Normative Virtue Ethics

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
What is deontology?.
Advertisements

Frameworks for Moral Arguments
Themes in Ethics and Epistemology
Ethical Theory.
Aristotle’s Virtue Ethics. How should we distribute the guitars? (Who should get one? Why?)
Practical wisdom Michael Lacewing
Normative Ethical Theory Jim Okapal Asst. Professor of Philosophy Missouri Western State University.
Michael Lacewing Virtue Ethics Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Rosalind Hursthouse: Virtue Theory and Abortion
© Michael Lacewing Three theories of ethics Michael Lacewing
Natural Law/Virtue Ethics. Morality and Human Nature  Natural Law Theory  Based upon assumption that the good is consistent with fundamental design.
1Chapter SECTION OPENER / CLOSER: INSERT BOOK COVER ART Defining Ethics Section 1.1.
UNIT 1 Ethics and the Law Section 1.1 Defining Ethics Section 1.2
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
AS Philosophy & Ethics Mrs Sudds What are your expectations?
“A man without ethics is a wild beast loosed upon this world.”
Rule utilitarianism Michael Lacewing
Ethical Theories Unit 9 Ethical Awareness. What Are Ethical Theories? - Explain what makes an action right or wrong - Have an overview of major ethical.
AIT, Comp. Sci. & Info. Mgmt AT02.98 Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues in Computing September Term, Objectives of these slides: l to describe an.
Ethical Decision Making , Ethical Theories
ETHICALETHICALETHICALETHICAL PRINCIPLESPRINCIPLESPRINCIPLESPRINCIPLES.
Utilitarianism Utilitarians focus on the consequences of actions.
An act is moral if it brings more good consequences than bad ones. What is the action to be evaluated? What would be the good consequences? How certain.
Basic Framework of Normative Ethics. Normative Ethics ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’ or ‘controls’ ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’
Kant and Kantian Ethics: Is it possible for “reason” to supply the absolute principles of morality?
Seminar Three.  1. Review of Work Due  2. Course Content  Virtue Ethics  Abortion  Universal Health Insurance.
KANTIAN ETHICS Immanuel Kant ( ).
MNU Five Other Ethical Systems Dr. Judy Martin Session 7 – February 18, 2014.
Ethical Perspectives October 18, Moral Objectivism Moral principles have objective validity, independent of cultural acceptance Moral principles.
The Ethics of Care According to this method, we have an obligation to exercise special care toward the people with whom we have valuable, close relationships.
Virtue Ethics: The goal of life is well-being (happiness) and the means to attain it is by acquiring a virtuous character.
Morality and the Moral Life. Ethics (moral philosophy): The study of morality using the methods of philosophy. Morality: Our beliefs about right and wrong.
Review for Exam 1.
Ethics and Moral reasoning
Basic concepts in Ethics
Ethics Topic 3.
Contemporary Moral Problems
Metaethics: an overview
Aristotle on practical wisdom
Chapter 1: A Moral Theory Primer
Michael Lacewing Rule utilitarianism Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Basic Principles: Ethics and Business
Ethical Dilemmas in Leadership
Michael Lacewing Virtue Ethics Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Without using your notes:
Without using your notes:
Kant and Kantian Ethics:
Deontology Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology.
Wisdom,Knowledge and Information
Divine command ethics, The morale positivism of Thomos Hobbes, Virtue Ethics. Basnet Narayan.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Recap Key-Terms Cognitivism Non-Cognitivism Realism Anti-Realism
Recap – Function Argument
Summary of Virtue Ethics
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
What is the difference between: Can you give an example of each?
What are the two types of virtue according to Aristotle
Summary of Virtue Ethics
01 4 Ethical Language 4.1 Meta-Ethics.
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
What is Ethics? Monday, May 22, 2017.
A Review of Principles DR. K. Smith, PharmD, MPH.
Recap Why was vagueness an issue for Virtue Ethics? What responses to this problem did we discuss last lesson? Do the responses work?
Kant’s Moral Theory.
Information, Knowledge and Wisdom
HONESTY.
Deontology Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology.
Traditional Ethical Theories
Utilitarianism Jeremy Bentham
Basic Principles: Ethics and Business
Presentation transcript:

Normative Virtue Ethics

What is a Moral Theory? Gives useful definitions of the elements of moral experience. A definition is ‘useful’ if it provides guidance for practical (moral) reasoning. What is a virtuous or vicious character trait? What is a right or wrong action? What is a morally good or bad state of affairs? Gives guidance for practical (moral) reasoning. Definitions can be used for classification. Provides rules we can reason with. Provides a procedure for resolving any moral dilemma (?) Explains how we achieve and transmit moral knowledge. What is moral knowledge? Is it empirical or a priori? How should we morally educate children?

The Challenge to Virtue Ethics Virtue ethics is not a moral theory because it doesn’t: Give a useful definition of right (and wrong) action. Provide rules for reasoning about right and wrong action. Provide a way of resolving every moral dilemma. Hursthouse argues that virtue ethics does give a useful definition of right (and wrong) action, and does provide rules of reasoning about right and wrong action. She argues that a moral theory need not provide a way of resolving every moral dilemma. In arguing for these points, she gives us a virtue ethics account of moral knowledge.

What is Virtue Ethics? It is a view about morality that emphasizes virtues, or moral character, as opposed to the consequences of actions (consequentialism) or rules of action (deontology). A virtue is an excellent character trait; a vice is a defective character trait. A character trait a well-entrenched disposition to notice, expect, value, feel, desire, choose, act, and react in certain characteristic ways.

Virtue Ethics and Right Action Hursthouse argues that virtue ethics gives the following definition of right action: V1. An action is right if and only if it is what a virtuous agent would characteristically (i.e. acting in character) do in the circumstances.

Virtue Ethics and Right Action Objection 1: this definition is not useful because it doesn’t tell us what counts as a virtuous agent. Hursthouse’s response is that it need not do this on its own. We can add: V1a. A virtuous agent is one who acts virtuously, that is, one who has and exercises the virtues. V2. A virtue is a character trait that…(a human being needs for euidamonia... is useful or agreeable to its possessor or others...) List of virtues derived from V2 (e.g., honesty, charity, kindness). Virtue ethics is in this respect just like consequentialism and deontology, according to Hursthouse.

Virtue Ethics and Right Action Objection 2: (1) Either I am a virtuous agent or I am not. (2) If I am, then I don’t need this definition in order to act rightly. (3) If I’m not, then I can’t use this definition to act rightly, because I cannot know what a virtuous agent would do. So (4) whether I am a virtuous agent or not, this definition is not useful. Hursthouse’s response is that (3) is false. I can know what a virtuous agent would do by consulting a virtuous agent, or by acting in accordance with the list of virtues derived from V2.

Virtue Ethics and Rules to Reason With The Virtue Ethics Account of Right Action V1. An action is right if and only if it is what a virtuous agent would characteristically (i.e. acting in character) do in the circumstances. V1a. A virtuous agent is one who acts virtuously, that is, one who has and exercises the virtues. V2. A virtue is a character trait that…(a human being needs for euidamonia... is useful or agreeable to its possessor or others...) List of virtues (e.g., honesty, kindness, charity). The rules that virtue ethics gives us (“V-Rules”) are derived from V1 and the list of virtues: For example, “do not act uncharitably,” “act honestly,” and so on.

Virtue Ethics and Rules to Reason With Objection 1 to the V-Rules: they aren’t useful because they use difficult evaluative terms (“honesty,” “charity,” etc.) Hursthouse’s response is that most rival moral theories must use rules with evaluative content. E.g., deontology will yield a rule like “Do not kill the innocent,” “Do not kill unjustly,” and so on.

Virtue Ethics and Rules to Reason With Objection 2 to the V-Rules: due to their use of difficult evaluative terms (“honesty,” “charitably,”) these rules could not be used for the purposes of moral education. Hursthouse’s response is that, although we can use simplified rules for children (“do not lie”), if we have an interest in teaching them the moral truth, and the moral truth about what to do is the virtue-ethical account, then we ultimately want children to achieve a more sophisticated level of moral understanding—an understanding that, e.g., to be honest is not the same as never lying. The V-Rules represent the moral truth.

Virtue Ethics and Moral Dilemmas Objection 3 to the V-Rules: The V-Rules can sometimes tell us to do mutually inconsistent things (e.g., act both justly and mercifully). And the V-Rules don’t tell us how to resolve these conflicts. So the V-Rules fail to provide guidance. Hursthouse responds that virtue ethics has resources to resolve some conflicts between V-Rules. Some conflicts are merely apparent, arising from a mis-application of the virtue or vice terms. For example, an apparent conflict between the V-Rule “act kindly” and “act honestly” can sometimes be resolved once we see that in this particular case, concealing the truth is not kind, or that the importance of the truth is more important than hurt feelings.

Virtue Ethics and Moral Dilemmas Furthermore, virtue ethics has a deep explanation for why such apparent moral dilemmas can arise. Determining the morally right action can be difficult because the morally right action is determined by the v-rules, and correctly applying the v-rules in a particular case requires experience—it requires knowing, for example, what sort of truths can be concealed without cost to the person lied to, and what sort of truths ought to told regardless of hurt feelings. Hence, moral knowledge is empirical, unlike mathematical knowledge. Because of this, moral whiz-kids are extremely rare.

Virtue Ethics and Moral Dilemmas Hursthouse acknowledges that some moral dilemmas cannot be readily resolved (i.e., reduced to a single “solution,” an action or choice) by virtue ethics. She thinks it’s possible that some moral dilemmas are irresolvable. If moral theories must provide a solution to any moral dilemma, then virtue ethics is not a moral theory. But Hursthouse denies that a moral theory must provide a solution to every moral dilemma. Instead, she says that a moral theory can and should leave open whether or not there are some irresolvable moral dilemmas. Virtue ethics does leave this question open: it’s possible to be a virtue ethicist and think that, for any situation of choice, there is exactly one morally right choice; or that there are some situations in which there is more than one morally right choice (or none).

Questions Do you find the virtue-ethics account of right action persuasive? Do you agree that moral knowledge depends on experience, at least to a large extent? Do you think there are irresolvable moral dilemmas?

For Thursday Read Jack Smart’s “Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism.”