Negations of Quantified Statements

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
The Logic of Quantified Statements
Advertisements

CS128 – Discrete Mathematics for Computer Science
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 2 THE LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS THE LOGIC OF COMPOUND STATEMENTS.
2.2 Conditional Statements. Goals Identify statements which are conditional Identify the antecedent and consequent of a conditional statement Negate conditional.
Discrete Structures Chapter 1 Part B Fundamentals of Logic Nurul Amelina Nasharuddin Multimedia Department 1.
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 2 Alexander Bukharovich New York University.
Discrete Mathematics Math 6A Instructor: M. Welling.
Chapter 3: The Logic of Quantified Statements 3.2 Predicates and Quantified Statements II 1 TOUCHSTONE: Stand you both forth now: stroke your chins, and.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Discrete Structures Chapter 3: The Logic of Quantified Statements
Ch 1.3: Quantifiers Open sentences, or predicates, are sentences that contain one or more variables. They do not have a truth value until variables are.
CSE115/ENGR160 Discrete Mathematics 01/20/11 Ming-Hsuan Yang UC Merced 1.
Quantifiers and Negation Predicates. Predicate Will define function. The domain of a function is the set from which possible values may be chosen for.
Predicates and Quantifiers
Section 1.5 Implications. Implication Statements If Cara has a piano lesson, then it is Friday. If it is raining, then I need to remember my umbrella.
Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications
Mathematical Structures A collection of objects with operations defined on them and the accompanying properties form a mathematical structure or system.
Predicates and Quantified Statements M , 3.2.
Chapter 1, Part II: Predicate Logic With Question/Answer Animations.
2.3Logical Implication: Rules of Inference From the notion of a valid argument, we begin a formal study of what we shall mean by an argument and when such.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 3 THE LOGIC OF QUANTIFIED STATEMENTS THE LOGIC OF QUANTIFIED STATEMENTS.
Thinking Mathematically Equivalent Statements, Conditional Statements, and De Morgan’s Laws.
(CSC 102) Lecture 8 Discrete Structures. Previous Lectures Summary Predicates Set Notation Universal and Existential Statement Translating between formal.
Predicates and Quantified Statements
Chapter 2 The Logic of Quantified Statements. Section 2.1 Intro to Predicates & Quantified Statements.
Chapter 2 Logic 2.1 Statements 2.2 The Negation of a Statement 2.3 The Disjunction and Conjunction of Statements 2.4 The Implication 2.5 More on Implications.
Lecture 7 – Jan 28, Chapter 2 The Logic of Quantified Statements.
CS 285- Discrete Mathematics Lecture 4. Section 1.3 Predicate logic Predicate logic is an extension of propositional logic that permits concisely reasoning.
Week 4 - Friday.  What did we talk about last time?  Floor and ceiling  Proof by contradiction.
Section 1.5 and 1.6 Predicates and Quantifiers. Vocabulary Predicate Domain Universal Quantifier Existential Quantifier Counterexample Free variable Bound.
1 Introduction to Abstract Mathematics Chapter 3: The Logic of Quantified Statements. Predicate Calculus Instructor: Hayk Melikya 3.1.
Discrete Mathematics Lecture # 4. Conditional Statements or Implication  If p and q are statement variables, the conditional of q by p is “If p then.
Section 1.4. Propositional Functions Propositional functions become propositions (and have truth values) when their variables are each replaced by a value.
Introduction to Predicates and Quantified Statements I Lecture 9 Section 2.1 Wed, Jan 31, 2007.
Simple Logic.
رياضيات متقطعة لعلوم الحاسب MATH 226. Chapter 1 Predicates and Quantifiers 1.4.
Harper Langston New York University Summer 2017
2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary
Conditional Statements
3. The Logic of Quantified Statements Summary
Predicates and Quantified Statements I
CSE15 Discrete Mathematics 01/23/17
CSNB 143 Discrete Mathematical Structures
Chapter 3 The Logic of Quantified Statements
Methods of proof Section 1.6 & 1.7 Wednesday, June 20, 2018
Logic.
(CSC 102) Discrete Structures Lecture 2.
CMSC Discrete Structures
Chapter 1 The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Introduction to Predicates and Quantified Statements II
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
CHAPTER 1: LOGICS AND PROOF
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Introduction to Predicates and Quantified Statements II
Chapter 1 Logic and Proof.
(1.4) An Introduction to Logic
Introduction to Predicates and Quantified Statements I
Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications Kenneth H
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 3: Predicate and Quantifier
Discrete Mathematics CMP-200 Propositional Equivalences, Predicates & Quantifiers, Negating Quantified Statements Abdul Hameed
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Equivalent Statements
Predicates and Quantifiers
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 4 Logic of Quantified Statements
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
CPSC 121: Models of Computation
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Logic Logic is a discipline that studies the principles and methods used to construct valid arguments. An argument is a related sequence of statements.
CHAPTER 3 Logic.
Presentation transcript:

Negations of Quantified Statements “All students in class passed this course” “There exists a student in class such that he/she did not pass this course.” Let D denote the set of students in class, and let P(x) denote “x passed this course.” ∀x  D, P(x) ∃x  D, ~P(x)

Negations of Quantified Statements

Negations of Quantified Statements Thus The negation of a universal statement (“all are”) is logically equivalent to an existential statement (“some are not” or “there is at least one that is not”). The negation of an existential statement (“some are”) is logically equivalent to a universal statement (“none are” or “all are not”). Note that when we speak of logical equivalence for quantified statements, we mean that the statements always have identical truth values no matter what predicates are substituted for the predicate symbols and no matter what sets are used for the domains of the predicate variables.

Negations of Universal Conditional Statements Negations of universal conditional statements are of special importance in mathematics. The form of such negations can be derived from facts that have already been established. By definition of the negation of a for all statement, But the negation of an if-then statement is logically equivalent to an and statement. More precisely,

Negations of Universal Conditional Statements Substituting (3.2.2) into (3.2.1) gives Written less symbolically, this becomes

Example 4 – Negating Universal Conditional Statements Write a formal negation for statement (a) and an informal negation for statement (b). a. ∀ people p, if p is blond then p has blue eyes. ∃ a person p such that p is blond and p does not have blue eyes. b. If a computer program has more than 100,000 lines, then it contains a bug. There is at least one computer program that has more than 100,000 lines and does not contain a bug.

The Relation among ∀, ∃, ∧, and ∨ The negation of a for all statement is a there exists statement, and the negation of a there exists statement is a for all statement. These facts are analogous to De Morgan’s laws, which state that the negation of an and statement is an or statement and that the negation of an or statement is an and statement. This similarity is not accidental. In a sense, universal statements are generalizations of and statements, and existential statements are generalizations of or statements.

The Relation among ∀, ∃, ∧, and ∨ If Q(x) is a predicate and the domain D of x is the set {x1, x2, . . . , xn}, then the statements and are logically equivalent.

The Relation among ∀, ∃, ∧, and ∨ Similarly, if Q(x) is a predicate and D = {x1, x2, . . . , xn}, then the statements and are logically equivalent.

Vacuous Truth of Universal Statements In general, a statement of the form is called vacuously true or true by default if, and only if, P(x) is false for every x in D.

Variants of Universal Conditional Statements We have known that a conditional statement has a contrapositive, a converse, and an inverse. The definitions of these terms can be extended to universal conditional statements.

∀x ∈ R, if x > 2 then x2 > 4. Example 5 – Contrapositive, Converse, and Inverse of a Universal Conditional Statement Write a formal and an informal contrapositive, converse, and inverse for the following statement: If a real number is greater than 2, then its square is greater than 4. Solution: The formal version of this statement is ∀x ∈ R, if x > 2 then x2 > 4.

Example 5 – Solution Contrapositive: ∀x ∈ R, if x2 ≤ 4 then x ≤ 2. cont’d Contrapositive: ∀x ∈ R, if x2 ≤ 4 then x ≤ 2. Or: If the square of a real number is less than or equal to 4, then the number is less than or equal to 2. Converse: ∀x ∈ R, if x2 > 4 then x > 2. Or: If the square of a real number is greater than 4, then the number is greater than 2. Inverse: ∀x ∈ R, if x ≤ 2 then x2 ≤ 4. Or: If a real number is less than or equal to 2, then the square of the number is less than or equal to 4.

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions, Only If The definitions of necessary, sufficient, and only if can also be extended to apply to universal conditional statements.

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions, Only If Being born in U.S. is a sufficient condition for being eligible for U.S. citizenship. ∀ people p, if p is born in U.S, then p is eligible for U.S. citizenship. Being at least 18 years old is a necessary condition for being eligible to vote. ∀ people p, p is eligible to vote only if p is at least 18 years old. ∀ people p, if p is not at least 18 years old, then p is not eligible to vote. ∀ people p, if p is eligible to vote, then p is at least 18 years old.