Algebra by Another Name

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Critical Reading Strategies: Overview of Research Process
Advertisements

Sorting It All Out Mathematical Topics
Whiteboardmaths.com © 2004 All rights reserved
Algebra by Another Name ? Interpretations of Book II of Euclid's Elements John Little Holy Cross Summer Mathematical Seminar June 25, 2014.
Philosophy 120 Symbolic Logic I H. Hamner Hill CSTL-CLA.SEMO.EDU/HHILL/PL120.
Mathematical History Today, we want to study both some famous mathematical texts from the Old Babylonian period to see what they tell us about the mathematics.
So far we have learned about:
THE TRANSITION FROM ARITHMETIC TO ALGEBRA: WHAT WE KNOW AND WHAT WE DO NOT KNOW (Some ways of asking questions about this transition)‏
Algebra and the Mathematical Practices Google Image.
Math 260 Foundations of Geometry
Chapter 3 Greek Number Theory The Role of Number Theory Polygonal, Prime and Perfect Numbers The Euclidean Algorithm Pell’s Equation The Chord and Tangent.
Whole Numbers Are the whole numbers with the property of addition a group?
Basic Concepts of Algebra
CHAPTER 10: Hypothesis Testing, One Population Mean or Proportion
Common Fractions © Math As A Second Language All Rights Reserved next #6 Taking the Fear out of Math 1÷3 1 3.
MATH 224 – Discrete Mathematics
As you know generally it is assumed that the Euler equation and the Navier-Stokes equation Are the equations written as some analogues of Newton equation.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 4 ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF ELEMENTARY NUMBER THEORY AND METHODS OF PROOF.
Purpose: To understand words and vocabulary use
A Cheerful Fact: The Pythagorean Theorem Presented By: Rachel Thysell.
MAT 333 Fall  As we discovered with the Pythagorean Theorem examples, we need a system of geometry to convince ourselves why theorems are true.
Math 105: Problem Solving in Mathematics
Biological Science.
Pythagorean Theorem. History of Pythagorean Theorem Review The Pythagorean theorem takes its name from the ancient Greek mathematician Pythagoras (569.
Euclid and the “elements”. Euclid (300 BC, 265 BC (?) ) was a Greek mathematician, often referred to as the "Father of Geometry”. Of course this is not.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Naïve Set Theory. Basic Definitions Naïve set theory is the non-axiomatic treatment of set theory. In the axiomatic treatment, which we will only allude.
{ What is a Number? Philosophy of Mathematics.  In philosophy and maths we like our definitions to give necessary and sufficient conditions.  This means.
What is Science? Chapter 1, Lesson 1. Using one or more of your senses and tools to gather information. observing.
BY: LEONARDO BENEDITT Mathematics. What is Math? Mathematics is the science and study of quantity, structure, space, and change. Mathematicians.
Intertheoretic Reduction and Explanation in Mathematics
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. Fundamental Concepts of Algebra 1.1 Real Numbers.
The Elements, Book I – Propositions 1 – 10 MONT 104Q – Mathematical Journeys: Known to Unknown September 25, 2015.
Types of Research: General categories. The general types: 1. Analytical –Historical –Philosophical –Research synthesis (meta-analysis) 2. Descriptive.
What is History?. DUH???!!!! Important people Important dates Important events.
© 2013 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH Supporting Rigorous Mathematics Teaching and Learning Shaping Talk in the Classroom: Academically Productive Talk Features.
1 2/21/2016 MATH 224 – Discrete Mathematics Sequences and Sums A sequence of the form ar 0, ar 1, ar 2, ar 3, ar 4, …, ar n, is called a geometric sequence.
Theory of Knowledge: Mathematics. What is maths? In order to discuss what maths is, it is helpful to look back at how maths as a discipline developed.
 The Pythagorean Theorem provides a method to find a missing side for a right triangle. But what do we do for triangles that are not right?  The law.
Copyright © 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc. CHAPTER 10: Hypothesis Testing, One Population Mean or Proportion to accompany Introduction.
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF SCIENCE?
The World’s History of Math I S T A P R O V E D
AVID Ms. Richardson.
Chapter 2 Sets and Functions.
PowerPointmaths.com © 2004 all rights reserved
Functions of Complex Variable and Integral Transforms
Geometry What is it?.
Scientific Method.
Axiomatic Number Theory and Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems
untuk mengiringi Introduction to Business Statistics
Direct Proof and Counterexample III: Divisibility
Unit 4.4 Deriving the Equation of a Circle and Proving that all Circles are Similar Instructional Days: 9.
Direct Proof and Counterexample I: Introduction
How Many Ways Can 945 Be Written as the Difference of Squares?
Chapter 21 More About Tests.
Testing Hypotheses About Proportions
CONTINUOUS RANDOM VARIABLES
Section 2: Science as a Process
Presented by: Angela J. Williams
Chapter #1 Presentation
Unit 1 Points, Lines, Planes, and Angles
Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science
Introduction to Philosophy
Remember these terms? Analytic/ synthetic A priori/ a posteriori
Fundamentals of Computer Systems
Key Words and Introduction to Expressions
Pythagorean Theorem.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Pythagorean Theorem.
Presentation transcript:

Algebra by Another Name Algebra by Another Name? Interpretations of Book II of Euclid's Elements John Little MONT 107Q February 17, 2017

Book II of the Elements Consists of 14 Propositions, leading to a “punchline” Book II, Proposition 14. To construct a square [with area] equal to [that of] any given rectilinear figure In traditional terms – a “problem” rather than a “theorem” – gives an explicit construction, proves that the results are correct “quadrature” in its original sense(!) A collection of propositions is set up as a collection of “lemmas” for later use

“Geometric algebra?” Isn't Proposition 2 “just” a geometric version of the distributive law for multiplication over addition: Write AC = x, CB = y, then (x + y)(x + y) = (x + y)x + (x + y)y Couldn't you also prove Proposition 5 using those ideas too? Perhaps write AD = x and DB = y and assume x > y Then claim is: x y + ((x – y)/2)² = ((x + y)/2)² And of course the answer is, yes if we are thinking about the underlying logical relationships!

But is that what Euclid meant by this? But another question to ask here is: Was this Book II of the Elements a sort of “algebra in geometric form” for the Greeks? Many well-known historians of mathematics in 19th and early 20th centuries thought so H. Zeuthen, P. Tannery, O. Neugebauer, B. L. van der Waerden, … T. L. Heath (translator of most commonly- used English version of Euclid): Book II contains “... the geometric equivalent of the algebraical operations … “

C. Boyer, from “Euclid of Alexandria” “It is sometimes asserted that the Greeks had no algebra, but this is patently false. They had Book II of the Elements, which is geometric algebra and served much the same purpose as does our symbolic algebra. There can be little doubt that modern algebra greatly facilitates the manipulation of relationships among magnitudes. But it is undoubtedly also true that a Greek geometer versed in the fourteen theorems of Euclid's 'algebra' was far more adept in applying these theorems to practical mensuration than is an experienced geometer of today.”

Boyer, cont. “Ancient geometric 'algebra' was not an ideal tool, but it was far from ineffective. Euclid's statement (Proposition 4), 'If a straight line be cut at random, the square on the whole is equal to the squares on the segments and twice the rectangle contained by the segments,' is a verbose way of saying that (a + b)² = a² + 2ab + b²”

O. Neugebauer's view Provocatively, Neugebauer even noted that Proposition 5 is equivalent to (i.e. can be restated with the same algebraic relation as) a step-by-step procedure for solving the type of quadratic equation occurring in many Old Babylonian problem texts like YBC 6967 (dating to about 1800 BCE) He suggested that Book II of the Elements might record a sort of “technology transfer” from the Babylonian tradition into Greek mathematics, but recast in typically Greek geometric form

Sabetai Unguru's critique S. Unguru, On the need to rewrite the history of Greek mathematics, Archive for History of Exact Sciences 15 (1975/76), 67—114. Forcefully refutes “geometric algebra” as a correct description of Book II of Euclid Unguru's main point: it's geometry pure and simple; Greek mathematics did not have any of the apparatus of symbolic algebra Rejects and even ridicules Neugebauer's proposed “Babylonian connection” because no explicit evidence exists for it

Unguru's argument, summarized Attempting to “explain” Euclid this way is perniciously wrong from the historical point of view because it uses modern concepts that are a false description of a fundamentally different understanding of mathematics (“conceptual anachronism,” or “Whig history” – presents the past as leading inevitably to the present): In symbolic algebra, variables are effectively placeholders for numerical values, but for the Greeks, the idea of number (ἀριθμός) always referred to “counting numbers” (positive integers)

Unguru, continued So, Euclid never used a numerical value as a measure of length or area and used different methods in the “arithmetical books” VII – IX of the Elements Moreover, depending on how we label different lengths in figures, the algebraic “translation” can end up being quite different For example, Book II, Proposition 5 could also be written as (x + y)(x – y) + y² = x² if we make x = AC, y = CD Which algebraic version was Euclid thinking of? Unguru's answer: NONE of them!

If Unguru wanted to start a war, he succeeded! From Unguru's article – a fairly typical example of the tone – really quite extraordinary(!) “ … history of mathematics has been typically written by mathematicians … who have either reached retirement age and ceased to be productive in their own specialties or become otherwise professionally sterile … the reader may judge for himself how wise a decision it is for a professional to start writing the history of his discipline when his only calling lies in professional senility …”

A bitter academic controversy When Unguru's article appeared, one of the mathematicians/historians Unguru had savaged, B. L. van der Waerden, was still alive (his dates: 1903 – 1996). You can imagine how well he liked that passage from Unguru's article! He published a rejoinder – a defence of his point of view in the same issue of the Archive for History of Exact Sciences – “A defence of a 'shocking' point of view”, 199 – 210.

H. Freudenthal – another response “What is algebra and what has it been in history?” Archive for History of Exact Sciences 16 (1976/77), 189 – 200. Argues that there is indeed algebra in Greek mathematics, using examples from Archimedes But of course, a historian would say “I thought we were talking about Euclid. Archimedes was active about 50-70 years after Euclid's time, … “

André Weil “weighs in” “Who betrayed Euclid? Extract from a letter to the editor,” Archive for History of Exact Science 19 (1978/79), 91 – 93: Essentially asks: “who was responsible for allowing such a trashy article to be published? What is happening to the quality of this journal?” And gets in a nice ad hominem attack: “ … it is well to know mathematics before concerning oneself with its history … ”

A “tempest in a teapot?” This may all strike you as a nasty but silly disagreement over a minor issue. But it points out a fundamental difference between doing mathematics and doing history of mathematics (as history). As mathematicians, recognizing logical connections between old and new work and making reinterpretations is a part of what we do. When apparently different things are logically the same, just expressed in different ways, we can treat them as the same(!) So we are always looking for those equivalences – finding them can represent an advance in our understanding!

A “tempest in a teapot?” And (as Unguru insinuated in his own nasty way) van der Waerden, Freudenthal, Weil were certainly all primarily mathematicians who had eminent research records and then turned to writing history later in their professional careers Not surprising that they had the “habits of mind” and point of view of working mathematicians, not historians! In particular, to put words in their mouths: “if it's logically equivalent to algebra, then it's a geometric form of algebra”

A “tempest in a teapot?” But for intellectual historians, it's not so much logical equivalences that matter – it's particular features, differences! Each culture, era, scientific school, etc. is a unique and separate thing – their first and most important job is to understand Greek mathematics on its own terms, not on our terms A fundamentally different way of thinking; can see Unguru and van der Waerden, Freudenthal, Weil talking past each other without really understanding the others' points because they aren't approaching the question from the same place.

Winners and losers? In many ways, have to say Unguru was the “winner” here A small but growing corps of historians of mathematics (as distinct from mathematicians doing history) now exists and they take Unguru's view for the most part Even mathematicians doing history have to be sensitive to these issues to have their work accepted these days

Since the controversy – whose vindication? From a historian's point of view it's also interesting to ask how understanding of Euclid's Book II evolved over time More recent work (see Corry, Archive for History of Exact Sciences (2013)) – as the Elements passed through the Medieval Islamic world and Renaissance Europe (where our symbolic algebra was developed), the connection between geometry and algebra was realized and alternate algebraic proofs started to be presented for the propositions in Book II (!) “Geometric algebra” probably does do a good job of describing later understanding!