Decisions under risk Sri Hermawati.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
From risk to opportunity Lecture 10 John Hey and Carmen Pasca.
Advertisements

Paradoxes in Decision Making With a Solution. Lottery 1 $3000 S1 $4000 $0 80% 20% R1 80%20%
Chapter 12 Uncertainty Consider two lotteries L 1 : 500,000 (1) L 1 ’: 2,500,000 (0.1), 500,000 (0.89), 0 (0.01) Which one would you choose? Another two.
Utility Theory.
1 1 Slide © 2009 South-Western, a part of Cengage Learning Slides by John Loucks St. Edward’s University.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 6 Pascal’s wager
General Logic In order to decide what we ought to do to obtain some good or avoid some harm, it is necessary to consider not only the good or harm in itself,
6-1 Stats Unit 6 Sampling Distributions and Statistical Inference - 1 FPP Chapters 16-18, 20-21, 23 The Law of Averages (Ch 16) Box Models (Ch 16) Sampling.
General Logic In order to decide what we ought to do to obtain some good or avoid some harm, it is necessary to consider not only the good or harm in itself,
When Intuition Differs from Relative Frequency
Behavioral Finance Uncertain Choices February 18, 2014 Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Utility Axioms Axiom: something obvious, cannot be proven Utility axioms (rules for clear thinking)
CHAPTER 14 Utility Axioms Paradoxes & Implications.
1 Utility Theory. 2 Option 1: bet that pays $5,000,000 if a coin flipped comes up tails you get $0 if the coin comes up heads. Option 2: get $2,000,000.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Utility Functions, Utility Elicitation, and Risk Attitudes Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
L3: Risk and Risk Measurement 1 Risk and Risk Measurement (L3) Following topics are covered: –Risk –Defining “More Risk Averse” Utility functions Absolute.
Decision making and economics. Economic theories Economic theories provide normative standards Expected value Expected utility Specialized branches like.

1 A Brief History of Descriptive Theories of Decision Making Kiel, June 9, 2005 Michael H. Birnbaum California State University, Fullerton.
1 The Case Against Prospect Theories of Risky Decision Making Michael H. Birnbaum California State University, Fullerton.
1 A Brief History of Descriptive Theories of Decision Making: Lecture 2: SWU and PT Kiel, June 10, 2005 Michael H. Birnbaum California State University,
Risk and Uncertainty for Fun and for Profit Risk = “Objective Uncertainty” –You know the probabilities of all the outcomes Uncertainty = “Subjective Uncertainty”
Behavioral Finance Other Noise Trader Models Feb 3, 2015 Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
PSY 5018H: Math Models Hum Behavior, Prof. Paul Schrater, Spring 2005 Rational Decision Making.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Probability, Utility, and Game Theory Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
Problems With Expected Utility or if the axioms fit, use them but...
Jon Curwin and Roger Slater, QUANTITATIVE METHODS: A SHORT COURSE ISBN © Thomson Learning 2004 Jon Curwin and Roger Slater, QUANTITATIVE.
Decision Analysis (cont)
Decision making Making decisions Optimal decisions Violations of rationality.
Economic evaluation of health programmes Department of Epidemiology, Biostatistics and Occupational Health Class no. 9: Cost-utility analysis – Part 2.
Thinking and Decision Making
Phil 148 Choices. Choice Theory: The relationship between probability and action is often complex, however we can use simple mathematical operations (so.
Markets, Firms and Consumers Lecture 4- Capital and the Firm.
Prospect Theory. 23A i 23B, reference point 23A) Your country is plagued with an outbreak of an exotic Asian disease, which may kill 600 people. You.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 6 Pascal’s wager By David Kelsey.
Playing the Lottery 6/4/2016Copyright © 2010… REMTECH, inc … All Rights Reserved1 Probability Theory and the Lottery ● The Lottery picks numbers at random.
Ellsberg’s paradoxes: Problems for rank- dependent utility explanations Cherng-Horng Lan & Nigel Harvey Department of Psychology University College London.
Choice under uncertainty Assistant professor Bojan Georgievski PhD 1.
Decision theory under uncertainty
© 2005 Pearson Education Canada Inc Chapter 17 Choice Making Under Uncertainty.
Expected Value, Expected Utility & the Allais and Ellsberg Paradoxes
Allais Paradox, Ellsberg Paradox, and the Common Consequence Principle Then: Introduction to Prospect Theory Psychology 466: Judgment & Decision Making.
1 Systems Analysis Methods Dr. Jerrell T. Stracener, SAE Fellow SMU EMIS 5300/7300 NTU SY-521-N NTU SY-521-N SMU EMIS 5300/7300 Utility Theory Applications.
Risk Efficiency Criteria Lecture XV. Expected Utility Versus Risk Efficiency In this course, we started with the precept that individual’s choose between.
Behavioral Finance Biases Feb 23 Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Behavioral Finance Preferences Part I Feb 16 Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
DADSS Lecture 11: Decision Analysis with Utility Elicitation and Use.
Uncertainty and Games (Ch. 15). Uncertainty If a game outcome is certain can it achieve meaningful play? –Example of such a game? Two kinds of uncertainty:
RISK AND UNCERTAINTY Scarce resources create opportunities costs, which renders the idea of a zero-risk society a noble but unattainable goal. 1.
Time Value of Money Present value of any the amount of money today that would future sum of money = be needed at current interest rates to.
Ex Ante Efficiency and Ex Post Equality
Causal vs. evidential decision theory
Vincent Conitzer CPS Utility theory Vincent Conitzer
Probability Axioms and Formulas
Introduction to Decision theory
19/11/1439 Decision Analysis.
Games of pure conflict two person constant sum
Expected Value, Expected Utility & the Allais and Ellsberg Paradoxes
Lecture 2 Hastie & Dawes: Changing Our Minds: Bayes’ Theorem. In Rational Choice in an UncertainWorld, 2nd ed., 2010, pp
The Allais Paradox & the Ellsberg Paradox
Risk Chapter 11.
Decision Analysis Decision Trees Chapter 3
Utility Theory Decision Theory.
Choices, Values and Frames
Contemporary Engineering Economics
Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Vincent Conitzer Utility theory Vincent Conitzer
Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Making Simple Decisions
Presentation transcript:

Decisions under risk Sri Hermawati

Maximising what? three closely related principles The principle of maximising expected monetary value The principle of maximising expected value The principle of maximising expected utility

example Imagine that you are offered a choice between receiving a million dollars for sure, and receiving a lottery ticket that entitles you to a fifty per cent chance of winning either three million dollars or nothing

The expected monetary value (EMV) The expected monetary value (EMV) of these lotteries can be computed by applying the following general formula, EMV = p1.m1 + p2. m2 +....... + pn mn (1) in which p1 is the probability of the first state and m1 the monetary value of the corresponding outcome:

expected value the principle of maximising expected value makes more sense from a normative point of view than the principle of maximising expected monetary value. EV = p1.v1 + p2.v2 + ..... + pn.vn (2)

utility in order to single out the kind of value that is the primary object of study in decision theory – the value of an outcome as evaluated from the decision makers point of view – it is the concept of utility EU = p1.u1 + p2.u2 + ..... + pn.un (3)

Why is it rational to maximise expected utility? based on the law of large numbers; it seeks to show that in the long run you will be better off if you maximise expected utility. Deriving the expected utility principle from some more fundamental axioms for rational decision making, which make no reference to what will happen in the long run.

The axiomatic approach The axiomatic approach to the expected utility principle is not based on the law of large numbers to show that the expected utility principle can be derived from axioms that hold independently of what would happen in the long run.

two fundamentally different strategies for axiomatising the expected utility principle. In the indirect approach, which is the dominant approach, the decision maker does not prefer a risky act to another because the expected utility of the former exceeds that of the latter. The direct approach seeks to generate preferences over acts from probabilities and utilities directly assigned to outcomes.

A direct axiomatisation of the expected utility principle EU 1 : If all outcomes of an act have utility u, then the utility of the act is u. EU 2 : If one act is certain to lead to better outcomes under all states than another, then the utility of the first act exceeds that of the latter; and if both acts lead to equal outcomes they have the same utility. EU 3 : Every decision problem can be transformed into a decision problem with equally probable states, in which the utility of all acts is preserved. EU 4 : If two outcomes are equally probable, and if the better outcome is made slightly worse, then this can be compensated for by adding some amount of utility to the other outcome, such that the overall utility of the act is preserved.

Allais paradox Ticket no. 1 Ticket no. 2–11 Ticket no. 12–100 Gamble 1 In a choice between Gamble 1 and Gamble 2 it seems reasonable to choose Gamble 1 since it gives the decision maker one million dollars for sure ($1M), whereas in a choice between Gamble 3 and Gamble 4 many people would feel that it makes sense to trade a ten-in-hundred chance of getting $5M, against a one-in-hundred risk of getting nothing, and consequently choose Gamble 4. the principle of maximising expected utility recommends that the decision maker prefers Gamble 1 to Gamble 2 if and only if Gamble 3 is preferred to Gamble 4. Ticket no. 1 Ticket no. 2–11 Ticket no. 12–100 Gamble 1 $1M Gamble 2 $0 $5M Gamble 3 Gamble 4

Ellsbergs paradox Suppose the decision maker is presented with an urn containing 90 balls, 30 of which are red. The remaining 60 balls are either black or yellow, but the proportion between black and yellow balls is unknown. The decision maker is then offered a choice between the following gambles: Gamble 1 Receive $100 if a red ball is drawn Gamble 2 Receive $100 if a black ball is drawn Gamble 3 Receive $100 if a red or yellow ball is drawn Gamble 4 Receive $100 if a black or yellow ball is drawn.

Ellsbergs paradox 30 60 red yelow Gamble 1 $100 $0 Gamble 2 Gamble 3 No matter what the decision makers utility for money is, and no matter what she believes about the proportion of black and yellow balls in the urn, the principle of maximising expected utility can never recommend G1 over G2 and G4 over G3, or vice versa. This is because the expected utility of G1 exceeds that of G2 if and only if the expected utility of G3 exceeds that of G4. To show this, we calculate the difference in expected utility between G1 and G2, as well as the difference between G3 and G4.