Functional Verification III

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Functional Verification III Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida Software Testing and Verification Lecture Notes 23.
Advertisements

Axiomatic Verification I Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida Software Testing and Verification Lecture 17.
So far we have learned about:
4/17/2017 Section 3.6 Program Correctness ch3.6.
Copyright © 2007 Pearson Education, Inc. Slide 8-1.
Introduction to Proofs
Reading and Writing Mathematical Proofs
Chapter 3 (Part 3): Mathematical Reasoning, Induction & Recursion  Recursive Algorithms (3.5)  Program Correctness (3.6)
Exam 2 Help Session Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida Software Testing and Verification.
Proofs of Correctness: An Introduction to Axiomatic Verification Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida CEN 5035 Software Engineering.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 4 ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF.
Application: Correctness of Algorithms Lecture 22 Section 4.5 Fri, Mar 3, 2006.
Recursive Algorithms &
Application: Correctness of Algorithms Lecture 22 Section 4.5 Fri, Feb 18, 2005.
Direct Proof and Counterexample I Lecture 11 Section 3.1 Fri, Jan 28, 2005.
Functional Verification I Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida Software Testing and Verification Lecture Notes 21.
White-Box Testing Techniques I Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida Software Testing and Verification Lecture 7.
Advanced Algorithms Analysis and Design By Dr. Nazir Ahmad Zafar Dr Nazir A. Zafar Advanced Algorithms Analysis and Design.
Proof And Strategies Chapter 2. Lecturer: Amani Mahajoub Omer Department of Computer Science and Software Engineering Discrete Structures Definition Discrete.
Axiomatic Verification II Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida Software Testing and Verification Lecture Notes 18.
The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
Indirect Argument: Contradiction and Contraposition
Chapter 4 (Part 3): Mathematical Reasoning, Induction & Recursion
Advanced Algorithms Analysis and Design
Reasoning About Code.
Theory of Computation Lecture 14: A Universal Program V
White-Box Testing Techniques II
Functional Verification IV: Revisiting Loop Invariants
Indirect Argument: Contradiction and Contraposition
Predicate Transforms II
Functional Verification IV: Revisiting Loop Invariants
Functional Verification III
Proving Properties of Recursive List Functions
White-Box Testing Techniques III
Formal Program Specification
Predicate Transforms I
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
Functional Verification I
Exercise Solutions: Functional Verification
Formal Program Specification
Exercise Solutions: Functional Verification
Axiomatic Verification II
White-Box Testing Techniques III
CSE 311: Foundations of Computing
CS 220: Discrete Structures and their Applications
Functional Verification I
White-Box Testing Techniques I
Axiomatic Verification II
Axiomatic Verification I
Proofs of Correctness: An Introduction to Axiomatic Verification
Functional Verification II
Functional Verification IV: Revisiting Loop Invariants
Axiomatic Verification I
Predicate Transforms I
Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida
Functional Verification III
Application: Algorithms
Application: Algorithms
Predicate Transforms II
Functional Verification III
Advanced Analysis of Algorithms
Chapter 11: Further Topics in Algebra
Problem Set 7: Functional Verification
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Functional Verification IV: Revisiting Loop Invariants
Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Formal Program Specification
Program Correctness an introduction.
Presentation transcript:

Functional Verification III Software Testing and Verification Lecture Notes 23 Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida

Previously… Correctness conditions and working correctness questions: sequencing decision statements

Today’s Topics Iteration Recursion Lemma (IRL) Termination predicate: term(f,P) Correctness conditions for while_do statement Sufficient correctness conditions Correctness conditions for repeat_until statement Subgoal Induction

Iteration Recursion Lemma (IRL) The IRL reduces the verification of programs with loops to a question of termination and the verification of loop-free programs by converting iteration to recursion. For while loops, the Lemma states: f = [while p do g] = [if p then g;f end_if] (note recursion)

Iteration Recursion Lemma (cont’d) F p T F F F p p p g f = = = = T T T g g g;f F p T f g

Iteration Recursion Lemma (cont’d) Rather than verify directly that f is the program function of K = while p do g which can be very difficult, it is sufficient to prove that 1. K terminates for all X  D(f), and that 2. f is the program function of Q = if p then g;f end_if because [K] = [Q].

An important implication of the IRL Suppose for “input” X0 the while loop term- inates after n iterations with “output” Xn. Furthermore, let X1, X2, ..., Xn-1 be the in- termediate states generated by the loop. Then  0≤i<n, we know: p(Xi), Xi+1=g(Xi), and ¬p(Xn).

An important implication of the IRL (cont’d) As f = [while p do g] = [if p then g;f end_if], it follows that f(X0) = f(X1) = ... = f(Xn) = Xn More generally, after each iteration of the loop, the function value of the current state, X, must be the same as the function value of the initial state, X0. That is: f(X) = f(X0) We will revisit this observation in connection with Mill’s Invariant Status Theorem later.

Illustrative Example of IRL To further illustrate the fact that [while p do g] = [if p then g;f end_if] consider a concrete example... Let K = while y>0 do x,y := x+1,y−1 Claim: K is function equivalent to Q = if y>0 then x,y := x+1,y−1;k end_if where, by definition, k = [K]. p g p k o g

Illustrative Example of IRL (cont’d) Case (y>0): For K = while y>0 do x,y := x+1,y−1, the loop body executes y times before the predicate y>0 becomes false. By observation, then, the final value of x is x0+(1)y0 = x0+y0 and the final value of y is 0. Thus, (y>0) => k = (x,y := x+y,0) Also, note that when y=0 initially, k = I = (x,y := x,y) = (x,y := x+0,y) = (x,y := x+y,0) Therefore, (y≥0) => k = (x,y := x+y,0)

Illustrative Example of IRL (cont’d) Case (y>0): (cont’d) [Q] is a composition of two functions, i.e., k o g, and may be determined by direct substitution. For y>0 initially, y will be greater than OR EQUAL to 0 after executing the loop body, but since we know (y≥0) => k = (x,y := x+y,0), we have [Q] = (x,y := x+y,0) o (x,y := x+1,y−1) = (x,y := (x+1)+(y−1),0) = (x,y := x+y,0) = k (the function computed by K) Thus, [Q] = [K] when y>0.

Illustrative Example of IRL (cont’d) Case (y≤0): Since the predicate (y>0) fails, both K and Q do nothing, and are therefore equivalent. Thus, [Q] = I = [K] when y≤0. Therefore, K is function equivalent to Q.

Termination Predicate The correctness of a looping program P depends, in part, on termination. Consideration is limited to programs whose termination can be established and the following predicate is defined: term(f,P)  ‘‘P terminates for every initial state X  D(f)’’

Before we continue… Take out a piece of paper and a pen/pencil. Without looking back in the lecture notes, write down the complete correctness con-ditions for: f = [if p then g]

if_then Correctness Conditions Complete correctness conditions for f = [if p then g]: Prove: p  (f = g) Л ¬p  (f = I) So, aside from proving termination over the domain of f, what are the two corresponding conditions for: f = [while p do g] = [if p then fog] ?

while_do Correctness Conditions Complete correctness conditions for f = [K] = [while p do G] (where g = [G] has already been shown): Prove: term(f,K) Л p  (f = f o g) Л ¬p  (f = I)

while_do Correctness Conditions (cont’d) Working correctness questions: Is loop termination guaranteed for any argument of f ? When p is true does f equal f composed with g? When p is false does f equal Identity?

while_do Example Prove f = [T] where, for integers x, y, and z: f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) and T is: while y<>0 do z := z+x y := y−1 end_while p G

while_do Example (cont’d) Proof: g = [G] = (z,y := z+x,y−1) by observation term(f,T)? f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) and T is: while y<>0 do z := z+x y := y−1 end_while So, does y≥0 initially  T will terminate?

while_do Example (cont’d) Proof: g = [G] = (z,y := z+x,y−1) by observation term(f,T)? √ (Prove this…)

while_do Example (cont’d) Proof: g = [G] = (z,y := z+x,y−1) by observation term(f,T)? √ (Prove this…) Does (y=0)  ( f = I )? ¬p ( Recall: f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Proof: g = [G] = (z,y := z+x,y−1) by observation term(f,T)? √ (Prove this…) Does (y=0)  ( f = I )? √ (y=0)  ( f = (z,y := z+x(0),0) = (z,y := z,0) ) (y=0)  ( I = (z,y := z,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? p

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case a: Does (y<0)  ( f = f o g )? (y<0)  ( f = undefined ) (y<0)  ( f o g = f o (z,y := z+x,y−1) What is f when applied after g decrements the initially negative value of y? ( Recall: f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case a: Does (y<0)  ( f = f o g )? (y<0)  ( f = undefined ) (y<0)  ( f o g = undefined o (z,y := z+x,y−1) since y<0  gy(y<0)<0 ( Recall: f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case a: Does (y<0)  ( f = f o g )? (y<0)  ( f = undefined ) (y<0)  ( f o g = undefined o (z,y := z+x,y−1) = undefined )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case a: Does (y<0)  ( f = f o g )? √ (y<0)  ( f = undefined ) (y<0)  ( f o g = undefined o (z,y := z+x,y−1) = undefined )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case b: Does (y>0)  ( f = f o g )? ( Recall: f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case b: Does (y>0)  ( f = f o g )? (y>0)  ( f = (z,y := z+xy,0) ) (y>0)  ( f o g = f o (z,y := z+x,y−1) Again, what is f when applied after g decrements the initially positive value of y? ( Recall: f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case b: Does (y>0)  ( f = f o g )? (y>0)  ( f = (z,y := z+xy,0) ) (y>0)  ( f o g = (z,y := z+xy,0) o (z,y := z+x,y−1) since y>0  gy(y>0)≥0 ( Recall: f = (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case b: Does (y>0)  ( f = f o g )? (y>0)  ( f = (z,y := z+xy,0) ) (y>0)  ( f o g = (z,y := z+xy,0) o (z,y := z+x,y−1) = (z,y := (z+x)+x(y−1),0) = (z,y := z+xy,0) )

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? case b: Does (y>0)  ( f = f o g )? (y>0)  ( f = (z,y := z+xy,0) ) (y>0)  ( f o g = (z,y := z+xy,0) o (z,y := z+x,y−1) = (z,y := (z+x)+x(y−1),0) = (z,y := z+xy,0) ) We could have also composed the full, conditional definition of f with g, i.e. (y≥0  z,y := z+xy,0) o (z,y := z+x,y−1) to yield (y≥1  z,y := z+xy,0) which is just (z,y := z+xy,0) when y>0.

while_do Example (cont’d) Does (y0)  ( f = f o g )? √ case b: Does (y>0)  ( f = f o g )? √ (y>0)  ( f = (z,y := z+xy,0) ) (y>0)  ( f o g = (z,y := z+xy,0) o (z,y := z+x,y−1) = (z,y := (z+x)+x(y−1),0) = (z,y := z+xy,0) ) Therefore, f = [T].

Exercise 1 For program M below, where all variables are integers, hypothesize a function f for [M] and prove f = [M]. while i<n do t := t*x i := i+1 end_while

Sufficient Correctness Conditions Given the complete correctness conditions for f = [H] = [while p do g]: Prove: term(f,H) Л p  (f = f o g) Л ¬p  (f = I)

Sufficient Correctness Conditions (cont’d) What are the sufficient correctness conditions for f  [H] = [while p do g]? Prove: f’ = [H] for some f’ Л f  f’

Sufficient Correctness Conditions (cont’d) What are the sufficient correctness conditions for f  [H] (for ANY program, H)? Prove: f’ = [H] for some f’ Л f  f’

repeat_until Statement What are the complete correctness conditions for f = [R] = [repeat g until p]? g f = T p F

repeat_until Statement (cont’d) An IRL for repeat_until statements: f = [repeat g until p] = [g; if ¬p then f]

“Proof” by Picture g g g g f = = = = p p ¬p p g f f p T T F T F F T F

repeat_until Statement (cont’d) Therefore, it is sufficient to verify that 1. R terminates for all X  D(f), and that 2. f is the program function of Q = g; if ¬p then f end_if because [R] = [Q].

repeat_until Correctness Conditions Complete correctness conditions for f = [R] = [repeat G until p] (where g = [G] has already been shown): Prove: term(f,R) Л (p o g)  (f = g) Л ¬(p o g)  (f = f o g)

repeat_until Correctness Conditions (cont’d) Working correctness questions: Is loop termination guaranteed for any argument of f ? When p o g is true does f equal g? When p o g is false does f equal f o g?

Exercise 2 For program R below, where all variables are integers, hypothesize a function r for [R] and prove r = [R]. repeat: x := x−1 y := y+2 until x=0

Summary Iteration Recursion Lemma (IRL) Termination predicate: term(f,P) Correctness conditions for while_do statement Sufficient correctness conditions Correctness conditions for repeat_until statement Subgoal Induction

Coming up next… Thinking about invariants again Invariant Status Theorem (IST) While Loop Initialization Utility of IST

Functional Verification III Software Testing and Verification Lecture Notes 23 Prepared by Stephen M. Thebaut, Ph.D. University of Florida