Ethical Theories: Introduction Nanoethics Lecture II

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Utilitarianism Maximize good.
Advertisements

EVIL IS STILL A PROBLEM!!!.
MORALITY AND ETHICS (cont.)
Ethical Theories: Conclusion Nanoethics Lecture III
Frameworks for Moral Arguments
The Main Philosophical Approaches To Morality
Introduction to Ethics
Morality.
Ethical Theory.
Phil 160 Kant.
Chapter Seven: Utilitarianism
Ethics and Morality Theory Part 2 11 September 2006.
Ethics and ethical systems 12 January
COMP 381. Agenda  TA: Caitlyn Losee  Books and movies nominations  Team presentation signup Beginning of class End of class  Rawls and Moors.
Ethics & Computers Sources: “The Right Thing to Do”, P. Aarne Vesilind, Lakeshore Press, 2004, (ISBN ) “Ethics for the Information Age”, Michael.
How Actions Can Be Morally Evaluated l Teleological Ethics: morality is the means to achieve what is identified as good or valuable l Deontological Ethics:
How Actions Can Be Morally Evaluated l Teleological Ethics: morality is the means to achieve what is identified as good or valuable l Deontological Ethics:
Standards of Conduct DoD’s Standards of Conduct
Normative Ethical Theory Jim Okapal Asst. Professor of Philosophy Missouri Western State University.
Rosalind Hursthouse: Virtue Theory and Abortion
THEORIES ABOUT RIGHT ACTION (ETHICAL THEORIES)
Ethics and Ethical Theories
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Chapter One: Moral Reasons
PHIL 2 Philosophy: Ethics in Contemporary Society
What is the right thing to do?
Introduction to Ethical Theory I Last session: “our focus will be on normative medical ethics, i.e., how people should behave in medical situations” –
“A man without ethics is a wild beast loosed upon this world.”
© 2002, Karey Perkins The Commandant Example  The Baby? - or-  The 5,000?
Utilitarianism or Consequentialism Good actions are those that result in good consequences. The moral value of an action is extrinsic to the action itself.
Ethics A look at the reasons behind decisions about what is right and wrong. What is the right thing to do?
Consequentialism Is it OK to inflict pain on someone else? Is it OK to inflict pain on someone else? What if it is a small amount of pain to prevent a.
Theories of Morality Kant Bentham Aristotle. Morality  Morality: Action for the sake of principle  Guides our beliefs about right and wrong  Sets limits.
Ethical Theories Unit 9 Ethical Awareness. What Are Ethical Theories? - Explain what makes an action right or wrong - Have an overview of major ethical.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 15 Ethics #1 (Intro.) By David Kelsey.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant By David Kelsey.
Traditional Ethical Theories. Reminder Optional Tutorial Monday, February 25, 1-1:50 Room M122.
Theories of Morality Kant Bentham Aristotle. Morality  Morality: Action for the sake of principle  Guides our beliefs about right and wrong  Sets limits.
Chapter One: Moral Reasons Review Applying Ethics: A Text with Readings (10 th ed.) Julie C. Van Camp, Jeffrey Olen, Vincent Barry Cengage Learning/Wadsworth.
AREA 1 GUIDING PRINCIPLES SECTION 3 Consequences (Utilitarian Ethics) Duty and Reason (Kantian Ethics)
From Last Time The good will is the only good thing in an ‘unqualified way” Acting from duty vs. acting in accord with duty Categorical vs. hypothetical.
Revision whizz through relativism A recap from the start: – Teleological and Deontological – Absolutism Plato and the ‘forms’ – Relativism Protagorus Aristotle.
Chapter 3: How Can I Know What is Right?
Ethics Overview: Deontological and Teleological ( Consequentalist) Systems.
Ethics A look at the reasons behind decisions about what is right and wrong. What is the right thing to do?
Basic Framework of Normative Ethics. Normative Ethics ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’ or ‘controls’ ‘Normative’ means something that ‘guides’
Theory of Consequences and Intentions There are two traditional ways of looking at the “rightness” or “wrongness” of an act. 1. Look at the consequences.
MNU Five Other Ethical Systems Dr. Judy Martin Session 7 – February 18, 2014.
Aristotle ( BCE) Virtue Ethics An act is good if and only if it says good things about one’s character Usually weighed by “moderation” of virtue.
EECS 690 January 27, Deontology Typically, when anyone talks about Deontology, they mean to talk about Immanuel Kant. Kant is THE deontologist.
Morality and the Moral Life. Ethics (moral philosophy): The study of morality using the methods of philosophy. Morality: Our beliefs about right and wrong.
What is the right thing to do?
Contemporary Moral Problems
Introduction to Philosophy
Is torture wrong? If so, why?
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant
Chapter 1: A Moral Theory Primer
Ethical reasoning 2 Consequentialism: We can decide the right action (alternative, option, in a decision) by considering consequences, rather than just.
PHIL242: MEDICAL ETHICS SUM2014, M-F, 9:40-10:40, SAV 156
PHIL242: MEDICAL ETHICS SUM2014, M-F, 9:40-10:40, SAV 156
Theory of Health Care Ethics

Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 15 Ethics #1: Utilitarianism
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Immanuel Kant
Theories of Ethics.
Intro to Philosophy Ethical Systems.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 15 Ethics #1 (Intro.)
History of Philosophy Lecture 17 Immanuel Kant’ Ethics
Professional Ethics (GEN301/PHI200) UNIT 2: NORMATIVE THEORIES OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS Handout # 2 CLO # 2 Explain the rationale behind adoption of normative.
Presentation transcript:

Ethical Theories: Introduction Nanoethics Lecture II Roderick T. Long Auburn Dept. of Philosophy

What Are Ethical Theories? Explain what makes an action right or wrong Ethical theories vs. particular ethical judgments Analogy with scientific theories and observations

Some Kinds of Ethical Theory Consequentialism Deontology Virtue Ethics Contractarianism Natural Law Relativism Divine Command Ethics

Consequentialism The rightness/wrongness of an action is determined by its consequences

Consequentialism Example: utilitarianism The right action is the one that promotes the greatest happiness of the greatest number (maximizes social utility)

Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) THESE GUYS AGAIN!

Consequentialism Another example: ethical egoism The right action is the one that promotes the greatest happiness of the agent (maximizes the agent’s utility)

Two Ethical Egoists Benjamin Tucker (1854-1939) Ayn Rand (1905-1982)

Deontology The rightness/wrongness of an action is determined by inherent features of the action itself, or by an inherently valid rule

“The end doesn’t justify the means.” Deontology If an action is of the wrong kind, it is forbidden, no matter how good its consequences are Rejects both Utilitarianism and Ethical Egoism “The end doesn’t justify the means.”

Deontology Example: Kantianism Right actions must be universalizable and must treat rational agents as ends, not mere means (trade-offs forbidden) Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)

Kant’s Deontology Universalizability: must be possible to will the principle of your action for everybody without inconsistency. Lying violates universalizability because lying presupposes and exploits a general practice of telling the truth

Kant’s Deontology Ends, not mere means: don’t treat rational agents (others or yourself) as mere objects to be used or exploited. Personhood is the basis of ethical value and can’t be subordinated to other values. Mustn’t sacrifice the few even to benefit the many.

Virtue Ethics The rightness/wrongness of an action is determined by the character traits it expresses Emphasize what kind of person you should be

Virtue Ethics Examples: Aristotelianism, Confucianism Aristotle (384-322 BCE) Confucius (551-479

Virtue Ethics Virtue-ethicists tend to side with deontologists against consequentialists – though not always

Contractarianism The rightness/wrongness of an action is determined by whether rational people do, or under appropriate conditions would, agree to it Example: John Rawls’ Veil of Ignorance (about which more later on)

Natural Law A body of legal or quasi-legal precepts that: are based in human nature, not convention can be ascertained by human reason set the standard for, and take precedence over, manmade laws

Natural Law “One may well ask: ‘How can you advocate breaking some laws and obeying others?’ The answer lies in the fact that there are two types of laws: just and unjust. I would be the first to advocate obeying just laws. One has not only a legal but a moral responsibility to obey just laws. Conversely, one has a moral responsibility to disobey unjust laws. I would agree with St. Augustine that ‘an unjust law is no law at all.’ …

Letter from Birmingham Jail Natural Law “… Now, what is the difference between the two? How does one determine whether a law is just or unjust? A just law is a manmade code that squares with the moral law or the law of God. An unjust law is a code that is out of harmony with the moral law. To put it in the terms of St. Thomas Aquinas: An unjust law is a human law that is not rooted in eternal law and natural law. Any law that uplifts human personality is just. Any law that degrades human personality is unjust.” – Martin Luther King, Jr., Letter from Birmingham Jail

Natural Law Natural law theories 1. often combine deontology & virtue ethics 2. are sometimes theologically based (Thomas Aquinas, John Locke, Martin Luther King) …

Natural Law … but not necessarily so (Hugo Grotius, Lysander Spooner)

Natural Law … but not necessarily so (Hugo Grotius, Lysander Spooner)

Example of a Natural Law Theory The doctrine of double effect (Aquinas) – If an action has two results, one good one bad, it’s permissible only if a) the good outweighs the bad [consequentialist component] and b) the bad is only foreseen, not intended [non-consequentialist component] Actions individuated by their intentions

Example of a Natural Law Theory So collateral damage OK (civilian deaths foreseen but not part of plan) Dresden/Hiroshima not OK (civilian deaths part of plan) Too strict for many consequentialists Too permissive for many deontologists

Relativism The rightness of an action depends on the approval of some person/group/culture. Allows conflicting moralities: such-and-such is right for group A (because group A approves of it) but wrong for group B (because group B disapproves of it).

Relativism (What most philosophers regard as) bad arguments for relativism: relativism will make us tolerant (but the Nazis were relativists) cultures disagree about moral values (but they disagree about scientific facts too) ethical disagreements can’t be settled (but what’s wrong with reflective equilibration?)

Divine Command Ethics What makes an action right is the fact that God commands it. (As opposed to the view that God commands things because they are right already.) A form of relativism?

Divine Command Ethics Problems for divine command theory: - A perfect being would have good reasons for whatever she commands – but DCE seems to make that impossible - Is it possible to praise God if DCE is true? - God must already be good before she commands, so goodness isn’t reducible to divine commands

Divine Command Ethics Defense of divine command theory: How could God be subject to moral standards he didn’t create? Reply: the standard of morality might be God’s nature rather than God’s will (Thomas Aquinas, c. 1225-1274)

Ethical Theories and Ethical Standing What has ethical standing? - individuals? - communities? - non-human animals? - plants? - the non-living environment?

Ethical Theories and Ethical Standing Kantianism: rational agents only (cruelty to animals bad only because it tends to make you the sort of person who’ll be cruel to people) Contractarianism: only those beings that can enter agreements

Ethical Theories and Ethical Standing Utilitarianism: those beings who can feel pleasure or pain (“The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?” – Jeremy Bentham) Virtue ethics: whatever beings a virtuous person would care about! Divine Command: whatever beings God cares about!

Applying Reflective Equilibration to Ethical Theories Case study: Utilitarianism Advantage: simplicity (analogy with superiority of Newtonian over Aristotelian mechanics) Disadvantage: potential conflict with existing norms

Simplicity in Science: Aristotle vs. Newton Apple falls, moon doesn’t: why? Aristotle: two kinds of matter with different principles of motion. Terrestrial matter has a naturally vertical motion; celestial matter has a naturally circular motion

Simplicity in Science: Aristotle vs. Newton Newton: same laws of motion apply to both. Simplicity: if two theories explain the same phenomena equally well, the one that posits fewer explanatory principles is better.

Simplicity in Ethics: Utilitarianism We ordinarily think beneficial results are one ethical consideration among others. Utilitarianism offers to explain the same range of ethical phenomena equally well by appealing solely to consequences. This would make it a superior theory – if in fact it explains them equally well. Does it?

A Question for Next Time!