If You Aren’t Dong Arguments, You Aren’t Doing Evidence

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Reason and Argument Induction (Part of Ch. 9 and part of Ch. 10)
Advertisements

Believing Where We Cannot Prove Philip Kitcher
Hypotheticals: The If/Then Form Hypothetical arguments are usually more obvious than categorical ones. A hypothetical argument has an “if/then” pattern.
What is Social Theory?. Theory Harrington 2005: 1-3 Greek word theōria, opp. of praxis contemplation / reflection Reflection on the value and meaning.
Libertarianism A Libertarian, such as Taylor:
Hume’s Problem of Induction 2 Seminar 2: Philosophy of the Sciences Wednesday, 14 September
 Assertions: unsupported declaration of a belief  Prejudice: a view without evidence for or against  Premises: explicit evidence that lead to a conclusion.
Debate: Evidence. Review Valid: The conclusion of the argument follows logically from its premises. Sound: The argument is valid and all of its premises.
© Michael Lacewing Hume’s scepticism Michael Lacewing
Naturalism The world we live in. Supplementary Reading A Field Guide to Recent Species of Naturalism Alex Rosenberg The British Journal for the Philosophy.
Cosmological arguments from causation Michael Lacewing
Prepared By Jacques E. ZOO Bohm’s Philosophy of Nature David Bohm, Causality and Chance in Modern Physics (New York, 1957). From Feyerabend, P. K.
Logic. what is an argument? People argue all the time ― that is, they have arguments.  It is not often, however, that in the course of having an argument.
Lecture 6 1. Mental gymnastics to prepare to tackle Hume 2. The Problem of Induction as Hume argues for it 1. His question 2. His possible solutions 3.
Kent Where causal dualism comes from Monika Koeppl Causality, Cognition and the Constitution of Scientific Phenomena Department of Philosophy University.
The Problem of Knowledge. What new information would cause you to be less certain? So when we say “I’m certain that…” what are we saying? 3 things you.
Research Methods and Design
Descartes I am essentially rational, only accidentally an animal ‘essentially’ = logically necessarily ‘essentially’ = logically necessarily Strictly speaking,
Confirmation Bias. Critical Thinking Among our critical thinking questions were: Does the evidence really support the claim? Is there other evidence that.
Do Now Wednesday, August 27, 2014 Do Now Wednesday, August 27, 2014 What are three things you recall about the scientific method? Write your answer using.
What’s EPB? What’s so good about RCTs? (And what are we reading?) Philosophy of Social Science Phil 152 Winter 2011 Week 8.
Welcome to MM570 Psychological Statistics
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-a What is philosophy? By David Kelsey.
Philosophy 148 Inductive Reasoning. Inductive reasoning – common misconceptions: - “The process of deriving general principles from particular facts or.
Miracles: Hume and Howard-Snyder. * For purposes of initial clarity, let's define a miracle as a worldly event that is not explicable by natural causes.
Building Blocks of Scientific Research Chapter 5 References:  Business Research (Duane Davis)  Business Research Methods (Cooper/Schindler) Resource.
Certainty and ErrorCertainty and Error One thing Russell seems right about is that we don’t need certainty in order to know something. In fact, even Descartes.
Errors in Reasoning. Fallacies A Fallacy is “any error in reasoning that makes an argument fail to establish its conclusion.” There are two kinds of fallacies.
I think therefore I am - Rene Descartes. REASON (logic) It has been said that man is a rational animal. All my life I have been searching for evidence.
Philosophy of science What is a scientific theory? – Is a universal statement Applies to all events in all places and time – Explains the behaviour/happening.
Causal truthmakers vs Causal interpretations Federica Russo Philosophy, Kent.
Section 2 Effective Groupwork Online. Contents Effective group work activity what is expected of you in this segment of the course: Read the articles.
EXPERIENCE REASONING RESEARCH DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE REASONING Deductive Reasoning (Top-Down Approach) Deductive reasoning works from the more general.
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF SCIENCE?
Lecture 8 Time: McTaggart’s argument
Lecture #8 Thursday, September 15, 2016 Textbook: Section 4.4
Part 4 Reading Critically
Tutors:Maureen McLachlan & Joanne Duval
Introduction to Moral Theory
Sociological Research
Michael Lacewing Mackie’s error theory Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Introduction to Moral Theory
Inductive / Deductive reasoning
Research & Writing in CJ
Emotional Regulation: Checking the Facts
Research methods Lesson 2.
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
A new perspective on philosophical debates
UC San Diego Department of Mathematics
Dialectic.
Validity and Soundness
An introduction to Bayesian reasoning Learning from experience:
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
Logic, Philosophical Tools Quiz Review…20 minutes 10/31
Arguments.
Distinguish valid from invalid arguments and sound from unsound
The Nature of Science How can you differentiate between science and non-science using the scientific method?
Propositional Logic.
Midterm Discussion.
Metaphysics & Epistemology
Nature of Science Dr. Charles Ophardt EDU 370.
Significance Tests: The Basics
What processes do scientists use when they perform scientific investigations? Chapter Introduction.
Philosophy of Religion Arguments for the existence of God
Chapter 7: Sampling Distributions
Chapter 3 The Idea Of Causation on Social Research
Lucretianism Bigelow.
ID1050– Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning
Presentation transcript:

If You Aren’t Dong Arguments, You Aren’t Doing Evidence Kent Conference on Evidence and Causation Nancy Cartwright, UCSD & Durham University

Aim: A theory of evidence for domains where rigor is supposed to matter, like science and EBP. The Argument Theory of Evidence: Evidence = facts recorded in good arguments.

As empirical evidence for a fact h in science and EBP we want… True facts that speak for the policy. 21/09/2018

True facts We do not want to support our build an argument for a policy or scientific claims on shaky grounds. 21/09/2018

Speak for = relevant No matter how sturdy this foundation: It won’t support these houses:

Two going theories of relevance – that don’t work Achinstein’s evidential relevance = explanatory relevance Probabilistic accounts Esp. Roush, where relevance = f(liklihood) Achinstein’s catches more cases; Roush’s has the ‘right idea’ Peter Achinstein

Sherri Roush P(h/e) is high Leverage: P(e/h)/P(e/-h) > 1 P(e) is high

My enterprise = Roush’s enterprise Roush’s theory of knowledge ≠ Roush’s theory of evidence. Theory of knowledge has to do with what ensures our entitlement to take claims as true. Theory of evidence has to do with what ensures that claims are true. Roush: ‘...the notions of evidence that I am aiming for are objective in the following sense. That e is evidence for h is understood as holding in virtue of a factual relation between the statement e’s being true and the statement h’s being true, not in virtue of anyone’s believing that this relation exists.’ [p 156]

The use of evidence I want an account of evidence that tells us what evidence for h is. So that, when I want to know about h… I can use this account to ascertain whether e would be evidence for h were it to hold. So that I can then decide how much, if anything, to invest in trying to learn e in order to come to know about h.

Evidence is a not a 2-place What’s wrong with the 2 standard accounts They both expect a criterion that will Look at h Look at e Decide if e is evidence for h. But this won’t work because there is no such feature. Evidence is a not a 2-place but a 3-place relation E is evidence for h relative to A. What is A? A is a good argument. ……….

Explanatory relevance best case – causal relevance Is the occurrence of a cause of h evidence for the occurrence of h (s’posing h did occur)? Suppose the following are true The principle ‘Es (can) cause Hs’ An E-type event (e) occurs An H-type event (h) occurs But in this case not e but something else caused h.

Then the answer is NO What secures the relevance of ‘e occurs’ to ‘h occurs’ is the additional fact F: ‘e causes h’. Why should F make it the case that the occurrence of e speaks for the occurrence of h anymore than… any other fact F’ s.t. if F’ holds then if e occurs h occurs?

Suppose it is a fact that F’: if e occurs, h occurs 10 minutes later. Then e’s occurring is just as sure a guarantee that h occurs as it is given F (‘e causes h’). Perhaps it is more difficult to learn F’ than F. (Is it?) If so, maybe it is more difficult to know that e is evidence for h. But that doesn’t affect whether e is evidence for h. And, it can be just as difficult to learn e, or to learn that e is evidence for h, as it is to learn h ‘directly’. But that too has to do with knowledge, not with evidence.

The theory, in two versions Material mode: One fact, fe , is evidence for a second, fh, iff fe is a necessary member of a set of facts sufficient to ensure fh obtains. Formal mode: e is evidence for h iff e is a necessary premise in a (deductively) valid and sound argument for h.

What about probabilities? Here Roush has the right idea, in endorsing what she calls ‘Bayesianism’, which for her does not mean a subjective interpretation of probability. Rather…. ‘The Bayesian makes the idealizing assumption that all statements of the language in question possess probabilities. This is in contrast to the approach of classical statistics in which it is denied, for instance, that hypotheses have probabilities.’ [p 155] But for the objective notion of evidence that Roush and I both intend, it cannot be probabilities of statements that matter but rather probabilities of facts. I do not see that there generally are such probabilities.

Probabilities for facts arise from chance set-ups Suppose it is a fact that e: the ball in your hand is drawn from an urn with 8 red balls and 2 black each ball has an equal probabiliy of being drawn and nothing ‘untoward’ happens to affect the colour of the ball as it is drawn (no ‘finks’, etc).

Then (I allow) there is a probability (of .8) for h: the ball you hold is red. So maybe e speaks for the truth of Pr(h) = .8 This is my preferred choice. Maybe you think e speaks for the truth of h. If so, then modify the theory appropriately. But only where, as Roush too demands, there are objective probabilities. Subjective probabilities belong in epistemology, not in a theory of evidence.

Lots of objections E speaks for itself. Me: Yes, very loudly. False claims never have evidence. Me: Of course we very often think they do. A&B is evidence for both A and B. Me: Yes indeed, very good evidence. Any 2 true facts are evidence for each other. Me: Yes, but only relative to the right arguments. None are real problems unless… evidence is trafficking with epistemology.

Summary Keep epistemology out of evidence. Why? So that you know what counts as evidence. Then you can decide whether you can learn it, at what cost and what it will entitle you to. The Argument Theory Evidence is a 3-place relation: e is evidence for h relative to A iff A is a good argument for h in which e is an essential premise.

Of what use is the argument theory? Now we can talk of entitlement. We can police claims that there’s evidence in support of h. Claims that e is evidence for h are enthymemes: e is evidence for h relatve to a good argument A. Standards of rigor and explicitness expected in science and EBP  A be made explicit. Then we can check just how good A is – what are the chances the other premises are true.

So….. A Closing Injunction Claims that e is evidence for h need backing up… So….. A Closing Injunction It ain’t evidence unless there’s evidence it’s evidence.

Thank you!