The Logic of The Third Man

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Modal Versions of the Ontological Argument Based on Alvin Plantingas discussion in God, Freedom, and Evil (1974).
Advertisements

Atomism, Causalism, and the Existence of a First Cause (source: paper with the same title that I submitted to a journal) Emanuel Rutten 31 October 2011.
Being and Time A Brief Summary.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 8 Moore’s Non-naturalism
ASYMPTOTIC PROPERTIES OF ESTIMATORS: PLIMS AND CONSISTENCY
1 Module 5 How to identify essay Matakuliah: G1222, Writing IV Tahun: 2006 Versi: v 1.0 rev 1.
Aristotle: Lecture 7 Topic 6 Practical Wisdom and Akrasia.
The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)
Logic and Philosophy Alan Hausman PART ONE Sentential Logic Sentential Logic.
REVIEW 12 SENTENCE PARAGRAPH. INTRODUCTION As you remember from our previous introduction to 5-paragraph essays, the a paragraph is a group of sentences.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved. CHAPTER 8 RELATIONS.
Section 2.3 Properties of Solution Sets
Hazırlayan DISCRETE COMPUTATIONAL STRUCTURES Propositional Logic PROF. DR. YUSUF OYSAL.
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
PHIL/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Ontological Argument.
LECTURE 19 THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT CONTINUED. THE QUANTUM MECHANICAL OBJECTION DEPENDS UPON A PARTICULAR INTERPRETATION WE MIGHT REASONABLY SUSPEND.
HUME ON THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT Text source: Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, part 9.
Naïve Set Theory. Basic Definitions Naïve set theory is the non-axiomatic treatment of set theory. In the axiomatic treatment, which we will only allude.
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence or how come we all exist? Is there a rational basis for belief in God?
An analysis of Kant’s argument against the Cartesian skeptic in his ‘Refutation of Idealism” Note: Audio links to youtube are found on my blog at matthewnevius.wordpress.com.
Aquinas’ Proofs The five ways. Thomas Aquinas ( ) Joined Dominican order against the wishes of his family; led peripatetic existence thereafter.
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence
Christian rejection of TAG
Lecture III Universals: nominalism
? Anti-realism, reductionism, reference
Chapter 2 Sets and Functions.
Ethics: Theory and Practice
Valid and Invalid Arguments
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT 1
Axiomatic Number Theory and Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems
Frege: Kaiser’s chariot is drawn by four horses
The Ontological Argument
Module 3 – Part 2 Node-Voltage Method with Voltage Sources
The ontological argument
Direct Proof and Counterexample I: Introduction
Chapter 15 Strategic Thinking
Philosophy MAP 2 and new topic The Idea of God
Understanding Fallacy
c) Strengths and weaknesses of Cosmological Arguments:
Aristotle’s Causes.
Concept Innatism.
The ontological argument: an a-priori argument (ie, deductive rather than inductive) Anselm ‘God’ is that being than which nothing greater can be conceived’;
O.A. so far.. Anselm – from faith, the fool, 2 part argument
Descartes’ conceivability argument for substance dualism
Leibniz’s reformulation of the Ontological Argument
Chapter 2 Sets and Functions.
March, 26, 2010 EPISTEMOLOGY.
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Anselm & Aquinas December 23, 2005.
THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Truth Tables Hurley
Recap of Aristotle So Far…
The Theory of Forms or The Theory of Ideas
On your whiteboard: What is innatism? Give two examples to support it
Metaphysics & Epistemology
The Ontological Argument
Publics and Counterpublics
What makes these things different?
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Clarify and explain the key ideas. A’priori Deductive
March, 26, 2010 EPISTEMOLOGY.
Clarify and explain the key ideas. A’priori Deductive
Properties of Solution Sets
Assess the weaknesses of the cosmological argument. (12 marks)
Explore the weaknesses of the ontological argument. (8 marks)
Implementation of Learning Systems
Clarify the key ideas Logic Definition Premises Outline opinion Flawed
Summarizing, Quoting, and Paraphrasing: Writing about research
The Main Connective (Again)
Presentation transcript:

The Logic of The Third Man S. Marc Cohen

The Logic of The Third Man [Overview] A. Central Topic: The Third Man Argument [TMA] I. the argument at Parmenides 132a-b B. Purpose I. Formulate a version of the TMA which: 1. is logically consistent 2. accurately represents Plato’s argument in the text II. Show how previous formulations are inadequate 1. Vlastos’ argument 2. Sellar’s argument C. Format (eight sections) I. sections(1-3): examination and critique of Vlastos’ and Sellar’s TMA formulations II. sections(4-6): Cohen’s TMA argument III. sections(7-8) implications of Cohen’s TMA argument and conclusions

Parmenides 132a-b [Cornford's Translation] “I imagine your ground for believing in a single form in each case is this. When it seems to you that a number of things are large, there seems I suppose, to be a certain single character which is the same when you look at them all; hence you think that largeness is a single thing.... But now take largeness itself and the other things which are large. Suppose you look at all these in the same way in your mind's eye, will not yet another unity make its appearance-a largeness by virtue of which they all appear large? ... If so, a second form of largeness will present itself, over and above largeness itself and the things that share in it, and again, covering all these, yet another, which will make all of them large. So each of your forms will no longer be one, but an indefinite number.”

Concepts A. Defining [Rough Definitions] I. One-Over-Many: For any plurality of F things, there is a form of F-ness by virtue of partaking of which each member of that plurality is F. II. Self-Predication [SP]: Every form of f-ness is itself F III. Non-Identity [NI]: No form partakes of itself B. Applying B One-Over-Many: A, B and C are all Tall, therefore they participate in one form, Tallness, which is over them all A C Self-Predication: the form of tallness is tall Non-Identity: tallness doesn't participate in the form of the tallness

Vlastos I. Formulation of the TMA II. Suppressed Premises of the TMA A1- if a number of things are all F, there must be a single form, F-ness. A2- if a number of things and F-ness are all F, then there must be another form, F-ness 1. II. Suppressed Premises of the TMA 1. Argues that A2 doesn’t follow from A1, therefore there must be suppressed premises SP: any form can be predicated of itself NI: if anything has a certain character, it cannot be identical with the Form in virtue which we apprehend that character 2. Contends that NI and SP are formal contradictories SP: F-ness is an F thing NI: amounts to the assumption that F-ness is not an F-thing 3. Still insists that these were the premises Plato used [unknowingly] III. Scholarly Critiques 1. Cohen disagrees, recognizing that if SP and NI are required, then the conclusion must necessarily be logically inconsistent. Cohen maintains that there is no support in the text for logical inconsistency in Plato’s conclusion and points out that if the conclusion is logically inconsistent, then any other inconsistent set of premises would work as well, not only SP and NI. 2. Sellar argues that the SP and NI assumptions don’t have to be viewed as contradictories.

Sellar I. Formulation of the TMA II. Scholarly Critiques 1. Argument focuses on the treatment of the expression “F-ness” 2. Contends that “F-ness” represents a class of variables rather than a class of names 3. In Sellar’s version of the assumptions, quantifiers are added and two more assumptions are included, G and P, in order to eliminate logical inconsistencies G: if a number of things are all F, there must be an F-ness by virtue of which they are all F P: a,b,c and so forth, particulars, are F SP’: All F-nesses are F. NI’: If x is F, then x is not identical with the F-ness by virtue of which it is F II. Scholarly Critiques 1. Vlastos regards this argument as “incomparably better” than his own, but he contends that it is not supported by the text, Cohen agrees 2. Vlastos formulates a revision of G, G1 G1: if a number of entities are all F, there must be exactly one form corresponding to the character, F; and each of those entities is F by virtue of participating in that Form 3. Cohen argues that Vlastos’ G1 is logically inconsistent with Sellar’s SP and NI assumptions. Likewise, he believes that it is not the only alternative to Sellar’s G. Cohen identifies G2 G2: if a number of entities are all F, there must be exactly one form by virtue of which they are all F. 4. Cohen argues that G2 is better than the previous formulations, but through examination he realizes is ultimately insufficient. Cohen contends that in order to come up with an adequate formulation of G2, a shift to a version which quantifies over sets of F’s as well as over F’s will be necessary.

Cohen I. Formulation of the TMA [OM-Axiom] A. Terms object: any F thing which ‘F’ can be predicated. particular: an object in which nothing participates. form: an object that is not a particular. maximal set: contains every object on every level equal to or less than the level of its highest-level member one-over-many: For any maximal set there is exactly one Form in which all and only members of that set participate. B. Levels level 0 objects: particulars level 1 objects: objects composed of only particulars and every particular level (n) objects: all participants are of level n-1 or lower, and all objects ` of n-1 or lower participate in it C. Critique 1. Cohen concludes that the idea of maximal sets doesn’t align with the text and implements the one-over- one relationship rather than a one-over-many principle.

OM-Axiom 1. Let [a] be the set of all particulars. Proofs: 2. [a] is a maximal set (level 0) (1) (D4) (D7) (D8) 3. There is exactly one Form over [a], call it "F-ness I." (2) (OM-axiom) 4. F-ness I is of level one (1) (3) (D5) 5. F-ness I is not a member of [a] (2) (4) (T1) (D7) 6. [a] U F-ness I is maximal (level one). (2) (4) (T2) (D7) (D8) 7. There is exactly one Form over [a] U F-ness I, call it F-ness II (6) (OM-axiom) 8. F-ness II is of level 2. (6) (7) (D6) 9. F-ness II is not a member of [a] and F-ness. (6) (8) (T1) (D7) 10. F-ness II NOT = F-ness I (9) ______________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (OM-axiom) For any maximal set there is exactly one Form in which all and only members of that set participate. (D4) I will also speak of a particular as an object of level 0 (D5) An object is an object of level one if (a) All of its participants are particulars, and (b) all particulars participate in it. (D6) In general, an object is an object of level n (n > I) if (a) All of its participants are of level n - 1 or lower, and (b) all objects of level n - 1 or lower participate in it. (D7) A set of objects is a set of level n if it contains an object of level n and no higher-level object. (D8) A set of level n will be said to be a maximal set if it contains every object of level m for every m < n. In other words, a maximal set contains every object on every level equal to or less that the level of its highest-level member. (T1) No object is on more than one level. (T2) There is exactly one object on each level (greater than 0).

Cohen II. Formulation of the TMA [IOM-Axiom] A. Terms one-over-many: for any set of F’s, there is exactly one Form immediately over that set Plato’s over relation: x is over y= if y is a set, every member of y, participates in x [many-over-many] immediately over: x is immediately over y=x is over y and x is over all and only those sets whose level is equal to or less than that of y [one-over-many] Plato’s uniqueness thesis: : when you consider a set of large things, exactly one Form of Largeness will come into view, immediately over that set; so there is exactly one Form of Largeness B. Conclusions 1. Cohen contends that the argument of one over many, thought to be a safe route to the uniqueness thesis, has been shown to be defective 2. apparent problem with the theory of the forms lies in the one-over-many principle

IOM-Axiom I. Let [a] be any set of F's (of level n). 2. There is exactly one Form immediately over [a], call it "F- ness I.” (1) (IOM-axiom) 3. F-ness I is of level n + 1 (1) (2) (T3) 4. F-ness I is not a member of [a] (1) (3) (T1) (D7) 5. [a] U F-ness I is of level n + I (1) (3) (D7) 6. There is exactly one Form immediately over [a] U F-ness I, call it "F-ness I I.” (IOM-axiom) (5) 7. F-ness II is of level n + 2 (5) (6) (T3) 8. F-ness II is not a member of [a] U F-ness I (5) (7) (T1) (D7) 9. F-ness II NOT= F-ness I (8) (D7) A set of objects is a set of level n if it contains an object of level n and no higher-level object (T1) No object is on more than one level (T3) If x is immediately over y, then the level of x is one greater than the level y (IOM-axiom) For any set of F's, there is exactly one Form immediately over that set.

IOM-Axiom(Many-Over-Many Relation) “I imagine your ground for believing in a single form in each case is this. When it seems to you that a number of things are large, there seems I suppose, to be a certain single character which is the same when you look at them all; hence you think that largeness is a single thing.... But now take largeness itself and the other things which are large. Suppose you look at all these in the same way in your mind's eye, will not yet another unity make its appearance-a largeness by virtue of which they all appear large? ... If so, a second form of largeness will present itself, over and above largeness itself and the things that share in it, and again, covering all these, yet another, which will make all of them large. So each of your forms will no longer be one, but an indefinite number.” F-ness 2 Particular S Form F-ness 1 A B C A B C Set 0 Set 1 Set 2