Utilitarianism 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Lesson 5 Utilitarian ethics
Advertisements

Decisions at the end of life
What is a normative theory?
RECAP – TASK 1 What is utilitarianism? Who is Jeremy Bentham?
Two Major Historical Theories of Ethics: 1.) Consequentialist: based on or concerned with consequences. (also called “teleological” theories) 2.) Nonconsequentialist:
4/15/2017 Utilitarianism 4/15/2017 ©Lawrence M. Hinman.
1Utilitarianism Soazig Le Bihan - University of Montana.
Chapter Seven: Utilitarianism
Ethics A Very Brief Primer Ethics of Duty or Deontological Ethics.
Utilitarianism Leadership & Ethics OC Bobby Kenning.
Standards of Conduct DoD’s Standards of Conduct
ETHICS BOWL CONSEQUENTIALism.
Utilitarian Approach. Utilitarianism The founder of classical utilitarianism is Jeremy Bentham. According to Bentham human beings always try to avoid.
T HE U TILITARIAN A PPROACH Marcie Neils, Brandon Capelle, Aaron Zimbelman, & Nate Martin Monday 1:30-4:30 LP 5: Ethical Theory Presentation November 10,
Chapter 13: The Utilitarian: John Stuart Mill
1 Consequentialism vs. Deontology Consequentialism: –the view that an act is right if and only if it will maximize (or is likely to maximize) good consequences.
Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill. When an objection is raised: When some objection is raised to a moral theory, if that objection is a good one, the proponent.
Consequentialism Utilitarianism. John Stuart Mill ( ) Principle of Utility: actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness,
Utilitarianism Lesson # 4 Leadership and Ethics. Utilitarianism What is Utilitarianism?
Utilitarianism. Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters; pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we.
The Morality of Consequences. Utilitarian Ethics We ought to perform actions which tend to produce the greatest overall happiness for the greatest number.
PHIL 2525 Contemporary Moral Issues Lec. 13 Recapping: 3 main points of Utilitarianism:  Actions are judged right or wrong solely on the basis of their.
Act and Rule Utilitariansim
Utilitarianism Forensics 8.6 November 14, 2014.
PHIL 2525 Contemporary Moral Issues Lec. 14 Recapping... 3 main points of Utilitarianism:  Actions are judged right or wrong solely on the basis of.
Nicole Pongratz Allisen Jacques Shannon Griese Amber Teichmiller 4/13/2010.
Philosophy 360: Business Ethics Chapter 3. Consequentialism: Is part of a theory about what makes certain actions right or wrong. In a nutshell: Actions.
Morality in the Modern World
PHIL 2525 Contemporary Moral Issues Lec. 13 Recapping: 3 main points of Utilitarianism:  Actions are judged right or wrong solely on the basis of their.
Jan 29, 10 Ashley Tao. Tues 8-10pm Dundas Town Hall
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
BY ALDOUS HUXLEY Brave New World. The Author Aldous Huxley Born July 26, 1894 in Godalming, England Mother and sister both died in 1908 Educated at Balliol.
Lawrence M. Hinman, Ph.D. Director, The Values Institute University of San Diego 7/8/2016©Lawrence M. Hinman1 Utilitarianism.
 Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill  Reason not Revelation  Consequentialism – good or bad, right or wrong, are based on outcomes.
Assignment pts - Ethical Framework
Ethical theories and approaches in Business
Ethics: Theory and Practice
Bentham’s Classical Utilitarianism
It is unclear exactly what counts as a benefit or a cost
Utilitarianism.
Rule Utilitarianism To understand later developments in Utilitarianism and the works of Mill and Singer.
Bernard Williams: A Critique of Utilitarianism Phil 240, Introduction to Ethical Theory, W6L5 Benjamin Visscher Hole IV.
Utilitarianism Learning Intention:
John Stuart Mill.
Part Four. Act and Rule Utilitarianism
On your whiteboard: What is teleology? What is hedonism?
Part One. Fundamental Tenets of Utilitarianism
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 15 Ethics #1: Utilitarianism
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Religion and Justice Utilitarianism Jeremy Bentham ( )
Higher RMPS Utilitarian ethics.
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Bentham’s Utilitarianism
Philosophy 2030 Class #11 4/12/16 Take-home / open book midterm
Utilitarianism Phil. 321 Social Ethics Lawrence M. Hinman Summer 2010
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Outline the naturalistic fallacy
Utilitarianism Consequential, i.e. Utilitarianism – a good moral decision is that which the consequences of the action produces the greatest good for the.
The Ethics of Utility The Utilitarian Theory :
Moral Theories: Utilitarianism
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Principles of Morals and Legislation Jeremy Bentham
Week 3: Utilitarianism.
Utilitarianism Jeremy Bentham
Ethical Theory Seeking a Standard for Morally Correct Action
On your whiteboard: List the strengths and weaknesses of act utilitarianism.
Ethical concepts and ethical theories Topic 3
Utilitarianism – Bentham’s Classic Utilitarianism
Utilitarianism.
Presentation transcript:

Utilitarianism 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Overview Fundamental Tenets of Utilitarianism Standards of Utility/History of Utilitarianism The Utilitarian Calculus Act and Rule Utilitarianism Criticisms of Utilitarianism Concluding Assessment 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Part One. Fundamental Tenets of Utilitarianism 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Basic Insights of Utilitarianism The purpose of morality is to make the world a better place. Morality is about producing good consequences, not having good intentions We should do whatever will bring the most benefit (i.e., intrinsic value) to all of humanity. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

The Purpose of Morality The utilitarian has a very simple answer to the question of why morality exists at all: The purpose of morality is to guide people’s actions in such a way as to produce a better world. Consequently, the emphasis in utilitarianism is on consequences, not intentions. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Fundamental Imperative The fundamental imperative of utilitarianism is: Always act in the way that will produce the greatest overall amount of good in the world. The emphasis is clearly on consequences, not intentions. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

The Emphasis on the Overall Good We often speak of “utilitarian” solutions in a disparaging tone, but in fact utilitarianism is a demanding moral position that often asks us to put aside self-interest for the sake of the whole. Utilitarianism is a morally demanding position for two reasons: It always asks us to do the most, to maximize utility, not to do the minimum. It asks us to set aside personal interest. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

The Dream of Utilitarianism: Bringing Scientific Certainty to Ethics Utilitarianism offers us a powerful vision of the moral life, one that promises to reduce or eliminate moral disagreement. If we can agree that the purpose of morality is to make the world a better place; and If we can scientifically assess various possible courses of action to determine which will have the greatest positive effect on the world; then We can provide a scientific answer to the question of what we ought to do. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Part Two. Standards of Utility: A History of Utilitarianism 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Intrinsic Value Many things have instrumental value, that is, they have value as means to an end. However, there must be some things which are not merely instrumental, but have value in themselves. This is what we call intrinsic value. What has intrinsic value? Four principal candidates: Pleasure Jeremy Bentham Happiness John Stuart Mill Ideals G. E. Moore Preferences Kenneth Arrow 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Jeremy Bentham 1748-1832 Bentham believed that we should try to increase the overall amount of pleasure in the world. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Pleasure Definition: The enjoyable feeling we experience when a state of deprivation is replaced by fulfillment. Advantages Easy to quantify Short duration Bodily Criticisms Came to be known as “the pig’s philosophy” Ignores higher values Could justify living on a pleasure machine 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

John Stuart Mill 1806-1873 Bentham’s godson Believed that happiness, not pleasure, should be the standard of utility. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Happiness Advantages Disadvantages A higher standard, more specific to humans About realization of goals Disadvantages More difficult to measure Competing conceptions of happiness 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Ideal Values G. E. Moore suggested that we should strive to maximize ideal values such as freedom, knowledge, justice, and beauty. The world may not be a better place with more pleasure in it, but it certainly will be a better place with more freedom, more knowledge, more justice, and more beauty. Moore’s candidates for intrinsic good remain difficult to quantify. G. E. Moore 1873-1958 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Preferences Kenneth Arrow, a Nobel Prize winning Stanford economist, argued that what has intrinsic value is preference satisfaction. The advantage of Arrow’s approach is that, in effect, it lets people choose for themselves what has intrinsic value. It simply defines intrinsic value as whatever satisfies an agent’s preferences. It is elegant and pluralistic. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Part Three. The Utilitarian Calculus 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

The Utilitarian Calculus Math and ethics finally merge: all consequences must be measured and weighed. Units of measurement: Hedons: positive Dolors: negative 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

What do we calculate? Hedons/dolors may be defined in terms of Pleasure Happiness Ideals Preferences For any given action, we must calculate: How many people will be affected, negatively (dolors) as well as positively (hedons) How intensely they will be affected Similar calculations for all available alternatives Choose the action that produces the greatest overall amount of utility (hedons minus dolors) 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Example: Debating the school lunch program Utilitarians would have to calculate: Benefits Increased nutrition for x number of children Increased performance, greater long-range chances of success Incidental benefits to contractors, etc. Costs Cost to each taxpayer Contrast with other programs that could have been funded and with lower taxes (no program) Multiply each factor by Number of individuals affected Intensity of effects 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

How much can we quantify? Pleasure and preference satisfaction are easier to quantify than happiness or ideals Two distinct issues: Can everything be quantified? Some would maintain that some of the most important things in life (love, family, etc.) cannot easily be quantified, while other things (productivity, material goods) may get emphasized precisely because they are quantifiable. The danger: if it can’t be counted, it doesn’t count. Are quantified goods necessarily commensurable? Are a fine dinner and a good night’s sleep commensurable? Can one be traded or substituted for the other? 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

“…the problems of three little people don’t amount to a hill of beans in this crazy world.” Utilitarianism doesn’t always have a cold and calculating face—we perform utilitarian calculations in everyday life. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Part Four. Act and Rule Utilitarianism 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Act and Rule Utilitarianism Act utilitarianism Looks at the consequences of each individual act and calculate utility each time the act is performed. Rule utilitarianism Looks at the consequences of having everyone follow a particular rule and calculates the overall utility of accepting or rejecting the rule. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

An Example Imagine the following scenario. A prominent and much-loved leader has been rushed to the hospital, grievously wounded by an assassin’s bullet. He needs a heart and lung transplant immediately to survive. No suitable donors are available, but there is a homeless person in the emergency room who is being kept alive on a respirator, who probably has only a few days to live, and who is a perfect donor. Without the transplant, the leader will die; the homeless person will die in a few days anyway. Security at the hospital is very well controlled. The transplant team could hasten the death of the homeless person and carry out the transplant without the public ever knowing that they killed the homeless person for his organs. What should they do? For rule utilitarians, this is an easy choice. No one could approve a general rule that lets hospitals kill patients for their organs when they are going to die anyway. The consequences of adopting such a general rule would be highly negative and would certainly undermine public trust in the medical establishment. For act utilitarians, the situation is more complex. If secrecy were guaranteed, the overall consequences might be such that in this particular instance greater utility is produced by hastening the death of the homeless person and using his organs for the transplant. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

The Continuing Dispute Rule utilitarians claim: In particular cases, act utilitarianism can justify disobeying important moral rules and violating individual rights. Act utilitarianism also takes too much time to calculate in each and every case. Act utilitarians respond: Following a rule in a particular case when the overall utility demands that we violate the rule is just rule-worship. If the consequences demand it, we should violate the rule. Furthermore, act utilitarians can follow rules-of-thumb (accumulated wisdom based on consequences in the past) most of the time and engage in individual calculation only when there is some pressing reason for doing so. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Part Five. Criticisms of Utilitarianism Responsibility Integrity Intentions Moral Luck Who does the calculating? Who is included? 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

1. Responsibility Utilitarianism suggests that we are responsible for all the consequences of our choices. The problem is that sometimes we can foresee consequences of other people’s actions that are taken in response to our own acts. Are we responsible for those actions, even though we don’t choose them or approve of them? Discuss Bernard Williams’ example of Jim in the village Imagine a terrorist situation where the terrorists say that they will kill their hostages if we do not meet their demands. We refuse to meet their demands. Are we responsible for what happens to the hostages? Imagine someone like Sadam Hussein putting children in targets likely to be bombed in order to deter bombing by the United States. If we bomb our original targets, are we responsible if those children are killed by our bombing? 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

2. Integrity Utilitarianism often demands that we put aside self-interest. Sometimes this means putting aside our own moral convictions. Discuss Bernard Williams on the chemist example. Develop a variation on Jim in the village, substituting a mercenary soldier and then Martin Luther King, Jr. for Jim. Does this substitution make a difference? Integrity may involve certain identity-conferring commitments, such that the violation of those commitments entails a violation of who we are at our core. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

3. Intentions Utilitarianism is concerned almost exclusively about consequences, not intentions. There is a version of utilitarianism called “motive utilitarianism,” developed by Robert Adams, that attempts to correct this. Intentions may matter is morally assessing an agent, even if they don’t matter in terms of guiding action. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

4. Moral Luck By concentrating exclusively on consequences, utilitarianism makes the moral worth of our actions a matter of luck. We must await the final consequences before we find out if our action was good or bad. This seems to make the moral life a matter of chance, which runs counter to our basic moral intuitions. We can imagine actions with good intentions that have unforeseeable and unintended bad consequences We can also imagine actions with bad intentions that have unforeseeable and unintended good conseqeunces. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

5. Who does the calculating? Historically, this was an issue for the British in India. The British felt they wanted to do what was best for India, but that they were the ones to judge what that was. See Ragavan Iyer, Utilitarianism and All That Typically, the count differs depending on who does the counting In Vietnam, Americans could never understand how much independence counted for the Vietnamese. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

6. Who is included? When we consider the issue of consequences, we must ask who is included within that circle. Those in our own group (group egoism) Those in our own country (nationalism) Those who share our skin color (racism) All human beings (humanism or speciesism?) All sentient beings Classical utilitarianism has often claimed that we should acknowledge the pain and suffering of animals and not restrict the calculus just to human beings. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman

Concluding Assessment Utilitarianism is most appropriate for policy decisions, as long as a strong notion of fundamental human rights guarantees that it will not violate rights of small minorities. 1/2/2019 ©Lawrence M. Hinman