Roman Słowiński Poznań University of Technology, Poland

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Duality for linear programming. Illustration of the notion Consider an enterprise producing r items: f k = demand for the item k =1,…, r using s components:
Advertisements

Multi‑Criteria Decision Making
Introduction to Algorithms
Multiple-criteria ranking using an additive value function constructed via ordinal regresion : UTA method Roman Słowiński Poznań University of Technology,
Preference Elicitation Partial-revelation VCG mechanism for Combinatorial Auctions and Eliciting Non-price Preferences in Combinatorial Auctions.
CmpE 104 SOFTWARE STATISTICAL TOOLS & METHODS MEASURING & ESTIMATING SOFTWARE SIZE AND RESOURCE & SCHEDULE ESTIMATING.
Fundamentals of Data Analysis Lecture 12 Methods of parametric estimation.
Copyright © 2006 Pearson Education Canada Inc Course Arrangement !!! Nov. 22,Tuesday Last Class Nov. 23,WednesdayQuiz 5 Nov. 25, FridayTutorial 5.
Approximation Algorithms
Development of Empirical Models From Process Data
MADM Y. İlker TOPCU, Ph.D twitter.com/yitopcu.
Regression Analysis British Biometrician Sir Francis Galton was the one who used the term Regression in the later part of 19 century.
Presented by Johanna Lind and Anna Schurba Facility Location Planning using the Analytic Hierarchy Process Specialisation Seminar „Facility Location Planning“
1. The Simplex Method.
STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE APPROACH TO PORTFOLIO OPTIMIZATION Nesrin Alptekin Anadolu University, TURKEY.
Lecture 12 Statistical Inference (Estimation) Point and Interval estimation By Aziza Munir.
Pareto Linear Programming The Problem: P-opt Cx s.t Ax ≤ b x ≥ 0 where C is a kxn matrix so that Cx = (c (1) x, c (2) x,..., c (k) x) where c.
Analyzing the Problem (Outranking Methods) Y. İlker TOPCU, Ph.D twitter.com/yitopcu.
EASTERN MEDITERRANEAN UNIVERSITY Department of Industrial Engineering Non linear Optimization Spring Instructor: Prof.Dr.Sahand Daneshvar Submited.
Preference Modelling and Decision Support Roman Słowiński Poznań University of Technology, Poland  Roman Słowiński.
1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 2 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 2 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Linear Program Set Cover. Given a universe U of n elements, a collection of subsets of U, S = {S 1,…, S k }, and a cost function c: S → Q +. Find a minimum.
1  The Problem: Consider a two class task with ω 1, ω 2   LINEAR CLASSIFIERS.
Multiple-criteria sorting using ELECTRE TRI Assistant
Dominance-Bases Rough Set Approach: Features, Extensions and Application Krzysztof Dembczyński Institute of Computing Science, Poznań University of Technology,
Helsinki University of Technology Systems Analysis Laboratory Incomplete Ordinal Information in Value Tree Analysis Antti Punkka and Ahti Salo Systems.
Preference Modelling and Decision Support Roman Słowiński Poznań University of Technology, Poland  Roman Słowiński.
Section VI Capital Rationing. Section Highlights F Capital rationing F Linear programming F Shadow prices and the cost of capital F Integer programming.
2.5 The Fundamental Theorem of Game Theory For any 2-person zero-sum game there exists a pair (x*,y*) in S  T such that min {x*V. j : j=1,...,n} =
To the Decision Deck platform UTA GMS /GRIP plugin Piotr Zielniewicz Poznan University of Technology, Poland 2nd Decision Deck Workshop February 21-22,
 This will explain how consumers allocate their income over many goods.  This looks at individual’s decision making when faced with limited income and.
Fundamentals of Data Analysis Lecture 11 Methods of parametric estimation.
1 Chapter 4 Geometry of Linear Programming  There are strong relationships between the geometrical and algebraic features of LP problems  Convenient.
Proof And Strategies Chapter 2. Lecturer: Amani Mahajoub Omer Department of Computer Science and Software Engineering Discrete Structures Definition Discrete.
MAT 322: LINEAR ALGEBRA.
EMGT 6412/MATH 6665 Mathematical Programming Spring 2016
Physics 114: Lecture 13 Probability Tests & Linear Fitting
Chapter 7. Classification and Prediction
LINEAR CLASSIFIERS The Problem: Consider a two class task with ω1, ω2.
Computation of the solutions of nonlinear polynomial systems
Chap 10. Sensitivity Analysis
Flexible and Interactive Tradeoff Elicitation Procedure
Chapter 11 Optimization with Equality Constraints
Chapter 5 Systems and Matricies. Chapter 5 Systems and Matricies.
Duality for linear programming.
Propositional Calculus: Boolean Algebra and Simplification
Dave Powell, Elon University,
Chap 9. General LP problems: Duality and Infeasibility
Polyhedron Here, we derive a representation of polyhedron and see the properties of the generators. We also see how to identify the generators. The results.
The Simplex Method.
Chap 3. The simplex method
DEMAND THEORY III Meeghat Habibian Transportation Demand Analysis
Polyhedron Here, we derive a representation of polyhedron and see the properties of the generators. We also see how to identify the generators. The results.
Where did we stop? The Bayes decision rule guarantees an optimal classification… … But it requires the knowledge of P(ci|x) (or p(x|ci) and P(ci)) We.
Chapter 11 Limitations of Algorithm Power
MA/CSSE 474 More Math Review Theory of Computation
Chapter 5. The Duality Theorem
Agenda for This Week Monday, April 25 AHP Wednesday, April 27
I.4 Polyhedral Theory (NW)
I.4 Polyhedral Theory.
Multicriteria Decision Making
Introduction to Value Tree Analysis
Dr. Arslan Ornek DETERMINISTIC OPTIMIZATION MODELS
Simplex method (algebraic interpretation)
1.2 Guidelines for strong formulations
TRANSPORTATION DEMAND ANALYSIS
FITradeoff Method (Flexible and Interactive Tradeoff)
1.2 Guidelines for strong formulations
Approximation of Functions
Approximation of Functions
Presentation transcript:

Roman Słowiński Poznań University of Technology, Poland Multiple-criteria ranking using an additive value function constructed via ordinal regresion : UTA method Roman Słowiński Poznań University of Technology, Poland  Roman Słowiński

Problem statement g2(x) g2max A g2min g1(x) g1min g1max Consider a finite set A of actions (actions, solutions, objects) evaluated by m criteria from a consistent family F={g1,...,gm} Let I={1,…,m} g2max g1(x) g2(x) g2min g1min g1max A

What is a consistent family of criteria ? A family of criteria F={g1,...,gn} is consistent if it is: Complete – if two actions have the same evaluations on all criteria, then they have to be indifferent, i.e. if for any a,bA, there is gi(a)~gi(b), iI, then a~b Monotonic – if action a is preferred to action b (ab), and there is action c, such that gi(c)gi(a), iI, then cb Non-redundant – elimination of any criterion from the family F should violate at least one of the above properties

Problem statement Taking into account preferences of a Decision Maker (DM), rank all the actions of set A from the best to the worst A * x * * x x x x x * * x

Dominance relation g2(x) g2max A g2min g1(x) g1min g1max Action aA is non-dominated (Pareto-optimal) if and only if there is no other action bA such that gi(b)gi(a), iI, and on at least one criterion jI, gi(b)gi(a) g2max g1(x) g2(x) g2min g1min g1max A ideal nadir

Criteria aggregation model = preference model Dominance relation is too poor – it leaves many actions non-comparable One can „enrich” the dominance relation, using preference information elicited from the Decision Maker Preference information permits to built a preference model that aggregates the vector evaluations of elements of A

Why traditional MCDM methods may confuse their users ? Traditional MCDM methods require a rich and difficult preference information: many intracriteria and intercriteria parameters: thresholds, weights, … complete set of pairwise comparisons of actions on each criterion complete set of pairwise comparisons of criteria … They suppose the DM understands the logic of a particular aggregation model: meaning of weights: substitution ratios or relative strengths meaning of lotteries (ASSESS) meaning of indifference, preference and veto thresholds (ELECTRE) meaning of the ratio scale of the intensity of preference (AHP) meaning of „neutral” and „good” levels on particular criteria (MACBETH)

Towards „easy” preference information Traditional methods appear to be too demanding of cognitive effort of their users This is why we advocate for methods requiring „easy” preference information „Easy” means natural and even partial Psychologists confirm that DMs are more confident exercising their decisions than explaining them

Towards „easy” preference information The most natural is a holistic pairwise comparison of some actions relatively well known to the DM, i.e. reference actions A

Towards „easy” preference information The most natural is a holistic pairwise comparison of some actions relatively well known to the DM, i.e. reference actions x  y z  w x  w y  v u  t z  u u  z holistic preference information A AR x t z w v y u DM

Towards „easy” preference information Question: what is the consequence of using on the whole set A this information transformed to a compatible preference model ? A AR x t z w v y u DM x  y z  w x  w y  v u  t z  u u  z preference information analyst Preference model compatible with preference information Apply the preference model on A What ranking will result ?

Aggregation paradigms Disaggregation-aggregation (or regression) paradigm: The holistic preference on a subset ARA is known first, and then a compatible criteria aggregation model (compatible preference model) is inferred from this information to be applied on set A Traditional aggregation paradigm: The criteria aggregation model (preference model) is first constructed and then applied on set A to get information about holistic preference

Aggregation paradigms The disaggregation-aggregation paradigam has been introduced to MCDS by Jacquet-Lagreze & Siskos (1982) in the UTA method: the inferred criteria aggregation model is the additive value function with piecewise-linear marginal value functions The disaggregation-aggregation paradigam is consistent with the „posterior rationality” principle by March (1988) and „learning from examples” used in AI and knowledge discovery Other aggregation models inferred in this way: Fishburn (1967) – trade-off weights Mousseau & Słowiński (1998) – outranking relation (ELECTRE TRI) Greco, Matarazzo & Słowiński (1999) – decision rules or trees (DRSA – Dominance-based Rough Set Approach) We propose a methodology of fuzzy rough approximation that infers the most cautious conclusion from available imprecise information.

Basic concepts and notation Gi – domain of criterion gi (Gi is finite or countably infinte) – evaluation space x,yG – profiles of actions in evaluation space  – weak preference (outranking) relation on G: for each x,yG xy  „x is at least as good as y” xy  [xy and not yx]  „x is preferred to y” x~y  [xy and yx]  „x is indifferent to y”

Reminder of the UTA method (Jacquet-Lagreze & Siskos, 1982) For simplicity: Gi , iI, where I={1,…,m} For each gi, Gi=[i, i] is the criterion evaluation scale, i  i , where i and i, are the worst and the best (finite) evaluations, resp. Thus, A is a finite subset of G and Additive value (or utility) function on G: for each xG where ui are non-decreasing marginal value functions, ui : Gi  , iI

Principle of the ordinal regression - UTA (Jacquet-Lagreze & Siskos, 1982) The preference information is given in form of a complete preorder on a subset of reference actions ARA, AR={x1,x2,...,xn} – the reference actions are rearranged such that xk  xk+1 , k=1,...,n-1 x1  x2 x5 x6x7 x3x4 A AR

Principle of the ordinal regression Example: Let AR={a1, a2, a3}, G={Gain_1, Gain_2} Evaluation of reference actions on criteria Gain_1, Gain_2: Reference ranking: Gain_1 Gain_2 a1 4 6 a2 5 a3 a1  a2 a3

Principle of the ordinal regression

Principle of the ordinal regression

Principle of the ordinal regression Let’s change the reference ranking: One linear piece per each marginal value function u1, u2 is not enough a1  a2 a3 a1  a3 a2 Gain_1 Gain_2 a1 4 6 a2 5 a3 u1=k1Gain_1, u2=k2Gain_2, U=u1+u2 For a1a3, k2>k1, but for a3a2, k1>k2, thus, marginal value functions cannot be linear

Principle of the ordinal regression

Principle of the UTA method (Jacquet-Lagreze & Siskos, 1982) The comprehensive preference information is given in form of a complete preorder on a subset of reference actions ARA, AR={x1,x2,...,xn} – the reference actions are rearranged such that xk  xk+1 , k=1,...,n-1 The inferred value of each reference action xAR where + and - are potential errors of over- and under-estimation of the right value, resp. The intervals [i, i] are divided into i equal sub-intervals with the end points (iI)

Principle of the ordinal regression In the UTA method, the marginal value of action xA is approximated by linear interpolation: for

UTA additive preference model

Principle of the UTA method Ordinal regression principle for xk  xk+1 , k=1,...,n-1 Monotonicity of preferences Normalization

Principle of the UTA method The marginal value functions (breakpoint variables) are estimated by solving the LP problem where  is a small positive constant (C) k=1,...,n-1

Principle of the UTA method If EUTA*=0, then the polyhedron of feasible solutions for ui(xi) is not empty and there exists at least one value function U[g(x)] compatible with the complete preorder on AR If EUTA*>0, then there is no value function U[g(x)] compatible with the complete preorder on AR – three possible moves: increasing the number of linear pieces i for ui(xi) revision of the complete preorder on AR post-optimal search for the best function with respect to Kendall’s  in the area EUTA  EUTA*+  Jacquet-Lagreze & Siskos (1982) EUTA EUTA*+ polyhedron of constraints (C) EUTA= EUTA*

Współczynnik Kendalla Do wyznaczania odległości między preporządkami stosuje się miarę Kendalla Przyjmijmy, że mamy dwie macierze kwadratowe R i R* o rozmiarze m  m, gdzie m = |AR|, czyli m jest liczbą wariantów referencyjnych macierz R jest związana z porządkiem referencyjnym podanym przez decydenta, macierz R* jest związana z porządkiem dokonanym przez funkcję użyteczności wyznaczoną z zadania PL (zadania regresji porządkowej) Każdy element macierzy R, czyli rij (i, j=1,..,m), może przyjmować wartości: To samo dotyczy elementów macierzy R* Tak więc w każdej z tych macierzy kodujemy pozycję (w porządku) wariantu a względem wariantu b

Współczynnik Kendalla Następnie oblicza się współczynnik Kendalla : gdzie dk(R,R*) jest odległością Kendalla między macierzami R i R*: Stąd   -1, 1 Jeżeli  = -1, to oznacza to, że porządki zakodowane w macierzach R i R* są zupełnie odwrotne, np. macierz R koduje porządek a  b  c  d, a macierz R* porządek d  c  b  a Jeżeli  = 1, to zachodzi całkowita zgodność porządków z obydwu macierzy. W tej sytuacji błąd estymacji funkcji użyteczności F*=0 W praktyce funkcję użyteczności akceptuje się, gdy   0.75

Example of UTA+ Ranking of 6 means of transportation 1 2

Preference attitude: „economical”

Preference attitude: „hurry”

Preference attitude: „hurry”

One should use all compatible preference models on set A Question: what is the consequence of using all compatible preference models on set A ? A AR x t z w v y u DM x  y z  w y  v u  t z  u u  z preference information analyst All instances of preference model compatible with preference information Apply all compatible instances on A What rankings will result ?

Two rankings result: necessary and possible x y w z t u v necessary ranking possible ranking Includes necessary ranking and does not include the complement of necessary ranking x  y z  w y  v u  t z  u u  z preference information

Two rankings result: necessary and possible – effect of additional preference information „trial-and-error” interactions x y w z t u v necessary ranking enriched x  y z  w y  v u  t z  u u  z x  w additional preference information possible ranking impoverished Includes necessary ranking and does not include the complement of necessary ranking In the absence of any preference information: necessary ranking boils down to weak dominance relation possible ranking is a complete relation For complete pairwise comparisons (complete preorder in A): necessary ranking = possible ranking

The UTAGMS method (Greco, Mousseau & Słowiński 2004) The preference information is a partial preorder  on a subset of reference actions ARA A value function is called compatible if it is able to restore the partial preorder  reference actions from AR Each compatible value function induces a ranking on set A In result, one obtains two rankings on set A, such that for any pair of actions (x,y)A: x N y: x is ranked at least as good as y iff U(x)U(y) for all value functions compatible with the preference information (necessary weak preference relation N - a partial preorder on A) x P y: x is ranked at least as good as y iff U(x)U(y) for at least one value function compatible with the preference information (possible weak preference relation P - a strongly complete and negatively transitive binary relation on A)

The UTAGMS method (Greco, Mousseau & Słowiński 2004) The marginal value function ui(xi) ui(xi) gi i yi i wi zi vi y,v,w,zAR Characteristic points of marginal value functions are fixed on actual evaluations of actions from set A

The UTAGMS method (Greco, Mousseau & Słowiński 2004) The marginal value function ui(xi) ui(xi) gi i yi i wi zi vi ? y,v,w,zAR Marginal values in characteristic points are unknown

The UTAGMS method (Greco, Mousseau & Słowiński 2004) The marginal value function ui(xi) ui(xi) gi i yi i wi zi vi y,v,w,zAR In fact, they are intervals, because all compatible value functions are considered

The UTAGMS method (Greco, Mousseau & Słowiński 2004) The marginal value function ui(xi) ui(xi) gi i yi i wi zi vi y,v,w,zAR The area of all compatible marginal value functions

The UTAGMS method (Greco, Mousseau & Słowiński 2004) The marginal value function ui(xi) ui(xi) gi i yi i wi zi vi y,v,w,zAR In the area the marginal compatible value functions must be monotone

The UTAGMS method (Greco, Mousseau & Słowiński 2004) The marginal value function ui(xi) This means that the ordinal regression should not seek for m piecewise-linear marginal value functions, but for any compatible additive value function ui(xi) gi i yi i wi zi vi

The UTAGMS method Let i be a permutation on the set of actions AR{x,y} that reorders them according to increasing evaluation on criterion gi: where if AR{x,y}=, then =n+2 if AR{x,y}={x} or AR{x,y}={y}, then =n+1 if AR{x,y}={x,y}, then =n The characteristic points of ui(xi), iI, are then fixen in:

The UTAGMS method For any pair of actions (x,y)A, and for available preference information concerning AR, preference of x over y is determined by compatible value functions U verifying set E(x,y) of constraints: where  is a small positive constant For all (x,y)A, E(x,y) = E(y,x)  a,bAR E(x,y) a b

The UTAGMS method N means necessary (strong) preference relation Given a pair of actions x,yA xNy  d(x,y)  0 where d(x,y)  0 means that for all compatible value functions x is at least as good as y For x,yAR : xy  xNy

The UTAGMS method P means possible (weak) preference relation Given a pair of actions x,yA xPy  D(x,y)  0 where D(x,y)  0 means that for at least one compatible value function x is at least as good as y For x,yAR : xy  not yPx

The UTAGMS method Some properties: xNy  xPy N is a partial preorder (i.e. N is reflexive and transitive) P is strongly complete (i.e. for all x,yA, xPy or yPx) and negatively transitive (i.e. for all x,y,zA, not xPy and not yPz  not xPz ), (in general, P is not transitive) d(x,y) = Min{U(x)–U(y)} = –Max{–[U(x)–U(y)]} = = –Max{U(y)–U(x)} = –D(y,x) Strong goes with d (min) Weak goes with D (max)

Proof of transitivity of N d(x,y)>0 means: Min{U(x)-U(y)}>0 This is equivalent to the fact: for all value functions compatible with the reference preorder, U(x)>U(y) The set of all compatible value functions is the same for calculation of d(x,y) for any pair x,yA Suppose, the transitivity of N is not true, i.e. for x,y,zA Min{U(x)-U(y)}>0, Min{U(y)-U(z)}>0, but Min{U(x)-U(z)}<0 This means that U(x)-U(z) has achieved a minimum value d(x,z)<0 for a value function denoted by U*, such that U*(x)<U*(z), while U*(x)>U*(y) and U*(y)>U*(z) In other words, U*(x)>U*(y)>U*(z)>U*(x) This is a contradiction, so N is transitive

The UTAGMS method Elaboration of the final ranking: for the necessary preference relation being a partial preorder (N is supported by all compatible value functions) preference: xNy if xNy and not yNx indifference: xNy if xNy and yNx incomparability: x ? y if not xNy and not yNx for the possible preference relation being complete (P is supported by at least one compatible value function) preference: xPy if xPy and not yPx indifference: xPy if xPy and yPx N.B. It is impossible to infer one ranking from another because strong and weak outranking relations are not dual

The UTAGMS method – final ranking (partial preorder) Final ranking corresponding to necessary (strong) preference : N

The UTAGMS method – final ranking (complete preorder) Final ranking corresponding to possible (weak) preference : P

Example of UTAGMS Ranking of 6 means of transportation 1 2

„hurry” D(x,y)

„hurry” „economical”

Nested ranking with different credibility levels Reference rankings in growing sets: with credibility levels ordered decreasingly The reference ranking of alternatives from ARi does not change in ARi+1, i=1,…,p-1 Each time we pass from ARi to ARi+1, we add to (E) new constraints concerning alternatives from {ARi+1\ ARi} If d(x,y)<0 in iteration i turns to d(x,y)>0 in iteration i+1, then we assign to xNy the credibility level corresponding to ranking i+1 In this way we get a set of nested partial preorders In fact, we get a fuzzy partial preorder N~ with respect to credibility: for all x,y,zA, Min{Cr(xN~y), Cr(yN~z)}  Cr(xN~z), thus N~ is min-transitive and reflexive

Software demonstration Bank

New reference action

New reference ranking

High credibility ranking embedded in low credibility ranking Partial preorder graph (strong outranking)

GRIP – Generalized Regression with Intensities of Preference GRIP – Generalized Regression with Intensities of Preference (Figueira, Greco, Słowiński 2006) GRIP extends the UTAGMS method by adopting all features of UTAGMS and by taking into account additional preference information : comprehensive comparisons of intensities of preference between some pairs of reference actions, e.g. „x is preferred to y at least as much as w is preferred to z” partial comparisons of intensities of preference between some pairs of reference actions on particular criteria, e.g. „x is preferred to y at least as much as w is preferred to z, on criterion giF”

GRIP – Generalized Regression with Intensities of Preference DM is supposed to provide the following preference information : a partial preorder  on AR, such that x,yAR x  y  „x is at least as good as y”  =   not -1,  =   -1 a partial preorder * on ARAR, such that x,y,w,zAR (x,y) * (w,z)  „x is preferred to y at least as much as w is preferred to z” * = *  not *-1, * = *  *-1 a partial preorder i* on ARAR, i=1,...,m, such that x,y,w,zAR (x,y) i* (w,z)  „x is preferred to y at least as much as w is preferred to z, on criterion giF”, i* = i*  not i*-1, i* = i*  i*-1

GRIP – new contraints of the ordinal regression LP problem A value function U : [0, 1] is called compatible if it satisfes the constraints corresponding to DM’s preference information: U(x)  U(y) iff x  y U(x) > U(y) iff x  y U(x) = U(y) iff x  y U(x) – U(y)  U(w) – U(z) iff (x,y) * (w,z) U(x) – U(y) > U(w) – U(z) iff (x,y) * (w,z) U(x) – U(y) = U(w) – U(z) iff (x,y) * (w,z) ui(x)  ui(y) iff x i y, iI ui(x) – ui(y)  ui(w) – ui(z) iff (x,y) i* (w,z), iI ui(x) – ui(y) > ui(w) – ui(z) iff (x,y) i* (w,z), iI ui(x) – ui(y) = ui(w) – ui(z) iff (x,y) i* (w,z), iI

GRIP – new contraints of the ordinal regression LP problem Moreover, the following normalization constraints should also be taken into account: ui(i)=0, iI

GRIP – new contraints of the ordinal regression LP problem If constraints a) – l) are consistent, then we get two weak preference relations N and P , and two binary relations comparing intensity of preference *N and *P : for all x,yA, a necessary weak preference relation, x N y: U(x)  U(y) for all compatible value functions for all x,yA, a possible weak preference relation, x P y: U(x)  U(y) for at least one compatible value function for all x,y,w,z A, a necessary relation of preference intensity, (x,y) *N (w,z): [U(x) – U(y)] – [U(w) – U(z)]  0 for all compatible value functions for all x,y,w,z A, a possible relation of preference intensity, (x,y) *P (w,z): [U(x) – U(y)] – [U(w) – U(z)]  0 for at least one compatible value function

GRIP – fundamental properties of N, P, *N, *P Theorem: If constaraints a) – l) are satisfied, then the properties hold: For all x,yA, x N y  x P y For all x,yAR, x  y  x N y N is a partial preorder (i.e. the relation is transitive and reflexive) and P is strongly complete and negatively transitive For all x,y,zA, [x N y and y P z]  x P z For all x,y,zA, [x P y and y N z]  x P z For all x,y,w,zA, (x,y) *N (w,z)  (x,y) *P (w,z) For all x,y,w,zA, (x,y) * (w,z)  (x,y) *N (w,z) *N is a partial preorder and *P is strongly complete and negatively transitive For all x,y,w,z,r,sA, [(x,y) *N (w,z) and (w,z) *P (r,s)] (x',y) *P (r,s) For all x,y,w,z,r,sA, [(x,y) *P (w,z) and (w,z) *N (r,s)] (x,y) *P (r,s) For all x,x’,y,w,zA, [x’ N x and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x’,y) *N (w,z) For all x,x’,y,w,zA, [x’ N x and (x,y) *P (w,z)] (x’,y) *P (w,z) For all x,x’,y,w,zA, [x’ P x and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x’,y) *P (w,z)

GRIP – fundamental properties of N, P, *N, *P For all x,y,y’,w,zA, [y N y’ and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x,y’) *N (w,z) For all x,y,y’,w,zA, [y N y’ and (x,y) *P (w,z)] (x,y’) *P (w,z) For all x,y,y’,w,zA, [y P y’ and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x,y’) *P (w,z) For all x,y,w,w’,zA, [w N w’ and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x,y) *N (w’,z) For all x,y,w,w’,zA, [w N w’ and (x,y) *P (w,z)] (x,y) *P (w’,z) For all x,y,w,w’,zA, [w P w’ and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x,y) *P (w’,z) For all x,y,w,z,z’A, [z’ N z and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x,y) *N (w,z’) For all x,y,w,z,z’A, [z’ N z and (x,y) *P (w,z)] (x,y) *P (w,z’) For all x,y,w,z,z’A, [z’ P z and (x,y) *N (w,z)] (x,y) *P (w,z’) For all x,x’,yA, (x’,y) *N (x,y)  x’ N x For all x,x’,yA, (x’,y) *P (x,y)  x’ P x For all x,y,y’A, (x,y) *N (x,y’)  y’ N y For all x,y,y’A, (x,y) *P (x,y’)  y’ P y 

GRIP – the linear programming problem In order to verify the truth or falsity of necessary and possible weak preference relations N, P and *N, *P, one can use LP LP does not permit strict inequalities, such as b), e), i) They must be rewritten as: b’) U(x)  U(y) +  e’) U(x) – U(y)  U(w) – U(z) +  i’) ui(x) – ui(y)  ui(w) – ui(z) +  where >0 (small value) In UTA and in UTAGMS the result is dependent on the value of  We want to make the result of GRIP independent of 

GRIP – the linear programming problem The following result will be useful (see e.g. Marichal & Roubens 2000): Proposition: x is a solution of the linear system, if there exists >0, such that In particular, a solution exists, iff the following LP has optimal solution (x*,*), where *>0. Then, x* is a solution of # # Max

GRIP – the linear programming problem According to the Proposition, if constraints b),e),i) are considered, in order to verify the truth or falsity of N and P , one should : Max   subject to constraints a)–l), with b),e),i) written as b’),e’),i’) If maximal *>0, the set of compatible value functions is not empty Then, to verify the truth or falsity of xPy, for any x,yA, one should : and U(x)  U(y) Maximal *>0  xPy This means that there exists at least one compatible value function satisfying the hypothesis U(x)  U(y)

GRIP – the linear programming problem In order to verify the truth or falsity of xNy, rather than to check directly that for each compatible value function U(x)  U(y), we make sure that among the compatible value functions there is no one such that U(x) < U(y) : Max   subject to constraints a)–l), with b),e),i) written as b’),e’),i’) and U(y)  U(x) +  Maximal *≤0  xNy

GRIP – the linear programming problem Analogously, if constraints b),e),i) are considered, in order to verify the truth or falsity of (x,y)*P(w,z) for any x,y,w,zA, one should : Max   subject to constraints a)–l), with b),e),i) written as b’),e’),i’) and U(x)U(y)  U(w)U(z) Maximal *>0  (x,y)*P(w,z) In order to verify the truth or falsity of (x,y)*N(w,z) for any x,y,w,zA, one should : and U(w)U(z)  U(x)U(y) +  Maximal *≤0  (x,y)*N(w,z) The value of * is not meaningful – the result does not depend on it!

Comparison of GRIP and MACBETH (Bana e Costa & Vansnick 1994) Ordinal comprehensive preference inf. on pairwise comparison of some reference actions: xy, x,yAR Absolute qualitative judgement of intensity of preference for some pairs of reference actions – partial and/or comprehensive (e.g. v_weak, weak, moderate,..., extreme intensity of preference for (x,y)) OR Comparison of intensities of preference for some pairs of reference actions – partial and/or comprehens.: (x,y)i(w,z) and/or (x,y)(w,z) MACBETH Ordinal preference inf. w.r.t. each criterion for all not equally attractive pairs of actions: xiy or yix, x,yA Definition of „neutral” and „good” level on original scales of criteria Absolute qualitative judgement of differences of attractiveness for all not equally attractive pairs of actions w.r.t. each criterion, including „good” and „neutral” points (e.g. v_weak, weak, moderate,..., extreme int.pref. for (x,y)) Ordinal preference inf. for all not equally attractive criteria: gigj or gjgi equally attractive pairs of criteria (e.g. v_weak, weak, moderate,..., extreme intensity of preference for (gi,gj)) Preference information

Comparison of GRIP and MACBETH cont. Uses LP to identify a set of comprehensive additive value functions with interval scales, compatible with preference info. Builds necessary and possible weak preference relations on set A: N (partial preorder) P (strongly complete) weak preference relations on set AA: *N (partial preorder) *P (strongly complete) MACBETH Uses LP to build a single interval scale for each criterion, compatible with preference info., and computes a numerical marginal value for each action on each criterion Computes a weight for each criterion Builds a weighted sum model on marginal values which is additive piecewise linear or discrete Uses the model to set up a complete preorder on set A Preference model and final results

Comparison of GRIP and MACBETH (Bana e Costa & Vansnick 1994) Summary of crucial differences in the methodology: GRIP is using comprehensive and partial preference information on some pairs of actions MACBETH requires partial preference information on all pairs of actions Information about partial intensity of preference is of the same nature in GRIP and MACBETH (equivalence classes of relation i* correspond to qualitative judgements of MACBETH), but in GRIP it may not be complete GRIP represents „disaggregation-aggregation” approach MACBETH uses „aggregation” approach – needs weights to aggregate scales on particular criteria GRIP works with all compatible value functions, while MACBETH builds a single interval scale for each criterion, even if many such scales would be compatible with preference information

Other features of GRIP GRIP can be used interactively: In the absence of any preference information, N, *N boil down to weak dominance relation Each pairwise comparison  or each comparison of intensities of preference *, contributes to enrich N or *N In the absence of any preference information, P, *P is a complete relation Each pairwise comparison  or each comparison of intensities of preference *, contributes to impoverish P or *P For complete pairwise comparisons and comparisons of intensities: N = P and *N = *P GRIP permits to make preference intensity dependent on the part of criterion scale in which a difference of performances takes place, e.g. (17.000; 19.000) price (27.000; 30.000)

GRIP – illustrative example Car ranking problem Criteria: Intensity of preference:

GRIP – illustrative example Performance matrix Skoda Opel Ford Citroen Seat VW Price Speed Space Fuel_cons. Acceleration

GRIP – illustrative example Preference information Monotonicity must be respected for each criterion, e.g. if Speed(x)  Speed(y), then value[Speed(x)]  value[Speed(y)] In the ordinal regression LP problem, monotonicity is expressed by g) In Tables 2-6, we skip preference labels  and  that result from simple monotonicity, i.e. gi(x)=gi(y) or gi(x)gi(y), respectively

GRIP – illustrative example Partial information about preference intensity serves to define constraints h) and j) representing partial preorder i*

GRIP – illustrative example Comprehensive information about preference intensity serves to define constraints a) and c) representing partial preorder * (F) Skoda Opel Ford Citroen Seat VW

GRIP – illustrative example Calculation of D(x,y)=Max{U(x)–U(y)} Since all values are  0, for all pairs (x,y) of cars there exist at least one compatible value function for which x is at least as good as y Therefore, possible weak preference relation P  AA, so P brings no interesting information because all weak preferences are possible

GRIP – illustrative example Calculation of d(x,y)=Min{U(x)–U(y)} As Min{U(x)–U(y)}=–Max{U(y)–U(y)}, then d(x,y)=–D(y,x) All values  0 correspond to pairs (x,y) of cars for which all compatible value functions are in favor of x over y

GRIP – illustrative example Graph of necessary weak preference relation N

Conclusions In GRIP, preference information is given by the DM in terms of: partial preorder in the set of reference actions partial and comprehensive comparisons of intensities of preference between some pairs of reference actions, The preference information is used within regression approach to build a complete set of compatible additive value functions Considering all compatible value functions permits to find as result: necessary w.pref. relation in A and in AA (partial preorder) N, *N possible w.pref. relation in A and in AA (strongly complete) P, *P Possible extensions: preference information with gradual credibility group decision