Inglese 14-15 Lezione 4, 23/2/15.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
The value of certainty. Foundationalists suppose that true beliefs held with certainty (indubitable) together with logical and linguistic analysis offer.
Advertisements

Anselm On the Existence of God. “Nor do I seek to understand so that I can believe, but rather I believe so that I can understand. For I believe this.
The ontological argument. I had the persuasion that there was absolutely nothing in the world, that there was no sky and no earth, neither minds nor.
Descartes God.
Meditations on First Philosophy
Berkeley’s idealism (brief)
Descartes on Certainty (and Doubt)
The Rationalists: Descartes Certainty: Self and God
Meditation One What is the objective of the Meditations? Hint: look at second sentence of Med. I.
Philosophy of Mind Week 3: Objections to Dualism Logical Behaviorism
BERKELEY’S CASE FOR IDEALISM (Part 2 of 2)
Finding our way back  The initial result of Descartes’ use of hyperbolic doubt is the recognition that at least one thing cannot be doubted, at least.
Philosophy of Mind Week 2: Descartes and Dualism
Descartes Meditations The Wax Example. The Extension of the Cogito For even if, as I have supposed, none of the objects of imagination are real, the power.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
BERKELEY’S CASE FOR IDEALISM (Part 1 of 2) Text source: A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, sectns. 1-21,
Descartes. Descartes - b.1596 d.1650 ❑ Not a skeptic – “there really is a world, that men have bodies, and the like (things which no one of sound mind.
Descartes’ Meditations
Critical Thinking Dialogue Education 2009 THIS CD HAS BEEN PRODUCED FOR TEACHERS TO USE IN THE CLASSROOM. IT IS A CONDITION OF THE USE OF THIS CD THAT.
René Descartes ( AD) Meditations on First Philosophy (1641) (Text, pp )
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 12 Minds and bodies #1 (Descartes) By David Kelsey.
Berkeley’s idealism (long) Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Descartes' Evil Demon Hypothesis:
© Michael Lacewing Substance and Property Dualism Michael Lacewing
The Turn to the Science The problem with substance dualism is that, given what we know about how the world works, it is hard to take it seriously as a.
Need worksheet from yellow folder – arg from perceptual variation.
Argument From Dreaming. 1 This is the second sceptical argument – the second wave of doubt, after the argument from illusion – senses cannot be trusted.
An Outline of Descartes's Meditations on First Philosophy
Substance and Property Dualism Quick task: Fill in the gaps activity Quick task: Fill in the gaps activity ?v=sT41wRA67PA.
Testi Fil. in Inglese Lezione 8, (1a ora)
PHIL 200B ● Today – Locke's Essay concerning human understanding ● Method ( ) ● Locke's Empiricism – Against innate ideas/principles. – Ideas of.
The Origin of Knowledge
1. I exist, because I think. 2. I am a thinking thing 3
Lecture 8 Time: McTaggart’s argument
Michael Lacewing Direct realism Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Direct Realism Criticisms
Ethics: Theory and Practice
Meditation Six Of God: That He Exists.
Hume’s Fork A priori/ A posteriori Empiricism/ Rationalism
Substance and Property Dualism
Intuition and deduction thesis (rationalism)
Hume’s Fork A priori/ A posteriori Empiricism/ Rationalism
PHILOSOPHY OF HUMAN PERSON
Skepticism.
Sensible Qualities Things like heat ARE qualities that are subjective. These are secondary qualities. Everyone agrees that secondary qualities DO have.
Indirect realism Learning objectives: to understand the objection to indirect realism that it leads to scepticism about the nature of the external world.
Philosophy and History of Mathematics
Concept Innatism.
1st wave: Illusion Descartes begins his method of doubt by considering that in the past he has been deceived by his senses: Things in the distance looked.
Michael Lacewing Indirect realism Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Indirect Realism Understand the argument put forward by the indirect realist. Explain how a indirect realist would respond to perceptual problems. ‘Does.
The secondary quality argument for indirect realism
Michael Lacewing Berkeley’s idealism Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Descartes’ proof of the external world
Descartes, Meditations 1 and 2
Major Periods of Western Philosophy
Describing Mental States
Remember these terms? Analytic/ synthetic A priori/ a posteriori
Bullet Point on Whiteboards!
On your whiteboard: What is empiricism? Arguments/evidence for it?
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
Recap So Far: Direct Realism
Do we directly perceive objects? (25 marks)
Problems with IDR Before the holidays we discussed two problems with the indirect realist view. If we can’t perceive the external world directly (because.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 Berkeley
Inglese Lezioni 23-24, 20 Aprile 2015.
Critical Thinking Dialogue Education Update 4
Meditation 2: The Nature of the Mind, which is Better Known than the Body Descartes Meditation I.
First Meditation – paragraph 1
Epistemology “Episteme” = knowledge “Logos” = words / study of
Presentation transcript:

Inglese 14-15 Lezione 4, 23/2/15

To return to the table. It is evident from what we have found, that there is no colour which pre-eminently appears to be the colour of the table, or even of any one particular part of the table , it appears to be of different colours from different points of view, and there is no reason for regarding some of these as more really its colour than others.

The same thing applies to the texture. With the naked eye one can see the grain, but otherwise the table looks smooth and even. If we looked at it through a microscope, we should see roughnesses and hills and valleys, and all sorts of differences that are imperceptible to the naked eye. Which of these is the 'real' table?

The shape of the table is no better. We are all in the habit of judging as to the 'real' shapes of things, and we do this so unreflectingly that we come to think we actually see the real shapes. But, in fact, as we all have to learn if we try to draw, a given thing looks different in shape from every different point of view.

Similar difficulties arise when we consider the sense of touch. It is true that the table always gives us a sensation of hardness, and we feel that it resists pressure. But the sensation we obtain depends upon how hard we press the table and also upon what part of the body we press with;

Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing. The real table, if there is one, is not immediately known to us at all, but must be an inference from what is immediately known. Hence, two very difficult questions at once arise; namely, (1) Is there a real table at all? (2) If so, what sort of object can it be?

Let us give the name of 'sense-data' to the things that are immediately known in sensation: such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on.

The real table, if it exists, we will call a 'physical object'. Thus we have to consider the relation of sense-data to physical objects. The collection of all physical objects is called 'matter'. Thus our two questions may be re-stated as follows: (1) Is there any such thing as matter? (2) If so, what is its nature?

Inglese, Lez. 5, 23-2-15, ore 14

Dalla fine del cap. I Thus our familiar table, which has roused but the slightest thoughts in us hitherto, has become a problem full of surprising possibilities. The one thing we know about it is that it is not what it seems. Beyond this modest result, so far, we have the most complete liberty of conjecture. Leibniz tells us it is a community of souls: Berkeley tells us it is an idea in the mind of God; sober science, scarcely less wonderful, tells us it is a vast collection of electric charges in violent motion. Among these surprising possibilities, doubt suggests that perhaps there is no table at all. ...

Philosophy, if it cannot answer so many questions as we could wish, has at least the power of asking questions which increase the interest of the world, and show the strangeness and wonder lying just below the surface even in the commonest things of daily life.

Dal cap. II In this chapter we have to ask ourselves whether, in any sense at all, there is such a thing as matter. Is there a table which has a certain intrinsic nature, and continues to exist when I am not looking, or is the table merely a product of my imagination, a dream-table in a very prolonged dream?

... it may be that the whole outer world is nothing but a dream, and that we alone exist. This is an uncomfortable possibility; but although it cannot be strictly proved to be false, there is not the slightest reason to suppose that it is true. In this chapter we have to see why this is the case.

Sul cogito But some care is needed in using Descartes' argument. 'I think, therefore I am' says rather more than is strictly certain. It might seem as though we were quite sure of being the same person to-day as we were yesterday, and this is no doubt true in some sense. But the real Self is as hard to arrive at as the real table, and does not seem to have that absolute, convincing certainty that belongs to particular experiences. When I look at my table and see a certain brown colour, what is quite certain at once is not 'I am seeing a brown colour', but rather, 'a brown colour is being seen'. This of course involves something (or somebody) which (or who) sees the brown colour;

Inglese Lezioni 6-7, 25-2-15

but it does not of itself involve that more or less permanent person whom we call 'I'. So far as immediate certainty goes, it might be that the something which sees the brown colour is quite momentary, and not the same as the something which has some different experience the next moment.

Thus it is our particular thoughts and feelings that have primitive certainty. And this applies to dreams and hallucinations as well as to normal perceptions: when we dream or see a ghost, we certainly do have the sensations we think we have, but for various reasons it is held that no physical object corresponds to these sensations.

One great reason why it is felt that we must secure a physical object in addition to the sense-data, is that we want the same object for different people. When ten people are sitting round a dinner-table, it seems preposterous to maintain that they are not seeing the same tablecloth, the same knives and forks and spoons and glasses. But the sense-data are private to each separate person; what is immediately present to the sight of one is not immediately present to the sight of another: they all see things from slightly different points of view, and therefore see them slightly differently.

Thus, if there are to be public neutral objects, which can be in some sense known to many different people, there must be something over and above the private and particular sense-data which appear to various people. What reason, then, have we for believing that there are such public neutral objects?

In one sense it must be admitted that we can never prove the existence of things other than ourselves and our experiences. ... There is no logical impossibility in the supposition that the whole of life is a dream, in which we ourselves create all the objects that come before us.

But although this is not logically impossible, there is no reason whatever to suppose that it is true; and it is, in fact, a less simple hypothesis, viewed as a means of accounting for the facts of our own life, than the common-sense hypothesis that there really are objects independent of us, whose action on us causes our sensations.

The way in which simplicity comes in from supposing that there really are physical objects is easily seen. If the cat appears at one moment in one part of the room, and at another in another part, it is natural to suppose that it has moved from the one to the other, passing over a series of intermediate positions. But if it is merely a set of sense-data, it cannot have ever been in any place where I did not see it; thus we shall have to suppose that it did not exist at all while I was not looking, but suddenly sprang into being in a new place. If the cat exists whether I see it or not, we can understand from our own experience how it gets hungry between one meal and the next; but if it does not exist when I am not seeing it, it seems odd that appetite should grow during non-existence as fast as during existence.