The pleasure principle: later developments

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Utilitarianism Maximize good.
Advertisements

Higher RMPS Lesson 6 Area 2 Examples.
The pleasure principle: later developments. Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900)
RECAP – TASK 1 What is utilitarianism? Who is Jeremy Bentham?
Utilitarianism.
Utilitarianism Jon Mayled.
Secular Responses Use of the Embryo. Utilitarianism Based on the idea of the greatest happiness for the greatest number or majority Also based on hedonism.
Utilitarianism Guiding Principle 5.
Chapter Seven: Utilitarianism
Standards of Conduct DoD’s Standards of Conduct
ETHICS BOWL CONSEQUENTIALism.
UTILITARIANISM: A comparison of Bentham and Mill’s versions
Ethical Theories: Deontology and Teleology
Utilitarian Approach. Utilitarianism The founder of classical utilitarianism is Jeremy Bentham. According to Bentham human beings always try to avoid.
THEORIES OF ETHICS PART 2 OF CHAPTER 12 (ETHICS).
 The benefits of embryo research come mainly from stem cell usage  it is hoped that stem cells can be stimulated to develop any tissue or organ of the.
Utilitarianism or Consequentialism Good actions are those that result in good consequences. The moral value of an action is extrinsic to the action itself.
Ethics A look at the reasons behind decisions about what is right and wrong. What is the right thing to do?
Consequentialism Is it OK to inflict pain on someone else? Is it OK to inflict pain on someone else? What if it is a small amount of pain to prevent a.
PEP 570, DeGeorge, Chp. 3 10/28/20151 Chapter Three: Dr. DeGeorge Utilitarianism: Justice and Love.
Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism Learning Objectives:- (long term) 1. To understand the ‘greatest happiness principle’. 2. To understand the similarities.
"Philosophers should consider the fact that the greatest happiness principle can easily be made an excuse for a benevolent dictatorship. We should replace.
AREA 1 GUIDING PRINCIPLES SECTION 3 Consequences (Utilitarian Ethics) Duty and Reason (Kantian Ethics)
Utilitarianism is a theory about what we ought to do. It states that we should always choose actions which produce the greatest amount of happiness for.
‘UTILITARIANISM FROM BENTHAM & MILL’ THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES
Morality in the Modern World
Ethics A look at the reasons behind decisions about what is right and wrong. What is the right thing to do?
Consequentialism (utilitarism). General description 'Consequentialist theories regard the moral value of actions, rules of conduct, and so on, as dependent.
Preference Utilitarianism. Learning Objectives By the end of this lesson, we will have... Consolidated our knowledge of Act and Rule Utilitarianism by.
Utilitarianism. Learning Objectives:- (long term) 1. To understand the ‘greatest happiness principle’. 2. To understand the similarities and differences.
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
Chapter 2: Readings in Moral Theory Jeremy Bentham, “The Principle of Utility” – Consequentialism: the rightness or wrongness of an action depends entirely.
 Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill  Reason not Revelation  Consequentialism – good or bad, right or wrong, are based on outcomes.
Ethical theories and approaches in Business
Utilitarianism Learning outcome:
KANT Kant was looking for some sort of objective basis for morality – a way of knowing our duty.
Utilitarianism.
Rule Utilitarianism To understand later developments in Utilitarianism and the works of Mill and Singer.
Preference Utilitarianism
What is the difference between these two situations?
Utilitarianism Learning Intention:
John Stuart Mill.
Lesson 5- Ideal and negative utilitarianism
Natural Law – Bernard Hoose’s Proportionalism
ETHICS BOWL CONSEQUENTIALism.
Utilitarianism: Modern Applications of the theory
Utilitarianism - Introduction
On whiteboards… Write down everything a brief summary of ethical naturalism, including criticisms.
Utilitarianism: John Stuart Mill
Theory of Health Care Ethics
Mill and Bentham’s Utilitarianism
Natural Law – Bernard Hoose’s Proportionalism
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 15 Ethics #1: Utilitarianism
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Bentham’s Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism 2.0.
Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham.
01 4 Ethical Language 4.1 Meta-Ethics.
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Outline the naturalistic fallacy
Utilitarianism – Bentham’s Classic Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism Consequential, i.e. Utilitarianism – a good moral decision is that which the consequences of the action produces the greatest good for the.
Moral Theories: Utilitarianism
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Intuitionism Explore and Evaluate the strengths and problems of Intuitionism as ethical language.
Ethical concepts and ethical theories Topic 3
Utilitarianism – Bentham’s Classic Utilitarianism
Professional Ethics (GEN301/PHI200) UNIT 2: NORMATIVE THEORIES OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS Handout # 2 CLO # 2 Explain the rationale behind adoption of normative.
Utilitarianism.
Presentation transcript:

The pleasure principle: later developments

Utilitarianism: key scholars Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900) G. E. Moore (1873–1958) Karl Popper (1902–1994) Richard Brandt (1910–1997) R. M. Hare (1919–2002) Peter Singer (1946–)

Utilitarianism: key terms Act utilitarianism Consequentialist Hedonic calculus Hedonism Ideal Utilitarianism Interest Utilitarianism Negative Utilitarianism Preference utilitarianism Principle of utility Qualitative Quantitative Rule utilitarianism Teleological Universalisability

Henry Sidgwick (1) Sidgwick argues that the balance of pleasure over pain is the ultimate goal of ethical decisions. His argument is closer to Bentham than to Mill, as he questions how it is possible to distinguish between higher and lower order pleasures, and how we can distinguish one higher order pleasure from another. However, Sidgwick does argue that the process of deciding is intuitive — we make self-evident judgements about what we ought to do.

Henry Sidgwick (2) He argued that justice is the similar and injustice the dissimilar treatment of similar cases: ‘whatever action any of us judges to be right for himself, he implicitly judges to be right for all similar persons in similar circumstances.’ So it is wrong for person A to treat person B in a way in which it would be wrong for B to treat A, simply on the grounds that they are two different individuals and without there being any difference in their circumstances or their natures. Saying that people must act according to just laws raises the issue of which laws are just and sits uncomfortably with the principle of utility and the act utilitarian position.

Ideal utilitarianism A utilitarian theory that denies that the sole object of moral concern is the maximising of pleasure or happiness. In G. E. Moore’s version of ideal utilitarianism in Principia Ethica (1903), it is aesthetic experiences and relations of friendship that have intrinsic value, and therefore ought to be sought and promoted. Consciousness of pain, hatred or contempt of what is good or beautiful, and the love, admiration or enjoyment of what is evil or ugly are the three things that have intrinsic disvalue and should therefore be shunned and prevented. It was Hastings Rashdall (1858–1924) in The Theory of Good and Evil (1907) who first used ‘ideal utilitarianism’ for non-hedonistic utilitarianism of this kind.

Negative utilitarianism (1) The term negative utilitarianism was coined by Sir Karl Popper. The concept of negative utilitarianism was foreshadowed earlier, e.g. in the work of Edmund Gurney (1847–88). It has obvious affinity with Buddhism. However, it has been argued that negative utilitarianism could lead to mass euthanasia, although this implication has been disputed. Popper’s ‘negative utilitarian’ principle is that we should act to minimise suffering rather than maximise pleasure. Classical utilitarian philosophers such as Sidgwick had explicitly argued for the moral symmetry of happiness and suffering. Complications aside, they supposed that increases in happiness, and reductions in suffering, are essentially of equal value when of equal magnitude.

Negative utilitarianism (2) Popper disagreed. He believed that the practical consequences of the supposed moral symmetry were also dangerous: ‘Philosophers should consider the fact that the greatest happiness principle can easily be made an excuse for a benevolent dictatorship. We should replace it by a more modest and more realistic principle: the principle that the fight against avoidable misery should be a recognized aim of public policy, while the increase of happiness should be left, in the main, to private initiative.’

Negative utilitarianism (3) ‘I believe that there is, from the ethical point of view, no symmetry between suffering and happiness, or between pain and pleasure. Both the greatest happiness principle of the Utilitarians and Kant’s principle, promote other people’s happiness…[and] seem to me (at least in their formulations) fundamentally wrong in this point, which is, however, not one for rational argument… In my opinion…human suffering makes a direct moral appeal for help, while there is no similar call to increase the happiness of a man who is doing well anyway.’ Popper, K. (1952) The Open Society and Its Enemies

Negative utilitarianism (4) Popper believed that by acting to minimise suffering, we avoid the terrible risks of ‘utopianism’, by which he had in mind the communist and fascist dictatorships of the twentieth century. ‘Those who promise us paradise on earth never produced anything but a hell.’ A staunch advocate of the ‘open society’, Popper defended ‘piecemeal social engineering’ rather than grandiose state planning.

Negative utilitarianism (5) Ironically, the full realisation of a negative utilitarian ethic depends inescapably on the ‘utopian’ planning that Popper abhorred. Only a global bio-engineering project of unparalleled ambition could bring about the eradication of suffering throughout the living world — not piecemeal social engineering. In seeking to liberate the world from the tyranny of pain, negative utilitarianism is no less ‘totalitarian’ in its policy implications than communism or fascism, albeit vastly more compassionate.

Preference utilitarianism An act utilitarian judges right or wrong according to the maximising of pleasure and minimising of pain. A rule utilitarian judges right or wrong according to the keeping of rules derived from utility. A preference (or interest) utilitarian judges moral actions according to whether they fit in with the preferences of the individuals involved. This approach to utilitarianism asks: ‘What is in my own interest? What would I prefer in this situation? Which outcome would I prefer?’ However, because utilitarianism aims to create the greatest good for the greatest number, it is necessary to consider the preferences of others in order to achieve this.

R. M. Hare Hare argues that in moral decision making we need to consider our own preferences and those of others: ‘equal preferences count equally, whatever their content.’ People are happy when they get what they prefer but this may clash with the preferences of others. Hare says we need to ‘stand in someone else’s shoes’ and try to imagine what someone else might prefer. We should treat everyone, including ourselves, with impartiality — he also argues for universalisability.

Peter Singer Singer suggests that people should take the viewpoint of an impartial spectator combined with a broadly utilitarian approach. ‘Our own preferences cannot count any more than the preferences of others’ and so, in acting morally, we should take account of all the people affected by our actions. For Singer, the ‘best possible consequences’ means what is in the best interests of the individuals concerned. He is not considering what increases pleasure and diminishes pain. This principle of equal consideration of preferences or interests acts like a pair of scales — everyone’s preferences or interests are weighed equally.

Richard Brandt Richard Brandt talks about the preferences someone would have if they had gone through a process of cognitive psychotherapy and explored all the reasons for their preferences and rejected any they felt were not true to their real values. He argued that the morality someone would then accept would be a form of utilitarianism — with their preferences free from any psychological blocks and them in full possession of all the facts. Such a person would not, therefore, be influenced by advertising.

Strengths of utilitarianism It is straightforward and based on the single principle of minimising pain and maximising pleasure and happiness. It relates to actions that can be observed in the real world. Its consequentialism is also a strength, as when we act it is only natural to weigh up the consequences. Utilitarianism’s acceptance of the universal principle is essential for any ethical system. The idea of promoting the ‘well-being’ of the greatest number is also important. Preference utilitarianism also gives the valuable principle of being an impartial observer. It is important to think about others’ interests or preferences as long as one also includes behaving justly.

Weaknesses of utilitarianism (1) It is good to consider the consequences of our actions, but these are difficult to predict with any accuracy. Utilitarianism can also be criticised because it seems to ignore the importance of duty. An act may be right or wrong for reasons other than the amount of good or evil it produces. Utilitarianism can also advocate injustice. Another weakness is the emphasis on pleasure or happiness. If I seek my own happiness it is impossible for me to seek general happiness and to do what I ought to do.

Weaknesses of utilitarianism (2) The qualitative and quantitative approaches pose problems, as all we can really do is guess the units of pleasure — how do we measure one pleasure against another? Utilitarianism does not consider motives and intentions and so rejects the principle of treating people with intrinsic value. Utilitarianism can be seen as too impersonal and does not consider the rights of individuals in its attempt to look for the ‘greater good’.