Atom Chip Group, Ben Gurion University, Beersheba, Israel

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Tony Short University of Cambridge (with Sabri Al-Safi – PRA 84, (2011))
Advertisements

I NFORMATION CAUSALITY AND ITS TESTS FOR QUANTUM COMMUNICATIONS I- Ching Yu Host : Prof. Chi-Yee Cheung Collaborators: Prof. Feng-Li Lin (NTNU) Prof. Li-Yi.
Postulates of Quantum Mechanics. The Fundamental Rules of Our Game Any measurement we can make with an experiment corresponds to a mathematical “operator”
Quantum Information Stephen M. Barnett University of Strathclyde The Wolfson Foundation.
Integrals over Operators
Quantum One: Lecture 4. Schrödinger's Wave Mechanics for a Free Quantum Particle.
Nonlocal Boxes And All That Daniel Rohrlich Atom Chip Group, Ben Gurion University, Beersheba, Israel 21 January 2010.
Bell inequality & entanglement
Bell’s inequalities and their uses Mark Williamson The Quantum Theory of Information and Computation
Wavefunction Quantum mechanics acknowledges the wave-particle duality of matter by supposing that, rather than traveling along a definite path, a particle.
Quantum fermions from classical statistics. quantum mechanics can be described by classical statistics !
Quantum Mechanics from Classical Statistics. what is an atom ? quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum field theory.
Chapter 3 Formalism. Hilbert Space Two kinds of mathematical constructs - wavefunctions (representing the system) - operators (representing observables)
4. The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics 4A. Revisiting Representations
P460 - many particles1 Many Particle Systems can write down the Schrodinger Equation for a many particle system with x i being the coordinate of particle.
Quantum information and the monogamy of entanglement Aram Harrow (MIT) Brown SUMS March 9, 2013.
Is Communication Complexity Physical? Samuel Marcovitch Benni Reznik Tel-Aviv University arxiv
6. Second Quantization and Quantum Field Theory
Physics 3 for Electrical Engineering Ben Gurion University of the Negev
MSEG 803 Equilibria in Material Systems 6: Phase space and microstates Prof. Juejun (JJ) Hu
Physics 3 for Electrical Engineering
In 1887,when Photoelectric Effect was first introduced by Heinrich Hertz, the experiment was not able to be explained using classical principles.
Feynman Festival, Olomouc, June 2009 Antonio Acín N. Brunner, N. Gisin, Ll. Masanes, S. Massar, M. Navascués, S. Pironio, V. Scarani Quantum correlations.
Steering witnesses and criteria for the (non-)existence of local hidden state (LHS) models Eric Cavalcanti, Steve Jones, Howard Wiseman Centre for Quantum.
The Quantum Theory of Atoms and Molecules The Schrödinger equation and how to use wavefunctions Dr Grant Ritchie.
Physics 3 for Electrical Engineering Ben Gurion University of the Negev
The Higgs Boson Observation (probably) Not just another fundamental particle… July 27, 2012Purdue QuarkNet Summer Workshop1 Matthew Jones Purdue University.
Hirophysics.com PATRICK ABLES. Hirophysics.com PART 1 TIME DILATION: GPS, Relativity, and other applications.
Unit 13 Relativity.
Monday, Apr. 4, 2005PHYS 3446, Spring 2005 Jae Yu 1 PHYS 3446 – Lecture #16 Monday, Apr. 4, 2005 Dr. Jae Yu Symmetries Why do we care about the symmetry?
Non-Locality Swapping and emergence of quantum correlations Nicolas Brunner Paul Skrzypczyk, Sandu Popescu University of Bristol.
Quantum Non-locality: From Bell to Information Causality Alex Thompson Physics 486 March 7, 2016.
Non-locality and quantum games Dmitry Kravchenko University of Latvia Theory days at Jõulumäe, 2008.
Quantum nonlocality based on finite-speed causal influences
The Quantum Theory of Atoms and Molecules
Systems of Identical Particles
Mathematical Formulation of the Superposition Principle
Q. M. Particle Superposition of Momentum Eigenstates Partially localized Wave Packet Photon – Electron Photon wave packet description of light same.
Formalism Chapter 3.
Postulates of Quantum Mechanics
Quantum Information Promises new insights Anthony J
Simulating entanglement without communication
Unusual Interactions of Pre- and Post-Selected Particles
Special Theory of Relativity
ICNFP, Kolymbari, Crete, Greece August 28 – September 5, 2013
Quantum One.
Quantum mechanics from classical statistics
Quantum One.
Schrodinger Equation The equation describing the evolution of Ψ(x,t) is the Schrodinger equation Given suitable initial conditions (Ψ(x,0)) Schrodinger’s.
Study of nonlocal correlations in macroscopic measurement scenario
4. The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics 4A. Revisiting Representations
Quantum Two.
Quantum One.
Concept test 15.1 Suppose at time
Quantum One.
Quantum Two.
Quantum Foundations Lecture 20
Quantum One.
The Stale of a System Is Completely Specified by lts Wave Function
13. The Weak Law and the Strong Law of Large Numbers
Signals and Systems Lecture 3
Total Energy is Conserved.
The Basic (Fundamental) Postulate of Statistical Mechanics
“counterfactual communication”?
Linear Vector Space and Matrix Mechanics
Linear Vector Space and Matrix Mechanics
16. Mean Square Estimation
13. The Weak Law and the Strong Law of Large Numbers
Experimental test of nonlocal causality
Quantum One.
Presentation transcript:

Atom Chip Group, Ben Gurion University, Beersheba, Israel Stronger-than-quantum correlations violate relativistic causality in the classical limit Daniel Rohrlich Atom Chip Group, Ben Gurion University, Beersheba, Israel 26 February 2012

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

Axioms for special relativity The laws of physics are the same in all inertial reference frames. There is a maximum signalling speed, and it is the speed of light c.

Axioms for quantum mechanics Physical states are normalized vectors ψ(r), Ψ(r,t), , . Measurable physical quantities – “observables” – correspond to Hermitian or (self-adjoint) operators on the state vectors. If a system is an eigenstate with eigenvalue a of an observable , then a measurement of on will yield a. Conversely, if a measurement of on any state yields a, the measurement leaves the system in an eigenstate . The probability that a system in a normalized state can be found in the state is .

Axioms for quantum mechanics The time evolution of a quantum state is given by where is the Hamiltonian (kinetic energy + potential energy) of the system in the state . The wave function of identical fermions (spin ½, ¾,…) must be antisymmetric under exchange of any pair of them; the wave function of identical bosons (spin 0, 1,…) must be symmetric under exchange of any pair of them. ²

“It’s like trying to derive special relativity from the wrong axioms “It’s like trying to derive special relativity from the wrong axioms.” – Yakir Aharonov Fast objects contract in the direction of their motion. Moving clocks slow down. Twins cannot agree about who is the oldest. The observer determines the results of measurements. …

H. Poincaré (1909) “La mécanique nouvelle” [“The new mechanics”] “One needs to make still a third hypothesis, much more surprising, much more difficult to accept, one which is of much hindrance to what we are currently used to. A body in translational motion suffers a deformation in the direction in which it is displaced.”

Question: What, indeed, is so “special” about special relativity? Answer: The two axioms so nearly contradict each other that only a unique theory reconciles them. Y. Aharonov and (independently) A. Shimony: Quantum mechanics, as well, reconciles two things that nearly contradict each other:

Question: What, indeed, is so “special” about special relativity? Answer: The two axioms so nearly contradict each other that only a unique theory reconciles them. Y. Aharonov and (independently) A. Shimony: Quantum mechanics, as well, reconciles two things that nearly contradict each other: Nonlocality

No signalling Nonlocality Question: What, indeed, is so “special” about special relativity? Answer: The two axioms so nearly contradict each other that only a unique theory reconciles them. Y. Aharonov and (independently) A. Shimony: Quantum mechanics, as well, reconciles two things that nearly contradict each other: Nonlocality No signalling

Can we derive a part quantum mechanics from these two axioms? 1. Nonlocal correlations 2. Relativistic causality

Alice and Bob share entangled pairs. They measure a, a′, b, and b′ – physical quantities having values ±1. Alice measures a or a′ CHSH inequality |CL(a,b)+CL(a,b′)+CL(a′,b)−CL(a′,b′)| ≤ 2 Tsirelson’s bound |CQ(a,b)+CQ(a,b′)+CQ(a′,b)−CQ(a′,b′)| ≤ 2 Bob measures b or b′ drawings by Tom Oreb © Walt Disney Co.

Alice and Bob share entangled pairs. They measure a, a′, b, and b′ – physical quantities having values ±1. Alice measures a or a′ CHSH inequality (locality) |CL(a,b)+CL(a,b′)+CL(a′,b)−CL(a′,b′)| ≤ 2 Tsirelson’s bound |CQ(a,b)+CQ(a,b′)+CQ(a′,b)−CQ(a′,b′)| ≤ 2 Bob measures b or b′ drawings by Tom Oreb © Walt Disney Co.

Alice and Bob share entangled pairs. They measure a, a′, b, and b′ – physical quantities having values ±1. Alice measures a or a′ CHSH inequality (locality) |CL(a,b)+CL(a,b′)+CL(a′,b)−CL(a′,b′)| ≤ 2 Tsirelson’s bound (relativistic causality?) |CQ(a,b)+CQ(a,b′)+CQ(a′,b)−CQ(a′,b′)| ≤ 2 Bob measures b or b′ drawings by Tom Oreb © Walt Disney Co.

For any measurement of a, a′, b, and b′, let the outcomes 1 and −1 be equally likely. Let CPR(a,b) = CPR(a,b′) = CPR(a′,b) = 1 = −CPR(a′,b′). Superquantum/maximally nonlocal box/PR-box correlations A A′ B B′ 45º 45º 45º Then CPR(a,b)+CPR(a,b′)+CPR(a′,b)−CPR(a′,b′) = 4. S. Popescu and DR, Found. Phys. 24 (1994) 379

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

It should not be so easy to disprove such a lovely conjecture!

More recent results: PR-box renders all communication complexity problems trivial. W. van Dam, Thesis, U. Oxford (1999); W. van Dam, preprint quant-ph/0501159 (2005) Stronger-than-quantum correlations may render communication complexity problems trivial. G. Brassard et al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 96 (2006) 250401 Most stronger-than-quantum correlations violate “information causality”. M. Pawłowski et al., Nature 461 (2009) 1101

Stronger-than-quantum correlations do not survive in the macroscopic (classical) limit. M. Navascués and H. Wunderlich, Proc. R. Soc. A 466 (2010) 881

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

PR-box correlations Suppose Alice measures a. She knows that if Bob measures b, he obtains b = a. If he measures b′, he obtain b′ = a.

PR-box correlations Suppose Alice measures a′. She knows that if Bob measures b, he obtains b = a′. If he measures b′, he obtain b′ = –a′.

PR-box correlations Suppose Alice measures a. She knows that b = b′. Suppose Alice measures a′. She knows that b = –b′.

PR-box correlations Suppose Alice measures a. She knows that b = b′. Suppose Alice measures a′. She knows that b = –b′. We might call a, a′, b and b′ (maximally) nonlocal hidden variables.

PR-box correlations All that stops Alice from signalling to Bob is complementarity between Bob’s measuring b and his measuring b′, even though (from Alice’s point of view) no uncertainty principle governs b and b′. Alice can even prepare ensembles (e.g. by measuring a and postselecting a = 1) in which Δb = 0 = Δb′. Complementarity is a

PR-box correlations All that stops Alice from signalling to Bob is complementarity between Bob’s measuring b and his measuring b′, even though (from Alice’s point of view) no uncertainty principle governs b and b′. Alice can even prepare ensembles (e.g. by measuring a and postselecting a = 1) in which Δb = 0 = Δb′. Complementarity is a for the PR-box.

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

Minimal, physical additional axiom: a classical limit Quantum mechanics has a classical limit. In this limit there are no noncommuting quantum observables; there are only jointly measurable macroscopic observables. This classical limit – our direct experience – is an inherent constraint, a kind of boundary condition, on quantum mechanics and on any generalization of quantum mechanics. Thus stronger-than-quantum correlations, too, must have a classical limit.

PR-box correlations Now suppose Alice measures just a or just a′ on N pairs. Define macroscopic observables B and B′: Alice already knows the values of B and B′, and there must be “weak” measurements that Bob can make to obtain partial information about both B and B′: there is no complementarity in the classical limit! On average both B and B′ vanish, but if Alice measures a, B and B′ will of order 1/√N and correlated; if she measures a′, B and B′ will of order 1/√N and anti-correlated.

Alice and Bob can measure exponentially many pairs (in groups of N) Alice and Bob can measure exponentially many pairs (in groups of N). Their expenses and exertions don’t concern us. Ultimately, Alice will be able to signal to Bob by consistently measuring a or a′. What matters is only that when Bob detects a correlation, it is more likely that Alice measured a than when he detects an anti-correlation. If not, Bob's measurements yield zero information about B or about B′, contradicting the axiom of a classical limit in which B and B′ are jointly measurable. drawings by Tom Oreb © Walt Disney Co.

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

What about weaker-than-PR-box correlations? In the classical limit, Bob has some information about both B and B′, hence some information about B ± B′. However, B + B′ = 0 if Alice measures only a′, while B + B′ fluctuates binomially if Alice measures only a. Either way , but the standard deviation Δa(B + B′) or Δa′(B + B′) reveals to him Alice’s message. What about weaker-than-PR-box correlations? What about a correlation C(a,b) such that C(a,b) = C(a,b′) = C(a′,b) = C = −C(a′,b′) for some constant –1 < C < 1? drawings by Tom Oreb © Walt Disney Co.

If C is close enough to 1, it will still be possible for Alice to signal to Bob. But for some critical C, it will not be possible. Is the critical C equal to CQ = /2? What about weaker-than-PR-box correlations? What about a correlation C(a,b) such that C(a,b) = C(a,b′) = C(a′,b) = C = −C(a′,b′) for some constant –1 < C < 1? drawings by Tom Oreb © Walt Disney Co.

If C is close enough to 1, it will still be possible for Alice to signal to Bob. But for some critical C, it will not be possible. Is the critical C equal to CQ = /2? Note that C does not determine B + B′ . It only determines a range for B + B′ . drawings by Tom Oreb © Walt Disney Co.

Question: Alice measures a. If Bob measures b, what are the probabilities p± that he obtains b = ±a? Answer: p+ + p– = 1 and p+ – p– = C, hence p± = (1 ± C)/2. If Bob measures b′, the probabilities that he obtains b′ = ±a are the same. Likewise if Alice measures a′, the probabilities that Bob obtains b = ±a′ are the same. But the probabilities that Bob obtains b′ = ±a′ are (1 C)/2.

p+ p− maximize Δa(B + B′) minimize Δa(B + B′) Δa(B + B′ ) ≥ 2 C

p+ p− maximize Δa(B + B′) minimize Δa(B + B′) Δa(B + B′ ) ≥ 2 C minimize Δa′(B + B′) maximize Δa′(B + B′) Δa′(B + B′ ) ≤ 2 C

If Δa′(B + B′ ) ≠ Δa′(B + B′ ), then Alice can signal to Bob.

If Δa′(B + B′ ) ≠ Δa′(B + B′ ), then Alice can signal to Bob. If C > 1/2, then Δa′(B + B′ ) ≤ 2 ≠ 2 ≤ Δa(B + B′ ).

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

Bell’s theorem Hidden variables Locality C ≤ 1/2

Relativistic causality Bell’s theorem? Relativistic causality Classical limit Hidden variables C ≤ 1/2

Relativistic causality Bell’s theorem? Relativistic causality Classical limit ? Hidden variables Locality C ≤ 1/2

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

The PR-box tells us nothing about Δa(B + B′ ) and Δa′(B + B′ ). But the classical limit tells us to think “outside the PR-box”.

The PR-box tells us nothing about Δa(B + B′ ) and Δa′(B + B′ ). But the classical limit tells us to think “outside the PR-box”.

Lemma Therefore and hence relativistic causality requires

Back to the correlations C(a,b), C(a,b′), C(a′,b) and C(a′,b′) . Suppose Alice measures a on sets of N pairs. If we define then A takes values –1, –1+2/N, –1+4/N,…,1–2/N, 1 in a perfect binomial distribution. If A = 1 – 2n/N, then B + B′ ≈ (1 – 2n/N)[C(a,b)+C(a,b′)]

Back to the correlations C(a,b), C(a,b′), C(a′,b) and C(a′,b′) . Suppose Alice measures a on sets of N pairs. If we define then A takes values –1, –1+2/N, –1+4/N,…,1–2/N, 1 in a perfect binomial distribution. If A = 1 – 2n/N, then B + B′ ≈ (1 – 2n/N)[C(a,b)+C(a,b′)].

[C(a,b)+C(a,b′)]/ ≤ Δa(B + B′ ) Back to the correlations C(a,b), C(a,b′), C(a′,b) and C(a′,b′) . Suppose Alice measures a on sets of N pairs. If we define then A takes values –1, –1+2/N, –1+4/N,…,1–2/N, 1 in a perfect binomial distribution. If A = 1 – 2n/N, then B + B′ ≈ (1 – 2n/N)[C(a,b)+C(a,b′)]. The minimum Δa(B + B′) (a convolution of ΔaA and “noise”) is for B + B′ = (1 – 2n/N)[C(a,b)+C(a,b′)], i.e. [C(a,b)+C(a,b′)]/ ≤ Δa(B + B′ ) [C(a′,b)–C(a′,b′)]/ ≤ Δa′(B – B′ ) Similarly

[C(a,b)+C(a,b′)]/ ≤ Δa(B + B′ ) Now [C(a,b)+C(a,b′)]/ ≤ Δa(B + B′ ) [C(a′,b)–C(a′,b′)]/ ≤ Δa′(B – B′ )

Now

|C(a′,b)–C(a′,b′)|2 = 4 – |C(a,b)+C(a,b′)|2 i.e. To maximize |C(a,b) + C(a,b′) + C(a′,b) – C(a′,b′)| we should saturate this bound, so that |C(a′,b)–C(a′,b′)|2 = 4 – |C(a,b)+C(a,b′)|2 and so we maximize with z = |C(a,b) + C(a,b′)|,

to derive Tsirelson’s bound, from the axioms of nonlocality, relativistic causality and the existence of a classical limit!

to derive Tsirelson’s bound, from the axioms of nonlocality, relativistic causality and the existence of a classical limit!

Outline What is a PR-box Why I hate the PR-box The PR-box is rotten Killing off the PR-box Killing off all stronger-than-quantum boxes A paradox A miraculous derivation of Tsirelson’s bound From quantum correlations to Hilbert space

By applying the constraint Δa(B + B′ ) = Δa′(B + B′ ) so that there will be no signalling, we have found that the maximal correlation is the quantum correlation, CQ= /2. The maximal correlation implies that when Alice measures a and obtains ±1, Bob measures b+b′ (not the same as measuring b or b′) and obtains ±2CQ.

By applying the constraint Δa(B + B′ ) = Δa′(B + B′ ) so that there will be no signalling, we have found that the maximal correlation is the quantum correlation, CQ= /2. The maximal correlation implies that when Alice measures a and obtains ±1, Bob measures b+b′ (not the same as measuring b or b′) and obtains ±2CQ. The fact that the linear combination (b + b′)/2CQ = (b + b′)/ of variables taking values ±1 is another variable taking values ±1 shows that b and b′ add as vectors, and not as scalars.