Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
PROOF BY CONTRADICTION
Advertisements

1 Turing Machines and Equivalent Models Section 13.2 The Church-Turing Thesis.
Primitive Recursive Functions (Chapter 3)
October 13, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III 1 Coding Programs by Numbers Gödel numbers are usually very large, even for small.
1 Undecidability Andreas Klappenecker [based on slides by Prof. Welch]
Discrete Mathematics Lecture 4 Harper Langston New York University.
CSE115/ENGR160 Discrete Mathematics 03/03/11 Ming-Hsuan Yang UC Merced 1.
October 27, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 12: A Universal Program IV 1Universality Then we append the following instruction: [C]IF K = Lt(Z) + 1 
November 10, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 16: Computation on Strings I 1Diagonalization Another example: Let TOT be the set of all numbers p such.
November 3, 2009Introduction to Cognitive Science Lecture 15: Theory of Computation II 1 Languages Accepted by Turing Machines Example 2: Language L =
October 8, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 10: A Universal Program II 1 Pairing Functions and Gödel Numbers This way the equation  x, y  = z defines.
September 24, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 6: Primitive Recursive Functions II 1 Homework Questions Question 1: Write a program P that computes 
September 17, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 4: Programs and Computable Functions III 1 Macros Now we want to use macros of the form: W  f(V 1, …,
November 3, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 14: A Universal Program VI 1 Recursively Enumerable Sets Definition: We write: W n = {x  N |  (x, n) 
Chapter 4: A Universal Program 1. Coding programs Example : For our programs P we have variables that are arranged in a certain order: Y 1 X 1 Z 1 X 2.
Algorithms: Selected Exercises Goals Introduce the concept & basic properties of an algorithm.
More Theory of Computing
1 Sections 1.5 & 3.1 Methods of Proof / Proof Strategy.
1 Proof Strategies CS/APMA 202 Rosen section 3.1 Aaron Bloomfield.
First Order Logic Lecture 2: Sep 9. This Lecture Last time we talked about propositional logic, a logic on simple statements. This time we will talk about.
December 1, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 21: Turing Machines II 1 Simulation of L n in T We will now construct a Post-Turing program Q that simulates.
1 Section 13.2 The Church-Turing Thesis The Church-Turing Thesis: Anything that is intuitively computable can be be computed by a Turing machine. It is.
4.1 Proofs and Counterexamples. Even Odd Numbers Find a property that describes each of the following sets E={…, -4, -2, 0, 2, 4, 6, …} O={…, -3, -1,
1 Turing’s Thesis. 2 Turing’s thesis: Any computation carried out by mechanical means can be performed by a Turing Machine (1930)
September 29, 2009Theory of Computation Lecture 7: Primitive Recursive Functions III 1 Some Primitive Recursive Functions Example 3: h(x) = x! Here are.
Theory of Computation Lecture 5: Primitive Recursive Functions I
Recursively Enumerable and Recursive Languages
1 Recursively Enumerable and Recursive Languages.
Decidability.
October 4, 2016Theory of Computation Lecture 9: A Universal Program I 1Minimalization Example 15: R(x, y) R(x, y) is the remainder when x is divided by.
CSE15 Discrete Mathematics 03/06/17
The Foundations: Logic and Proofs
Another Word on PRC Classes
Theory of Computation Lecture 10: A Universal Program I
Chapter 4 (Part 1): Induction & Recursion
Theory of Computation Lecture 12: A Universal Program III
Theory Of Computer Science
Linear Bounded Automata LBAs
Diagonalization and Reducibility
Theory of Computation Lecture 14: A Universal Program V
Recursively Enumerable Sets
CS154, Lecture 11: Self Reference, Foundation of Mathematics
Numerical Representation of Strings
Theory of Computation Lecture 22: Turing Machines III
Theory of Computation Lecture 16: A Universal Program VII
Theory of Computation Lecture 5: Programs and Computable Functions III
Theory of Computation Lecture 6: Primitive Recursive Functions I
Copyright © Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.
CSCE 411 Design and Analysis of Algorithms
Theory Of Computer Science
The Programming Language L
Pairing Functions and Gödel Numbers
Theory of Computation Lecture 21: Turing Machines II
Diagonalization and Reducibility
Recursively Enumerable Sets
CS154, Lecture 11: Self Reference, Foundation of Mathematics
Primitive Recursive Predicates
Theory of Computation Lecture 5: Programs and Computable Functions III
The Programming Language L
Theory of Computation Lecture 4: Programs and Computable Functions II
Theory of Computation Lecture 9: A Universal Program I
Pairing Functions and Gödel Numbers
Theory of Computation Lecture 6: Primitive Recursive Functions I
Some Primitive Recursive Functions
Theory of Computation Lecture 22: Turing Machines II
Theory of Computation Lecture 13: A Universal Program V
Recursively Enumerable Sets
Theory of Computation Lecture 17: Calculations on Strings II
Theory of Computation Lecture 12: A Universal Program IV
Theory of Computation Lecture 23: Turing Machines III
Presentation transcript:

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III The Halting Problem Let us define the predicate HALT(x, y). For a given number y, let P be the program such that #(P ) = y. Then HALT(x, y) is true if P(1)(x) is defined and false if P(1)(x) is undefined. In other words: HALT(x, y)  program number y eventually halts on input x. Here comes a surprise: Theorem 2.1: HALT(x, y) is not a computable predicate. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III The Halting Problem Proof (by contradiction): Assume that HALT(x, y) were computable. Then we could write the following program P : [A] IF HALT(X, X) GOTO A This program P would compute the following function: P(1)(x) =  if HALT(x, x) = 0 if HALT(x, x) Now let #(P ) = y0. Then by the definition of HALT we get: HALT(x, y0)  HALT(x, x) For input x = y0 we then have: HALT(y0, y0)  HALT(y0, y0) Contradiction! March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III The Halting Problem So finally we have an example of a predicate that is not computable by any program in the language L . We would even like to conclude the following: There is no algorithm that, given a program of L and an input to that program, can determine whether or not the given program will eventually halt on the given input. This is called the unsolvability of the halting problem. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III The Halting Problem If there were such an algorithm, we could use it to determine the truth value of HALT(x, y) for given x and y: We would first obtain the program Q so that #(Q ) = y. Then we would check whether Q eventually halts on input x. However, we have reason to believe that any algorithm for computing on numbers can be carried out by a program of L (Church’s Thesis). So this would contradict the fact that HALT(x, y) is not computable. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III The Halting Problem It may surprise you that there is no algorithm for solving the halting problem. Is it not possible for a computer scientist to analyze a given program and find out whether it will terminate for a particular input or not (even if this analysis takes a very long time)? No, actually we can devise a very simple program in L for which to date nobody is able to tell whether it will ever terminate. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III The Halting Problem This program is based on Goldbach’s conjecture, which assumes that every even number  4 is the sum of two prime numbers. For example, 4 = 2 + 2, 6 = 3 + 3, 48 = 41 + 7. It would be easy to write a program in L that searches for a counterexample to this conjecture. This program would check the following predicate for increasing values n: (x)n(y)n[Prime(x) & Prime(y) & x + y = n] Nobody knows whether this program will ever halt. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III Universality For each n > 0, let us define: (n)(x1, …, xn, y) = P(n)(x1, …, xn) , where #(P ) = y. Theorem 3.1 (Universality Theorem): For each n > 0, the function (n)(x1, …, xn, y) is partially computable. This is one of the most important theorems in computability theory. We will prove it by providing instructions for writing a program Un that computes (n) for each n > 0. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III Universality In other words, for each n > 0 we want to have: Un(n+1)(x1, …, xn, xn+1) = (n)(x1, …, xn, xn+1) . These programs Un are called universal. For example, U1 can be used to compute any partially computable function of one variable. If there is a program P that computes f(x), and #(P ) = y, then f(x) = (1)(x, y) = U1(2)(x, y). It is useful to think of the programs Un in terms of interpreters of programs in L . March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III Universality The universal programs must decode the number of the program given to them, keep track of the current snapshot during program execution, and generate the next snapshot based on the current one and the current instruction. When we write such programs, we will freely use macros referring to functions that we already know to be primitive recursive. We will also freely use label and variable names beyond those specified for the language L . March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III Universality In describing the state of a computation, we assume all variables to have the value 0 if not assigned a different value. Then we can code the state of the computation by the Gödel number [a1, …, am], where ai is the value of the i-th variable in our ordered list. Obviously, m is chosen so that all ai for i > m are 0. For example, the state Y = 1, X = 2, Z2 = 1 is coded by the following number: [1, 2, 0, 0, 1] = 2  32  11 = 198. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III Universality In order to store the current snapshot, we need to keep track of two numbers: K is the number of the instruction to be executed next, and S is the current state coded as a Gödel number (see previous slide). Now we are ready to write the program Un for computing Y = (n)(X1, …, Xn, Xn+1). We will explain Un piece by piece and finally put the pieces together. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III

Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III Universality Z  Xn+1 + 1 S  ni=1 (p2i)Xi K  1 If Xn+1 = #(P ), where P consists of the instructions I1, …, Im, then Z = [#(I1), …, #(Im)]. S is initialized as [0, X1, 0, X2, …, 0, Xn], which puts the input values into the first n input variables and 0s into the other variables. K is given the value 1 so that the computation will begin with the first instruction. March 26, 2019 Theory of Computation Lecture 11: A Universal Program III