Aquinas and Natural Law Ethics

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Aristotle + God Al-Farabi Al-Ghazali CE Al- Kindi CE CE Averroes CE Avicenna CE Anselm
Advertisements

Ethics LL.B. STUDIES 2015 LECTURE 5. TELEOLOGY Teleology: basic idea Humans’ deeds are purposive by nature; they aim at something. An attempt to ground.
NATURAL LAW ARISTOTLE AND HAPPINESS. Who was Aristotle? Born in 384 BC in Stagyra, Macedonia. Son of a wealthy court physician. Studied in Plato’s Academy.
Summa Theologica Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
The Cosmological Argument.
Chapter 6 The God of the Philosophers.  What is Scholastic Philosophy?  Answer: The Christian philosophy of the Middle Ages that combined faith and.
History of Philosophy Lecture 12 Thomas Aquinas
AS Philosophy & Ethics Mrs Sudds What are your expectations?
Plato On the Nature of The Good The SunThe Good is… that makes… to the.
“A man without ethics is a wild beast loosed upon this world.”
Aquinas’ Theory of Natural Law Based on two fundamental authorities: a.The Bible; b.Aristotle.
Deontological Ethics Is saving someone from drowning a morally praiseworthy act? Do motives play any role in whether an act is morally praiseworthy?
We are learning the different precepts of Aquinas’ theory.
Natural Moral Law Aquinas and Reason. This theory is absolute and deontological, this means that it is concerned with ‘action’. In his work “Summa Theological.
Morality in the Modern World. Where does morality come from?
Review for Intro to Western Philosophy Test DO NOW: Take out all notes and handouts that you have for this class. This review will touch on the major themes,
MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY. STOICISM  The term "Stoicism" derives from the Greek word "stoa," referring to a colonnade, such as those built outside or inside.
Ethics Overview: Deontological and Teleological ( Consequentalist) Systems.
Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition.
Virtue and Natural Law. Natural law theory (Aquinas) Eternal law: law of nature governing universe Natural law: governs what things should do or be A.
Anselm & Aquinas. Anselm of Canterbury ( AD) The Ontological Argument for the Existence of God (Text, pp )
Natural Law – Revision. The spec – What you need to know Main features of the theory That it is absolutist and deontological The relationship that Aquinas.
Lesson Objective: Lesson Outcomes: Lesson Objective: Lesson Outcomes: Mr M Banner 2016 Grade 12 th May 2016 Starter: What does Cosmology mean to you? Title:
Virtue Ethics: The goal of life is well-being (happiness) and the means to attain it is by acquiring a virtuous character.
St. Thomas Aquinas Ronald F. White, Ph.D. Professor of Philosophy
The Cosmological Argument
Natural Law and Thomas Aquinas
Ethics: Theory and Practice
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT 1
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant
Making Moral Decisions
Chapter 1: A Moral Theory Primer
Contemporary Moral Problems
Basic Moral Perspectives
Making Moral Decisions
Natural Law Ethics Always act so as to pursue good and to avoid evil.
Thomas Aquinas 13th-Century scholar in the Dominican order 1.
Challenges to the OAs The different versions of OA are challenged by:
Michael Lacewing Mackie’s error theory Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Administration in International Organizations 2015 TELEOLOGY
Divine Command Theory.
The Stoics were a school of Greek philosophy that started just after the time of Aristotle, and remained popular for about 400 years. human nature as part.
What is Philosophy?.
Natural Law – Bernard Hoose’s Proportionalism
Absolutism.
Forms and the Good.
St. Thomas Aquinas. Contents  1. Biography  II. Philosophy and Theology  III. Proofs of God’s Existence  IV. Knowledge of God’s Nature  V. Creation.
The Problem of Evil.
The Via Negativa Starter: What is it?
Absolute and Relative Morality
Plato On the Nature of The Good
Kant’s Categorical Imperative - revision
THOMAS AQUINAS ( ) DISTINCTION BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY& THEOLOGY, NATURAL & SUPERNATURAL ENDS A SYNTHESIS OF THE PLATONIC-AUGUSTINIAN & THE ARISTOTELIAN.
Plato On the Nature of The Good
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Natural Law – Bernard Hoose’s Proportionalism
Plato On the Nature of The Good
1 A The Cosmological Argument Kalam Argument
Discussion Point Is there a natural order in the universe? List the evidence for and against. Are there any moral beliefs held by most or all people which.
Write this title in your notes!
01 4 Ethical Language 4.1 Meta-Ethics.
The goodness or evil of human acts (deciding between Good and Evil)
Philosophy of Religion Arguments for the existence of God
By the end of this lesson you will have:
What is the ideal cup of tea like?
Traditional Ethical Theories
Administration in International Organizations 2018 TELEOLOGY
TELEOLOGY AND VIRTUE ETHICS
Presentation transcript:

Aquinas and Natural Law Ethics Aristotle + God

*All images link to scholarly articles Ockham Al-Farabi Avicenna Anselm Averroes 870-950 CE 1287-1347 AD 980-1037 CE 1038-1109 AD 1126-1198 CE 900 1300 Al- Kindi Al-Ghazali Maimonides Aquinas 801-873 CE 1058-1111 CE 1138-1204 AD 1225-1274 AD *All images link to scholarly articles

Thomas Aquinas Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) Aquinas was dubbed “the dumb ox” by his fellow students, for being large and quiet. He was apparently quiet because he was busy thinking; he became the Catholic church’s top theologian, a title he still holds today, without dispute.

Major Work Aquinas’s major work, the Summa Theologica, is divided into 4 parts. Prima Pars (1st Part) Existence and Nature of God Prima Secundae (1st Part of the 2nd Part) Happiness, Psychology, Virtues, Law (Human, Natural, Divine) Secunda Secundae (2nd Part of the 2nd Part) The virtues in detail Tertia Pars (3rd Part) Christian Doctrine

Aquinas and Aristotle During the Middle Ages, many of Aristotle’s works were lost to Western Europe, beginning in the first few centuries AD. Aquinas merged Aristotle with Christianity after the recovery of his philosophy via Muslim scholars in the 12th and 13th century. The ‘purposiveness’ or ‘end-directedness’ of nature in Aristotle is identified by Aquinas with God’s purposes.

Natural Law Human nature determines what is ‘natural’ in ‘Natural Law’. Viewed from the human perspective, the principles of natural law are knowable by human nature and are structured to aid in furthering individual and communal goods. God’s commands determine what is ‘lawful’ in ‘Natural Law’. Viewed from God’s perspective, humans participate in the Eternal Law, which is God’s eternal plan— “A law is a rule of action put in place by someone who has care of the community” –Mark Murphy

Normative Theory Aquinas’s first principle of morality is: Good should be done, and evil avoided We are by nature inclined toward the Good, according to Aquinas, but we cannot pursue the good directly because it is abstract—we must pursue concrete goods which we know immediately, by inclination. Those goods are: Preservation of life Procreation Knowledge Society Reasonable Conduct

Normative Theory Aquinas, then, has a value-based ethical theory. The rightness or wrongness of particular actions is determined by how those actions further or frustrate the goods. Certain ways of acting are “intrinsically flawed” or “unreasonable” responses to these human goods. Like Aristotle, Aquinas seems sure there can be no formula provided to determine what action is right or wrong in all particular cases. Prudence (practical wisdom) is required for the most part, if not always, to determine if a given act is intrinsically flawed or not.

Intrinsically Flawed Action Murphy provides a nice account of how acts can be intrinsically flawed or unreasonable: Aquinas does not obviously identify some master principle that one can use to determine whether an act is intrinsically flawed … though he does indicate where to look -- we are to look at the features that individuate acts, such as their objects …, their ends …, their circumstances …, and so forth. An act might be flawed through a mismatch of object and end -- that is, between the immediate aim of the action and its more distant point. If one were, for example, to regulate one's pursuit of a greater good in light of a lesser good -- if, for example, one were to seek friendship with God for the sake of mere bodily survival rather than vice versa -- that would count as an unreasonable act. An act might be flawed through the circumstances: while one is bound to profess one's belief in God, there are certain circumstances in which it is inappropriate to do so…. An act might be flawed merely through its intention: to direct oneself against a good -- as in murder …, and lying …, and blasphemy … -- is always to act in an unfitting way. –Mark Murphy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-law-ethics/

Fit with Utilitarians and Kantians Is an action ever intrinsically flawed because it fails to maximize goodness? Murphy, again: His natural law view understands principles of right to be grounded in principles of good; on this Aquinas sides with utilitarians, and consequentialists generally, against Kantians.  But Aquinas would deny that the principles of the right enjoin us to maximize the good -- while he allows that considerations of the greater good have a role in practical reasoning, action can be irremediably flawed merely through (e.g.) badness of intention, flawed such that no good consequences that flow from the action would be sufficient to justify it -- and in this Aquinas sides with the Kantians against the utilitarians and consequentialists of other stripes. –Mark Murphy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-law-ethics/

Fit with Aristotle Must prudence determine the right action in every situation, or are there at least some universal general rules that are always valid or correct? And while Aquinas is in some ways Aristotelian, and recognizes that virtue will always be required in order to hit the mark in a situation of choice, he rejects the view commonly ascribed to Aristotle (for doubts that it is Aristotle's view; see Irwin 2000) that there are no universally true general principles of right. – Mark Murphy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-law- ethics/

Photo Credits… Title Slide: Library, St. Paul’s College, Washington, D.C. http://www.flickr.com/photos/lricecsp/2365699386

3 Slides on the Metaphysics of Goodness

Plato: On the Nature of The Good Mind Analogy of the Sun The Sun The Good is… that makes… to the … through the power of… by providing … a visible object objects visible eye sight light an intelligible object objects intelligible soul understanding truth The tree above is the visible object, the Forms (Universals) are the intelligible objects that the Good shines on. Both the Sun and the Good create their objects. http://www.boisestate.edu/people/troark/didactics/ancient/materials/Line_Sun.pdf

Aristotle: On the Nature of The Good as a transcendental property Substance Quality Place Position Action Quantity Relation Time Possession Passion Socrates is white is in Athens is seated is speaking is one is a friend to Plato it is noon has a toga is being spoken to Is it odd that ‘good’ can be predicated in any of the 10 categories?

Aquinas: On the Nature of The Good God = Being = The Good Angels Humans Animals Plants Rocks Mud Nothingness The Great Chain of Being Actuality Potentiality Aquinas gets the chain from Plotinus (his student, Porphyry), Augustine, Boethius, Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, and others, and adds to it

‘Ontological Proof’ of God’s Existence Suppose there are 4 modes of existence: 1. Necessary 2. Actual 3. Possible 4. Impossible If a perfect being is possible, it must be actual, because it's more perfect to be actual than just possible. The argument succeeds. But there's more: if a perfect being is actual, it must be necessary, for the same reason ... it's more perfect to be necessary than just actual. SO ... a necessary being that is all good, all powerful, and all knowing, exists. Necessary beings can have no cause of their existence (except trivially themselves), and so it is confusion to ask who made God. God actually explains the existence of himself and everything else.

Objections to the Argument Objection: But is ‘existence’ a real predicate? A feature a thing may have or lack? Response: It isn't claimed that there is a possible perfect being. It's just pointed out that a perfect being is possible, or ‘perfect being’ is contradiction free. Think of it this way: there are red things. For them to exist, there did not have to be possible red things capable of having or lacking the property ‘existence’. 'What it is to be red', though, had to predate red things. What it is to be a perfect being predates, logically, but not temporally, a perfect being. The argument is one of reason, not causation. Does that make sense? There's nothing contradictory about a perfect being if that being is a person (personal qualities admit of perfection, unlike physical qualities ... no such thing as a perfect island, for instance, because you can always add another nice palm tree or nubian maiden ... but personal qualities, like knowledge, power, and goodness, have intrinsic maxima ... they have upper limits which, when met, yield perfection of that quality.