The Combinatorics of Voting Paradoxes

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
MAT199: Math Alive Voting, Power, and Sharing Ian Griffiths Mathematical Institute, University of Oxford, Department of Mathematics, Princeton University.
Advertisements

Computational Game Theory Amos Fiat Spring 2012
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan
6.896: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture 18 Constantinos Daskalakis.
Ioannis Caragiannis, Jason A. Covey, Michal Feldman, Christopher M. Homan, Christos Kaklamanis, Nikos Karanikolask, Ariel D. Procaccia, Je ff rey S. Rosenschein.
Presented by: Katherine Goulde
Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 3 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 3 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Algorithmic Game Theory Uri Feige Robi Krauthgamer Moni Naor Lecture 9: Social Choice Lecturer: Moni Naor.
NOTE: To change the image on this slide, select the picture and delete it. Then click the Pictures icon in the placeholder to insert your own image. CHOOSING.
Mark Wang John Sturm Sanjeev Kulkarni Paul Cuff.  Basic Background – What is the problem?  Condorcet = IIA  Survey Data  Pairwise Boundaries = No.
Public Finance (MPA405) Dr. Khurrum S. Mughal.
How “impossible” is it to design a Voting rule? Angelina Vidali University of Athens.
IMPOSSIBILITY AND MANIPULABILITY Section 9.3 and Chapter 10.
CS 886: Electronic Market Design Social Choice (Preference Aggregation) September 20.
Voting Theory.
Arrow’s impossibility theorem EC-CS reading group Kenneth Arrow Journal of Political Economy, 1950.
Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010 Michelle Blessing February 23, 2010.
Using a Modified Borda Count to Predict the Outcome of a Condorcet Tally on a Graphical Model 11/19/05 Galen Pickard, MIT Advisor: Dr. Whitman Richards,
Fair Elections Are they possible?. Acknowledgment Many of the examples are taken from Excursions in Modern Mathematics by Peter Tannenbaum and Robert.
Motivation: Condorcet Cycles Let people 1, 2 and 3 have to make a decision between options A, B, and C. Suppose they decide that majority voting is a good.
CPS Voting and social choice
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Complexity of unweighted coalitional manipulation under some common voting rules Lirong XiaVincent Conitzer COMSOC08, Sep. 3-5, 2008 TexPoint fonts used.
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = truthful voting Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University.
Social Welfare, Arrow + Gibbard- Satterthwaite, VCG+CPP 1 TexPoint fonts used in EMF. Read the TexPoint manual before you delete this box.: AAA A A A A.
A Fourier-Theoretic Perspective on the Condorcet Paradox and Arrow ’ s Theorem. By Gil Kalai, Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew University Presented by:
Social choice (voting) Vincent Conitzer > > > >
An efficient distributed protocol for collective decision- making in combinatorial domains CMSS Feb , 2012 Minyi Li Intelligent Agent Technology.
Voting Geometry: A Mathematical Study of Voting Methods and Their Properties Alan T. Sherman Dept. of CSEE, UMBC March 27, 2006.
CPS Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. Chapter 15 Section 2 - Slide Election Theory Flaws of Voting.
Elections and Strategic Voting: Condorcet and Borda E. Maskin Harvard University.
1 Elections and Manipulations: Ehud Friedgut, Gil Kalai, and Noam Nisan Hebrew University of Jerusalem and EF: U. of Toronto, GK: Yale University, NN:
Assoc. Prof. Yeşim Kuştepeli1 VOTING GAMES. Assoc. Prof. Yeşim Kuştepeli2 Outline Choosing Among Voting Mechanisms Majority Rule with Two Choices Plurality.
Math for Liberal Studies.  We have seen many methods, all of them flawed in some way  Which method should we use?  Maybe we shouldn’t use any of them,
Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science.
Let’s take a class vote. How many of you are registered to vote?
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem. Question: Is there a public decision making process, voting method, or “Social Welfare Function” (SWF) that will tell us.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan Voting and Social Choice Majority Rule and Condorcet’s Method Other Voting Systems for Three.
Voting System Review Borda – Sequential Run-Off – Run-Off –
Social Choice Lecture 16 John Hey. More Possibility/Impossibility Theorems Sen’s Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal Gibbard’s theory of alienable rights.
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem
Choosing the Lesser Evil: Helping Students Understand Voting Systems
Model n voters, m candidates
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Chapter 10: The Manipulability of Voting Systems Lesson Plan
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Gil Kalai Einstein Institute of Mathematics
Applied Mechanism Design For Social Good
8.2 Voting Possibilities and Fairness Criteria
Algorithmic Analysis of Elections: Voting Rules and Manipulability (minicourse) Piotr Faliszewski AGH University Kraków, Poland.
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Introduction If we assume
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Alex Tabarrok Arrow’s Theorem.
Negotiation Analytics 30C02000 Jyrki Wallenius
Manipulation Lirong Xia Fall, Manipulation Lirong Xia Fall, 2016.
Section 15.2 Flaws of Voting
5-2 Election Theory Flaws of Voting.
Voting systems Chi-Kwong Li.
Voting and social choice
Introduction to Social Choice
Quiz – 1/24 - Friday How many people voted in the election?
Flaws of the Voting Methods
CPS Voting and social choice
Chapter 9: Social Choice: The Impossible Dream Lesson Plan
Presentation transcript:

The Combinatorics of Voting Paradoxes Noga Alon, Tel Aviv U. and Microsoft, Israel IPAM, UCLA, Oct. 2009 TexPoint fonts used in EMF. Read the TexPoint manual before you delete this box.: AAAA

The Condorcet Paradox (1785): The majority may prefer A to B, B to C and C to A. Indeed, if the preferences of 3 voters are: A>B>C B>C>A C>A>B then 2/3 prefer A to B 2/3 prefer B to C 2/3 prefer C to A

The moral: The majority preferences may be irrational

marquis de Condorcet

McGarvey (1953): The majority may exhibit any pattern of pairwise preferences D E C A B A>B>C>D>E C>E>B>D>A D>E>A>B>C

The moral: The majority preferences may be chaotic

Voting schemes n voters, k candidates Each voter in the group ranks all candidates (linearly), and the scheme provides the group’s linear ranking of the candidates Axiom 1 (unanimity): If all voters rank A above B, then so does the resulting order Axiom 2 (independence of irrelevant alternatives): The group’s relative ranking of any pair of candidates is determined by the voters relative ranking of this pair.

IN THAT CASE, I’LL HAVE A CHICKEN BEEF, PLEASE WOULD YOU LIKE CHICKEN OR BEEF ? SORRY, WE ALSO HAVE A FISH

Arrow (1951): If k ≥3, the only scheme that satisfies axiom 1 and axiom 2 is dictatorship, that is, the group’s ranking is determined by that of one voter !

The moral: The only ``reasonable’’ voting scheme is dictatorship

Leader Election n voters, k candidates Each voter ranks all candidates linearly. The winner (=leader) is determined by these orderings following a known rule Axiom 1: The rule is not dictatorship, that is, no single voter can choose the leader by himself Axiom 2: Any candidate can win under the rule, with some profile of the voters’ preferences.

Gibbard (1973), Satterthwaite (1975): If k ≥ 3, any such scheme can be manipulated, that is, there are cases in which a voter who knows the preferences of the other voters and knows the rule has an incentive to vote untruthfully

The moral: Any reasonable leader election scheme can be manipulated

Back to the majority rule: A committee of size 2k-1 has to select r winners among n candidates. Each committee members (=voter) provides a linear order of the candidates, and the scheme chooses r winners. Axiom: For any profile of preferences, there is no non-winner A so that for every winner B, most of the committee members rank A over B Remark: The example of Condorcet shows that this is impossible for 2k-1=3, r=1.

Alon,Brightwell,Kierstead,Kostochka,Winkler(2006): For 2k-1=3, if r ≤ 2 there is no such scheme, r ≥ 3 suffices For larger k, if r ≤ ⅓ k / log k there is no such scheme, r ≥ 80 k log k suffices.

The proof is based on: Linear Programming Duality Integral and fractional covers of hypergraphs The theory of VC-dimension of range spaces Probabilistic arguments Open: What’s the smallest possible r that suffices for a committee of size 2k-1 ?

The moral: Bigger committees require bigger budget

Reality Games

In a variant of the TV show ``Survivor’’ each tribe member can recommend at most one other trusted member The mechanism selects a member to be eliminated in the tribal council, based on these recommendations Axiom: If there is a unique tribe member that received positive recommendations, then this member cannot be the eliminated one.

Alon, Fischer, Procaccia, Tennenholtz (2009): No such scheme can be strategy-proof, that is, there must be a scenario in which a member, knowing the scheme and the recommendations of all others, can gain (=avoid being eliminated) by mis-reporting his recommendation.

Proof: - Denote the tribe members by 0,1,..,n, and assume that when no positive votes are given, 0 is the one being eliminated. Consider the 2n scenarios in which 0 does not vote, and each i between 1 and n either votes for 0 or for nobody. By the axiom, 0 is being eliminated only in one such scenario (when nobody recommends him).

in some scenario, he is also the one to be - By strategy-proofness, if i > 0 is being eliminated in some scenario, he is also the one to be eliminated when i changes his vote Therefore, the total number of scenarios in which i is being eliminated is even. But this is impossible, as the total number of scenarios considered is even. □

The moral: Cheating is inherent in reality games (unless one uses randomization)

Summary (informal): we have seen Condorcet (1785): The majority may be irrational McGarvey (1953): The majority may be chaotic Arrow (1951): The only reasonable voting scheme is dictatorship GS (1973,75): Any reasonable leader election game can be manipulated ABKKW (2006): Bigger committees require bigger budget AFPT (2009): Cheating is inherent in reality games

Is the theory of Social Choice relevant to real life ? Condorcet (1775): ``Rejecting theory as useless in order to work on everyday things is like proposing to cut the roots of a tree because they do not carry fruit’’