Week 4: Deontology.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Non-Consequentialism
Advertisements

What is deontology?.
Morality As Overcoming Self-Interest
The Categorical Imperative
Kant Are there absolute moral laws that we have to follow regardless of consequences? First we want to know what Kant has to say about what moral rule.
Moral law and Kant’s imperatives.
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
Categorical Imperative
Deontology: the Ethics of Duty
Phil 160 Kant.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative and Euthanasia
Kant’s Moral Philosophy
Kantian Ethics Exam Questions
Kant’s deontological ethics
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Kantian ethics (& suicide): Kantian ethics (& suicide): Immanuel Kant ( ). A German philosopher. Ought implies Can Maxims Categorical Imperative.
Immanuel Kant. Two worlds Reason is part of the intelligible world Sensible (Lesser faculty) Part of the world of nature (empirical)
Categorical and Practical Imperative
Immanuel Kant Duty Ethics The moral worth of an action depends on motive (do the right thing for the right reason)
Duties, Rights, and Kant Ethics Dr. Jason M. Chang.
Objectives: SWBAT  Identify Immanuel Kant  Analyze Kantian Rationality  Identify and discuss the Categorical Imperative.
Lecture 6 Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant ( )
Immanuel Kant Deontological Ethics.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant By David Kelsey.
Kant Deontology Categorical Imperative. Immanuel Kant Profile: Dead German Time of Berkley, Rousseau, Hume, Bentham Not a fan of music or arts.
Utilitarianism Objection –Too permissive –Utilitarian response: (1) bite the bullet (2) try to show negative side-effects, long-term consequences –Rebuttal.
Class 6 Kant. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) From Königsberg, Germany.
Utilitarianism Act Utilitarianism: The right act is that which maximizes happiness (only version we’ve been discussing thus far) Rule Utilitarianism: The.
© Michael Lacewing Kant’s Categorical Imperative Michael Lacewing
The Moral Philosophy of Immanuel Kant The Ethics of Duty and Reason
The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Immanuel Kant.
Immanuel Kant and the moral law. Kant (1) Kant’s ethics are those of the deist, rather than the theist. He was an important thinker in the deist project,
Standard Form ► 1. State your position ► 2. 1 st Premise (Fact 1: State fact and source) ► 3. 2 nd Premise (Fact 2: State fact and source) ► 4. 3 rd Premise.
Chapter 7: Ethics Morality and Practical Reason: Kant
Immanuel Kant and the Enlightenment Immanuel Kant: German ( ) Enlightenment: 1700's (18th Century) Applies the new rational scientific method of.
Kantian Ethics Good actions have intrinsic value; actions are good if and only if they follow from a moral law that can be universalized.
Lecture 13 Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant ( )
Duty Ethics.
Ethical theories and approaches in Business
Kantian Ethics.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant
Kantian Ethics Spent virtually all of his life in Konigsberg, East Prussia. From a Lutheran family. Never married. Immanuel Kant.
KANT Kant was looking for some sort of objective basis for morality – a way of knowing our duty.
Basic Principles: Ethics and Business
Theory of Formalism.
Two objections to Kant’s Categorical Imperative
Kant’s theory of imperatives
Kant’s Categorical Imperative
Kant: the good will, duty and the Categorical Imperative
Immanuel Kant.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative
Immanuel Kant’s ethics
Noddy’s Guide to Kant.
Absolutism.
Philosophy 2030 Class #16 Deontology 5/3/16
Kant and Kantian Ethics:
Deontology Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative - revision
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Immanuel Kant
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Critique of Practical Reason [Kritik der reinen Vernunft]
Kant’s Moral Theory.
Moral Reasoning  Ethical dilemmas in management are not simple choices between “right” and “wrong”.They are complex judgments on the balance between economic.
Think Pair Share “Evaluating Kant’s Duties and Inclinations by Ranking Actions”
Deontology Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology.
Deontological Ethics Immanuel Kant.
History of Philosophy Lecture 17 Immanuel Kant’ Ethics
Ethical concepts and ethical theories Topic 3
Basic Principles: Ethics and Business
Presentation transcript:

Week 4: Deontology

Last Week Consequentialist Ethics: moral right/wrong, obligation/prohibition are determined entirely by what the consequences of actions are Utilitarianism is one kind of consequentialist ethical theory Deontological: mora right/wrong, obligation/prohibition without regard to what the consequences of actions are Kant’s Ethics is one kind of deontological ethical theory

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Influential German philosopher in ethics and metaphysics, epistemology A central figure of the Enlightenment Period Critique of Pure Reason – metaphysical and epistemological work Metaphysics of Moral – ethical work

Trolley Scenario

Duties Kant’s deontological ethics is concerned with duties to do something and duties not to do something Moral obligations to do x, moral prohibitions to do x What our duties are by analyzing what duty is Not by analyzing the consequences of an action

Requirements Two kinds of requirements/demands Hypothetical (practical) requirements; escapable Categorical requirements; not escapable Hypothetical Requirements If you want to read Kant in the original, you must to learn German Federal law requires you to make yourself available to serve on a jury Categorical Requirements obligations to do something no matter what our desires/goals are Cannot escape the force of requirement/obligation by giving up a desire/goal, nor by leaving a jurisdiction (e.g. country, club) Morality is based only on categorical requirements

Authority Requirements depend on the presence of an authority. Any source of practical authority depends on reasons for obeying it Hypothetical requirements depend for their force on an external authority the authority always open to question: why should we obey it? Example "If you want to punch someone in the nose, you have to make a fist.“ authority: desire You must attend jury duty if you received a call; authority: Canadian government Categorical requirements have an authority from within We cannot ask: why should we obey it? So, moral requirements must not depend for their force on external source of authority.

Intrinsically Authoritative Requirement The concept of an obligation is the concept of an intrinsically authoritative requirement-a requirement that, simply by virtue of what it requires, forestalls any question as to its authority. we must find something such that a requirement to do it would not be open to question. i.e. a requirement would carry authority simply by virtue of requiring that thing.

Excuses Suppose that you stay in shape by swimming laps two mornings a week, when the pool is open to recreational swimmers. But suppose that when your alarm goes off this morning, you just don'tfeel like going. You consider skipping your morning swim just this once. Excuse-making of this sort is odd. Why do you need a reason for not doing something that you don't feel like doing? Why you don't already have a good enough reason for not swimming, consisting in the fact that you just don't feel like it? Answer: If not feeling like it were a good enough reason for not swimming, then you'd almost never manage to get yourself into the pool, since the mornings on which you're supposed to swim almost always find you not feeling like it. Given that you want to stay in shape by swimming, you can't accept "I don't feel like it" as a valid reason, since it would completely undermine your program of exercise. Why not accept "I don't feel like it" as a reason on this occasion while resolving to reject it on all others? Answer: If a consideration counts as a reason for acting, then it counts as a reason whenever it is true

Persons, Rationality and Freedom A person has dignity Not because we own ourselves nor because we seek pleasure Because we are all rational beings – capable of acting rationally Kant rejects – that what is central to morality is pleasure/pain What are persons? Things capable of acting freely. Common-sense Freedom = having alternatives Kant strong view of freedom Free = To act autonomously (freely) is to act in accordance to a law (rule) I choose myself Not free: acting on a desire (inclination) that I haven’t chosen myself When act to satisfy desires for pain/pleasure, we are slaves to pain/pleasure; this is not freedom

When we act to realize ends of our inclination, we are mere instruments for our desires, and so not acting freely When we act freely i.e. when we act in accordance with a rule which we have chosen We start to be authors of our actions (not of our desires) We do something for its own sake We become ends in ourselves – not as tools for something else Acting freely gives people dignity, makes them worthy of respect This is why it is wrong to use people for the sake of other peoples happiness

Absolute Value Utilitarianism: Absolute Value Only one thing has absolute value: pleasure Everything else is done for the sake of pleasure Kant: Only a “Good Will” has absolute Value Values: Talent, Intelligence, Pleasant Sensation are valuable but not of absolute value

Moral Worth What makes an action morally worthy has to do with the quality of will or intention – the reason why an action is performed A good will must be done for the sake of moral law The only good reason is doing something for the sake of duty – done because its right thing to do

Illustration: Shop Keeper A shop-keeper who charges the same prices for selling his goods to inexperienced customers as for selling them to anyone else. This is in accord with duty. The shop-keeper does want to treat all his customers equitably; his intention is aimed at precisely that fact. Moreover, the shop-keeper wants to treat his customers equitably not because of what he wants for them, but because of how he wants them to behave later, specifically, so that his reputation is maintained Similar Case: A Corporation giving to charity – it’s a good thing but the motive is about profitability: increases reputation, which is marketable, which is in the end about increasing profit. An added complication: But there is also a prudential and not-duty-based motive that the shop-keeper might have for this course of conduct: when there is a buyers’ market, he may sell as cheaply to children as to others so as not to lose customers. Thus the customer is honestly served, but his conduct or policy on pricing comes neither from duty nor from directly wanting it, but from a selfish purpose. So, it is wrong.

Categorical Imperative

Categorical Imperative: Three Equivalent Formulations CI1: Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature CI 2: Never treat others as tools, rather only as ends in themselves CI 3: Acting on universal laws which make the kingdom of ends (a state where all individuals act rationally on universal laws) possible.

Categorical Imperative: 1st Formulation

“so if the will is to be called absolutely good without qualification; what kind of law can this be? Since I have robbed the will of any impulses that could come to it from obeying any law, nothing remains to serve as a guiding principle of the will except conduct’s universally conforming to law as such. That is, I ought never to act in such a way that I couldn’t also will that the maxim on which I act should be a universal law. “

Principles Subjective (maxims): principle you act on, you set out for yourself Objective (imperatives): principles which you ought to be following i.e. principles are the principles a rational person follow

1st Formulation ‘Act as if the maxim (rule) of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature’ i.e. absolute regularity. E.g. pure water boils at 1atmosphe at 100C E.g. everytime someone gets lazy, they do not go to the gym To imagine the maxim of my proposed action as a universal law of nature, I imagine that everyone always does the kind of act I propose doing when they are in the circumstances I am in

Test for CI Formulate maxim (rule): whenever I need money, I will get it by making a false promise to repay it universal law: whenever anyone needs money, she will get it by making a false promise to repay it Test in one of two ways Can I conceive that the maxim becomes a universal law? Even if I can conceive of its becoming a universal law of nature, can I will that it become a universal law of nature?

Suicide: 1st Formulation Maxim: I want to commit suicide to improve my condition (i.e. to help me stop suffering) Generalize Maxim: Suppose everyone acted on the maxims that committing suicide to improve the condition Test 1: Is it conceivable that the generalized maxim become a universal law of nature? Kant thinks it is contradictory to commit suicide out of self-love. It is contradictory because self-love is the very thing which motivates us to improve our lives, and ending our life is not an improvement Because the Maxim fails thee conceivability test, we have a perfect duty not to commit suicide out of self-love

Case: Suicide Is suicide permitted for a depressed person if he or she reasons as follows? a) To stay alive would be far less good for me than bad b) I love myself c) Because I love myself I do not want to see myself suffer. d) Therefore, I ought to commit suicide to end my suffering.

Case: Deceitful Promise Maxim: I want to borrow money and pretend that I will pay it back Generalize Maxim: Suppose everyone acted on the maxims that borrowing money with no intention to pay the money back Test 1: Is it conceivable that the generalized maxim become a universal law of nature? Kant thinks it is not possible; promises simply would not exist if no one fulfilled their promises. Because the maxim fails the conceivability test (test 1), we have a perfect duty not to make deceitful promises

Perfect Duties Imperfect Duties To Self Never commit suicide Develop some of one’s talents To Others Never make deceitful promise To help some others in distress

Imperfect duties “‘Can I will that my maxim be a universal law of nature?’ In other words, all things considered, do I really desire my maxim to become a universal law of nature?’ or ‘Could I, in every situation, accept this maxim as law?’ “ An imperfect duty is one which: 1) is conceivable as a universal law 2) a rational agent cannot will that it become a universal law of nature

Case: Wasting Your Talents What if one is financially independent and is also exceptionally talented? What then does she owe, if anything to her talent? Is it okay for her “to indulge in pleasure rather than to take pains in enlarging and improving her happy natural capacities?” Kant notes that it is possible for people - even an entire culture - to neglect their talents in fact, to devote their lives to idle amusement. But the moral question is, is it proper?

Maxim: I will avoid exercising my own talents for idle amusement Generalize Maxim: Everyone avoids exercising their own talents for idle amusement Test 1: Is it conceivable? Yes, it is possible that everyone avoids developing their own talents Test 2: No. It is not something a rational person would will to become a universal law He cannot will that we ought to neglect our talents since it is by means of our talents that we develop and improve our lives, and this is what a rational being aims for. That is, a rational being will necessarily will that his abilities be developed since they are useful to him, and serve any number of purposes. Accordingly, he cannot at the same time will that they be neglected without contradicting himself.