Diagramming Universal-Particular arguments

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Venn Diagram Technique for testing syllogisms
Advertisements

Test the validity of this argument: Some lawyers are judges. Some judges are politicians. Therefore, some lawyers are politicians. A. Valid B. Invalid.
Part 2 Module 3 Arguments and deductive reasoning Logic is a formal study of the process of reasoning, or using common sense. Deductive reasoning involves.
Part 2 Module 5 Analyzing premises, forming conclusions
Test the validity of this argument: Some lawyers are judges. Some judges are politicians. Therefore, some lawyers are politicians. A. Valid B. Invalid.
1 Valid and Invalid arguments. 2 Definition of Argument Sequence of statements: Statement 1; Statement 2; Therefore, Statement 3. Statements 1 and 2 are.
An overview Lecture prepared for MODULE-13 (Western Logic) BY- MINAKSHI PRAMANICK Guest Lecturer, Dept. Of Philosophy.
Deductive Arguments: Categorical Logic
1 Philosophy 1100 Title:Critical Reasoning Instructor:Paul Dickey Website:
Part 2 Module 3 Arguments and deductive reasoning Logic is a formal study of the process of reasoning, or using common sense. Deductive reasoning involves.
Philosophy 1100 Today: Hand Back “Nail that Claim” Exercise! & Discuss
Clarke, R. J (2001) L951-08: 1 Critical Issues in Information Systems BUSS 951 Seminar 8 Arguments.
Statements and Quantifiers
Chapter 16: Venn Diagrams. Venn Diagrams (pp ) Venn diagrams represent the relationships between classes of objects by way of the relationships.
Logic In Part 2 Modules 1 through 5, our topic is symbolic logic. We will be studying the basic elements and forms that provide the structural foundations.
Introduction to Venn Diagrams SP This is a Venn diagram for two terms. We can conceive of every element of S as being within the boundary of the S circle.
Part 2 Module 3 Arguments and deductive reasoning Logic is a formal study of the process of reasoning, or using common sense. Deductive reasoning involves.
Testing Validity With Venn Diagrams
Philosophy 148 Chapter 7. AffirmativeNegative UniversalA: All S are PE: No S is P ParticularI: Some S is PO: Some S is not P.
Venn Diagrams and Categorical Syllogisms
Chapter 3 Introduction to Logic © 2008 Pearson Addison-Wesley. All rights reserved.
Determining Validity and Invalidity in Deductive Arguments PHIL 121: Methods of Reasoning February 6, 2013 Instructor:Karin Howe Binghamton University.
4 Categorical Propositions
MLS 570 Critical Thinking Reading Notes for Fogelin: Categorical Syllogisms We will go over diagramming Arguments in class. Fall Term 2006 North Central.
CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS
Diagramming Universal-Particular arguments The simplest style of nontrivial argument is called a Universal-Particular argument. Earlier in Part 2 Module.
Chapter 17: Missing Premises and Conclusions. Enthymemes (p. 168) An enthymeme is an argument with an unstated premise or conclusion. There are systematic.
Invitation to Critical Thinking Chapter 6
Chapter 6 Evaluating Deductive Arguments 1: Categorical Logic Invitation to Critical Thinking First Canadian Edition.
Critical Thinking: A User’s Manual
McGraw-Hill ©2004 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Testing Validity With Venn Diagrams The aim of this tutorial is to help you learn.
Venn Diagram Technique for testing syllogisms
Chapter 2 Sets and Functions.
Deductive reasoning.
Valid and Invalid Arguments
VENNS DIAGRAM METHOD FOR TESTING CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISM
Unions and Intersections of Sets
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Venn Diagrams and Set Operation
Testing Validity With Venn Diagrams
Testing for Validity with Venn Diagrams
Disjunctive Syllogism
Chapter 3 The Real Numbers.
5 Categorical Syllogisms
Venn Diagrams 1= s that are not p; 2= s that are p; 3= p that are not s S P.
Today’s Topics Introduction to Predicate Logic Venn Diagrams
5.1 Standard Form, Mood, and Figure
5 Categorical Syllogisms
Chapter 3 Philosophy: Questions and theories
Logic In Part 2 Modules 1 through 5, our topic is symbolic logic.
Rules and fallacies Formal fallacies.
3 Logic The Study of What’s True or False or Somewhere in Between.
4.1 The Components of Categorical Propositions
The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
Philosophy 1100 Class #8 Title: Critical Reasoning
A Universal-Particular (U-P) argument
Philosophy 1100 Title: Critical Reasoning Instructor: Paul Dickey
Logical Forms.
Propositional Logic.
Chapter 3 Introduction to Logic 2012 Pearson Education, Inc.
Chapter 6 Categorical Syllogisms
Reason and Argument Chapter 7 (2/2).
TRUTH TABLES.
6.4 Truth Tables for Arguments
Chapter 3 Introduction to Logic © 2008 Pearson Addison-Wesley.
ID1050– Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning
Evaluating Deductive Arguments
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Validity and Soundness, Again
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Presentation transcript:

Diagramming Universal-Particular arguments The simplest style of nontrivial argument is called a Universal-Particular argument. These arguments can be analyzed by diagramming (they can also be dealt with by referencing common forms). A Universal-Particular argument is a two-premise argument in which one premise is a universal proposition (“All are…,” “None are…”), while the other premise, and the conclusion, are propositions that relate a particular individual to the categories in the universal premise. The universal premise will also be referred to as the major premise. The particular premise will also be referred to as the minor premise.

Examples of Universal-Particular arguments All cats have rodent breath. Whiskers doesn't have rodent breath. Thus, Whiskers isn't a cat. Gomer is not a rascal. No rascals are reliable. Therefore, Gomer is reliable.

Diagramming One way to test the validity of a Universal-Particular argument is to use a method based upon the diagramming techniques that were introduced in Part 2 Module 1 (a synopsis is presented toward the end of this slide show). In a nutshell, the method works like this. On a two-circle Venn diagram, make the appropriate markings to convey the information from the universal premise and the particular premise, in that order. If the marked diagram then shows that the conclusion is true, then the argument is valid. If the marked diagram shows that the conclusion is false or uncertain, then the argument is invalid. A more detailed explanation follows..

Diagramming a U-P argument To test the validity of a U-P argument, follow these steps. 1. First, mark the diagram according to the content of the universal premise. If the universal premise is positive, we will “shade out” a crescent-shaped region. If the universal premise is negative, we will “shade out” a football-shaped region. The shading shows that a region must have no elements. 2. Next, place a “X” on the diagram according to the content of the particular statement, bearing in mind the meaning of the shading already on the diagram. (The “X” represents the particular individual who is the subject of the argument.) If it is uncertain which of two regions should receive the “X,” then place the “X” on the boundary between the two regions. 3. If the marked diagram shows that the conclusion is true, then the argument is valid. If the marked diagram shows that the conclusion is false or uncertain, then the argument is invalid.

Exercise Use diagramming to test the validity of the following U-P argument: All cats have rodent breath. Whiskers doesn't have rodent breath. Thus, Whiskers isn't a cat. A. Valid B. Invalid

Another U-P argument Use diagramming to test the validity of this argument. Gomer is not a rascal. No rascals are reliable. Therefore, Gomer is reliable. A. Valid B. Invalid

Diagramming conventions The remaining slides present a reminder of the diagramming ideas that were introduced in Part 2 Module 1. In this case, the diagramming rules are stated in terms of a two-circle Venn diagram, because a U-P argument will involve two categories, not three. Also, this summary will involve a simplest kind of existential statement – namely, a particular statement, which proposes the existence of a single, named individual, rather than a sub-category that could conceivably encompass many individuals. This stuff will get more complicated when we discuss categorical syllogisms in Part 2 Module 4.

Diagramming conventions - universal premises We diagram a universal premises (“all are…”, “none are..”) by using shading to blot out the region(s) of the diagram that contradict the universal statement. In other words, we use shading to indicate that the shaded region must contain no elements. Here is an example. Consider the universal statement “No elephants are tiny” in the context of this two-circle Venn diagram. E represents the set of elephants, and T represents the set of tiny things.

Shading “No elephants are tiny.” According to the statement “No elephants are tiny,” the region where E intersects T must be empty. This is because any element that is in the intersection of E with T is both an elephant and tiny, contracting the statement that “No elephants are tiny.” We shaded that region of the diagram, to indicate that it contains no elements.

Shading “No elephants are tiny.”

Diagramming a negative universal premise

Diagramming “All poodles are yappy.” We will mark the Venn diagram to convey the information in the positive universal statement “All poodles are yappy.” P represents the set of poodles, and Y represents the set of yappy things. According to the statement “All poodles are yappy,” any region of the diagram that shows poodles who aren’t yappy must be empty.

Diagramming “All poodles are yappy.”

Diagramming “All are…” Generally, diagramming a statement of the form “all are…”, such as “All A are B” or “All B are A,” will have the effect of shading a crescent-shaped region. The shading always indicates that the shaded region is empty.

Diagramming a particular statement Recall that a particular statement is a statement that relates an individual to a category, such as “Gomer is a firefighter” or “Whiskers doesn’t have rodent breath.” To diagram a particular statement, we use an “X” to represent the particular person who is the subject of the statement, and when place the “X” on the diagram according to the content of the statement. If the “X” can be placed in either of two regions, then we place the “X” on the boundary between the two regions.

Diagramming a “Gomer is a firefighter.” Suppose that the diagram below refers to the categories “Firefighters”(F) and “Heroes” (H). Mark the diagram to convey the information “Gomer is a firefighter.” Let “X” represent Gomer. Note that there are two regions of the diagram in which the “X” can be placed to satisfy the statement “Gomer is a firefighter.”

Diagramming a “Whiskers doesn’t have rodent breath.” Suppose the Venn diagram below relates to the categories “Cats” (C) and “things with Rodent Breath” (R). Mark the diagram to convey the information in the particular statement “Whiskers doesn’t have rodent breath. We will use an “X” to represent the particular individual “Whiskers.” Note that there are two regions of the diagram in which the “X” could be placed to satisfy the the condition “Whiskers doesn’t have rodent breath.”

Diagramming a “Whiskers doesn’t have rodent breath.” Because there are two regions in which we could place the “X” to satisfy the condition “Whiskers doesn’t have rodent breath,” we place the “X” on the boundary between those two regions.