PHIL 2000 Philosophical Tools 1st Term 2016

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Causal Theories.
Advertisements

Causal Theories.
Kaplan’s Theory of Indexicals
Section 2.3 I, Robot Mind as Software.
Identity and Necessity
Philosophy of Mind Matthew Soteriou. Functionalism and Qualia Critics of functionalist accounts of the mental often appeal to thought experiments in which.
Saul Kripke, “Identity and Necessity” Driving question: How are contingent identity statements possible? For example, we take it to be the case that it.
LECTURE 24 THE NATURE OF PERSONS PHYSICALISM AND DUALISM (“WHAT AM I?)
Hillary Putnam Whichever way you cut it, meanings ain’t in the head.
Identity and Necessity Saul Kripke. Kripke’s Puzzle How are contingent identity statements possible? –Since everything that exists is necessarily self-identical.
1 6 The Sense/Reference Distinction Revisited. 2 Sense qua Identifying Descriptions See Donnellan, 1970 “Speaking of Nothing” and Kripke, 1972 Naming.
The Modal Argument. Review: The “Hard Problem”  Remember that there are three arguments that make consciousness a ‘hard’ problem. 1. Knowledge Argument.
The “Explanatory Gap” Where it is said that identity theory is not necessary false, but merely unknowable.
Causal Theories. THE ABSURDITY OF FIT The Absurdity of Fit In one sense, all the views we’ve considered in class so far are views on which meaning is.
The meaning and reference of natural kind terms Joanna Odrowąż-Sypniewska Warsaw University
2 March.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
The Causal Theory of Reference. Explaining Reference Kripke: a name refers to a thing if there is the right sort of causal link between the thing and.
Philosophy 4610 Philosophy of Mind Week 4: Objections to Behaviorism The Identity Theory.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Minds and Bodies #3 (Jackson) By David Kelsey.
Section 2.3 I, Robot Mind as Software McGraw-Hill © 2013 McGraw-Hill Companies. All Rights Reserved.
© Michael Lacewing Substance and Property Dualism Michael Lacewing
Naming & Necessity. Classical Descriptivism.
The Causal Historical Theory. Natural Kinds Kripke and another philosopher Hilary Putnam wanted to generalize what was true of names to “natural kind.
Learning objective: To understand the objection that even if a zombie world is conceivable it may not be possible, and to evaluate how convincing this.
Identity theory. Theory of Mind : Mental states are. Something is in pain only if, and because,. The Identity Theory : Mental states are physical.
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE Some topics and historical issues of the 20 th century.
Dispositional Metasemantics Michael Johnson HAP HKU 1.
Ontological Argument (Ontological is from the Greek word for being, named by Kant) Learning Objectives To know the specification content To know the meaning.
Lecture 6 Modality: Possible worlds
Ryle’s philosophical behaviourism
The Causal-Historical Theory
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT 1
Substance and Property Dualism
Truths and Possible Worlds
A Mickey Mouse Guide to the Ontological Argument
O.A. so far.. Anselm – from faith, the fool, 2 part argument
1st wave: Illusion Descartes begins his method of doubt by considering that in the past he has been deceived by his senses: Things in the distance looked.
Descartes’ conceivability argument for substance dualism
Problems for Identity Theory
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
The zombie argument: responses
Descartes, Meditations 1 and 2
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Minds and Bodies #3 (Jackson)
Philosophy of Language Seminar 3: Definite Descriptions (2)
Metaphysics Seminar 8: Modality (1)
Metaphysics Seminar 7: Ontology (4)
The De Se.
Michael Lacewing The zombie argument Michael Lacewing
Remember these terms? Analytic/ synthetic A priori/ a posteriori
The Copleston, Russell Debate
Use Theories.
Mind-Brain Type Identity Theory
Recap Key-Terms Cognitivism Non-Cognitivism Realism Anti-Realism
Meta-Ethics Objectives:
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
Recap Normative Ethics
Do we directly perceive objects? (25 marks)
The Mind Body Problem Our minds seem to be non-physical and different from our bodies. Our bodies seem to be something different from our minds. Are they.
True or False: Materialism and physicalism mean the same thing.
The Big Picture Deductive arguments - origins of the ontological argument Deductive proofs; the concept of ‘a priori’. St Anselm - God as the greatest.
Property Dualism - Recap
01 4 Ethical Language 4.1 Meta-Ethics.
The Ontological Argument
What is good / bad about this answer?
Or Can you?.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 12 Moral Realism and Relativism
Outline the naturalistic fallacy
Henry Taylor Philosophy of Language Seminar 7: Externalist theories of mental content. Henry Taylor
Presentation transcript:

PHIL 2000 Philosophical Tools 1st Term 2016 Naming and Necessity PHIL 2000 Philosophical Tools 1st Term 2016

Possible Worlds

Necessary vs. Contingent Necessary = “could not have been false” Note on modal auxiliary ‘could have’: personal, physical, metaphsycial Contingent = “could have been false” Metaphysical distinction, not epistemological Cf. “Can believe it’s false” vs. “Can’t believe it’s false”

A Posteriori Necessities Things that must be true, but need to be investigated to be known. Informative identity statements “Whales are mammals.” “Lightning is an electrical discharge.” Necessity of origin: Michael’s parents must have been Lowell and Wendy Johnson.

Moore’s Open Question Argument What is it for an act to be morally good? Can there be a natural property that is identical to the property of being morally good? Suppose there can, call it X. Then things that are X should obviously (a priori) be morally good, because X = moral goodness. But it’s always an open question: “Are the things that are X morally good?” So there is no such natural property.

An Argument for Dualism What is a conscious experience? Can conscious experiences be identified with physical states of the brain? Suppose seeing red = being in brain state B. Then it should be a priori that beings that see red are in brain state B. But I can imagine beings that are in B, but don’t see red (philosophical zombies, inverted spectrum cases…) Therefore, seeing red is not the same thing as being in any brain state.

A Priori Contingencies Things that could have been false, but can still be known without investigation. Cartesian truths? “I think”, “I exist”, “I have the idea of God”– are these the result of experience with the relevant facts? A posteriori certainties?? “Jack the Ripper was a murderer.” “Homer wrote the Iliad.” (Cf. “Shakespeare wrote Hamlet.”) “Dark energy is responsible for the universe’s expansion.”

Possibility A statement is possible if it can be true. Contingently true OR contingently false OR necessarily true Not necessarily false. P is possible = not necessarily not-P P is necessary = not possibly not-P

Possible Worlds Some things are not true, but they could have been true. It could have been true that there were talking donkeys, even though there aren’t actually any talking donkeys.

Possible Worlds Some philosophers have tried to analyze possibility in terms of possible worlds: It is possible that P. = In some possible world, it is true that P.

The Multiverse Important: some physicists believe our universe is part of a multiverse of universes. This is different from the philosophers notion of possible world. In particular, physicists are not committed to the claim that in some other universe, donkeys talk.

Possible Worlds Philosophers who believe in possible worlds disagree about what they are. According to Lewis: Possible worlds are just as real, and made out of the same sorts of things as the world we live in. They are universes that are not spatially connected to ours, so we cannot go there or change what happens there.

Possible Worlds Robert Stalnaker, however, thinks that possible worlds are not concrete universes. They are instead a type of uninstantiated property: Possible worlds are maximally specific ways that our world could have been.

Possible Worlds Possible worlds are maximally specific ways that our world could have been. This doesn’t particularly help with analyzing modality.

Classical Descriptivism

Representation Words/ thoughts have meanings. They are about things. Why do words, for example, represent the things that they do, instead of other things or nothing at all?

Classical Descriptivism For every name N, there is a description D that we associate with N such that: If x satisfies D, then N refers to x. If N refers to x, then x satisfies the description.

Classical Descriptivism We may say, following Russell: the name “Moses” can be defined by means of various descriptions. For example, as “the man who led the Israelites through the wilderness”, “the man who lived at that time and place and was then called ‘Moses’”, “the man who as a child was taken out of the Nile by Pharaoh's daughter” and so on. Investigations Section 79

Classical Descriptivism Moses: Lead the Israelites out of Egypt Parted Red Sea Given 10 commandments by God

Classical Descriptivism This guy Lead the Israelites out of Egypt Parted Red Sea Given 10 commandments by God

Classical Descriptivism Moses refers

Classical Descriptivism This guy Lead the Israelites out of Egypt Parted Red Sea Given 10 commandments by God

Classical Descriptivism Moses refers

Kripke against Descriptivism

Saul Kripke, 1940- Published first completeness proof for modal logic at 18. Highly influential in philosophy of language and mind. Developed the causal-historical theory of meaning

Saul Kripke, 1940- Kripke’s account is developed in his Naming and Necessity. The background is that he’s arguing against views on which the meanings of names are descriptions or definitions.

Against Descriptivism Kripke argues that for any name N, there is no description D that we associate with N such that: If x satisfies the description, N refers to x. If N refers to x, then x must satisfy the description.

Ignorance & Error He argues against each claim as follows: Against #1: Arguments from ignorance. Sometimes lots of things satisfy the descriptions we associate with N, but only one is N. Against #2: Arguments from Error. Sometimes nothing satisfies the descriptions we associate with N (or some non-x does), but N still = x.

Ignorance: Feynman What people know: He’s a physicist He’s famous He’s dead He worked on quantum mechanics

Ignorance: Feynman But Bohr: He’s a physicist He’s famous He’s dead He worked on quantum mechanics

Ignorance: Feynman it’s not true that ‘Feynman’ means Bohr and it’s not true that it means nothing. How is that possible for the descriptivist?

Error: Einstein Who is Albert Einstein? What people believe: Einstein is the inventor of the atomic bomb.

Error: Einstein But “the inventor of the nuclear bomb” can’t be the meaning of ‘Einstein’ because then ‘Einstein’ would refer to Leo Szilard (or whoever).

Causation & Representation

The Mirror Universe

Secondary Qualities

Possibility of Massive Error

Coordination across Theories A related upshot is that two people with radically different theories can nevertheless be talking about the same thing, and hence be meaningfully disagreeing with one another.

The Causal-Historical Account

Kripke’s Picture “Someone, let’s say, a baby, is born; his parents call him by a certain name. They talk about him to their friends, other people meet him. Through various sorts of talk the name is spread from link to link as if by a chain…”

Kripke’s Picture “A speaker who is on the far end of this chain, who has heard about, say Richard Feynman, in the market place or elsewhere, may be referring to Richard Feynman even though he can’t remember from whom he first heard of Feynman or from whom he ever heard of Feynman.”

Kripke’s Picture “A rough statement of a theory might be the following: An initial ‘baptism’ takes place. Here the object may be named by ostension, or the reference of the name may be fixed by a description…”

Kripke’s Picture “When the name is ‘passed from link to link’, the receiver of the name must, I think, intend when he learns it to use it with the same reference as the man from whom he heard it.”

The Causal-Historical Theory Let’s call that baby ‘Feynman’ Feynman Feynman Feynman Feynman

The Causal-Historical Theory Let’s call that baby ‘Feynman’ Feynman Feynman Feynman Feynman Historical Chain of Transmission

The Causal-Historical Theory Feynman Feynman Feynman Feynman Denotation

No Connotations The causal-historical theory, unlike the other theories, does not use mental facts (idea, experience, definition) to determine a referent. Denotations are determined by non-mental facts.* *Plus one intention for each link in the chain.

Natural Kinds Kripke and another philosopher Hilary Putnam wanted to generalize what was true of names to “natural kind terms” (a phrase introduced by Quine).

The Causal-Historical Theory Let’s call that thing a “tiger.” TIGER TIGER TIGER TIGER

Ignorance: Water In Hilary Putnam’s classic “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’” he argues that “meaning just ain’t in the head.” In particular, he presents his famous Twin Earth thought experiment, which is intended to show that what the word ‘water’ is true of is not determined by what we know or believe about water.

Twin Earth Twin Earth is a planet on the other side of the galaxy. In most ways, it is just like Earth, down to the smallest detail. You have a twin on Twin Earth who’s just like you, I have a twin who’s just like me, they’re sitting in a twin classroom, and my twin is giving a lecture just like this one to your twin. And so on and so forth.

Earth Twin Earth

Twin Earth There is however one difference between Earth and Twin Earth. On Earth, all the watery stuff is H2O. On Twin Earth, the watery stuff is composed of a complicated chemical compound we can abbreviate XYZ. H2O and XYZ look and behave exactly the same. They taste the same, they boil at the same temperatures at the same distance above sea level, their conductance is the same, etc.

Twin Earth Consider two twins, Arnold on Earth and Twin Arnold on Twin Earth. Neither knows any chemistry. What they know/ believe about the stuff they call ‘water’ is the same. Q: Would it be true for Arnold to call the stuff on Twin Earth ‘water’?

Twin Earth The intuition is supposed to be that, no, Arnold’s word ‘water’ is true of all an only H2O, whereas Twin Arnold’s word ‘water’ is true of all and only XYZ

The Moral The conclusion Kripke and Putnam draw from such cases is that we fix the referent of ‘water’ by a description like “the stuff around here in lakes and rivers and streams that falls from the sky and quenches thirst.” But this description only fixes the referent. If you replaced all the H2O on Earth with XYZ, there wouldn’t be any more water here.