designed to apply to the ‘basic structure’ – the political, social and economic institutions of society. It provides a normative ideal by which we are to judge the political constitution of society and the principal economic and social arrangements.

The just society, according to justice as fairness, is one governed by the two principles of justice. These principles are: Each person has the same indefensible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties, which scheme is compatible with the same scheme of liberties for all (equal basic liberties principle). Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: 1. they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity (fair equality of opportunity principle) 2. second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least- advantaged members of society (difference principle).

They are listed in order of priority: The equal basic liberties principle must be satisfied before the second principle is invoked and the fair equality of opportunity principle must be satisfied before the difference principle can be invoked.

The main components of Rawls’s liberal theory and some of the objections raised against it. In constructing his theory of ‘justice as fairness’ Rawls appeals to the idea of the social contract (inspired by contractarians like John Locke, Jean- Jacques Rousseau and Immanuel Kant) The main rival of the contractarian tradition is utilitarianism and Rawls offers his theory as an alternative to utilitarianism, which had been the dominant tradition prior to the publication of A Theory of Justice.

Utilitarians have put forth diverse accounts of what qualifies as ‘human happiness’, or ‘utility’, but they share the belief that the best outcome is the one that maximizes overall happiness or utility. Institutions and acts are right if, of the available alternatives, they produce the most good: teleological theory. Deontological theories can be defined as a theory ‘that either does not specify the good independently from the right, or does not interpret the right as maximising the good’ Rawls wants to defend a theory that is deontological in this second sense, that is, it gives a priority to the right over the good.

By asserting a priority of the right over the good Rawls seeks to avoid the injustices that may be made in the name of maximizing utility. He does invoke certain fundamental ideas he believes are embedded in the public political culture of a democratic society. These include: The idea of society as a fair system of social cooperation over time from one generation to the next. The idea of citizens as free and equal persons. As such, they are taken to possess two moral powers: the capacity for a sense of justice (the capacity to understand, to apply, and to act from (and not merely in accordance with) the principles of political justice that specify the fair terms of social cooperation and; persons have a capacity for a conception of the good (the capacity to have, revise, and rationally to pursue a conception of the good).

These fundamental ideas are, claims Rawls, viewed as being familiar from the public political culture of a democratic society. What the specific requirements of fair terms of cooperation actually are?

The original position It corresponds to the state of nature in traditional contract theories. Parties are placed in the original position and given two tasks: to choose the principles that are to govern the basic structure of society and to choose the principles that are to apply to individuals. They are also given a limited list of principles from which to choose. This list includes Rawls’s two principles of justice and their priority rules, utilitarianism and perfectionism

Rawls describes the original position as the appropriate initial status quo. It is one in which all people are treated as equals. In order to ensure that the choice of principles of justice is impartial and fair Rawls invokes the following two constraints: 1- The principles must fulfil what he calls the formal constraints of the right. 2- They must be chosen behind a veil of ignorance.

From behind the veil of ignorance the parties are denied certain information: Their place in society (for example, class or social status). Their race or gender. Their fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities (for example, intelligence, strength, etc.). Their conception of the good. The particular circumstances of their society (for example, its economic or political situation). The generation they belong to.

Having clarified the task facing the parties in the original position and the constraints placed on their choice by the formal constraints of the right and the veil of ignorance, Rawls turns to the issue of the rationality of the parties. In order to ensure that individuals have the opportunity to pursue their conception of the good in the real world, once the veil is lifted, the parties in the original position seek to secure the largest share they can of what Rawls calls the social primary goods. These goods are rights and liberties, powers and opportunities, income and wealth and self-respect

formal equality of opportunity. Formal equality of opportunity entails that all have at least the same legal right of access to all advantaged social positions: a society of equal liberty and a free market economy (natural liberty) Rawls argues that such a society will bring about unjust distributive outcomes Formal equality of opportunity does not capture the intuitive appeal of the ideal of equal opportunity. The elimination of arbitrary barriers (policies of racial or gender discrimination) to advancement is a necessary but not sufficient measure for securing equal opportunity for all. The system of natural liberty permits morally arbitrary factors to greatly influence one’s distributive share.

Fair equality of opportunity seeks to eliminate, or at least minimize as much as possible, the influence social contingencies (such as social class) have on people’s opportunities. Liberal equality is more appealing than the system of natural liberty. It does a better of job of cohering to the intuitions that underlie our commitment to the ideal of equal opportunity.

The third interpretation is democratic equality. It is arrived at by ‘combining the principle of fair equality of opportunity with the difference principle’. Rawls’s analysis of equal opportunity has, so far, pushed us in the direction of objecting to any inequalities in social primary goods because such inequalities will reflect morally arbitrary factors. Formal equality of opportunity and liberal equality fail to provide us with compelling reasons why all citizens, especially the least advantaged should accept the institutional arrangements such societies implement (equality of outcomes).

The difference principle permits inequalities provided such inequalities maximize the prospects of the least advantaged.