Dorothy Edgington Paris June 2019

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Computing Truth Value.
Advertisements

Sentential Logic. One of our main critical thinking questions was: Does the evidence support the conclusion? How do we evaluate whether specific evidence.
1 Philosophy and Arguments. 2Outline 1 – Arguments: valid vs sound 2. Conditionals 3. Common Forms of Bad Arguments.
Formal Probability Theory
Semantics of SL and Review Part 1: What you need to know for test 2 Part 2: The structure of definitions of truth functional notions Part 3: Rules when.
Chapter 1 Critical Thinking.
Today’s Topics n Review Logical Implication & Truth Table Tests for Validity n Truth Value Analysis n Short Form Validity Tests n Consistency and validity.
PHIL 120: Jan 8 Basic notions of logic
BASIC CONCEPTS OF ARGUMENTS
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil By David Kelsey.
Elementary Logic PHIL Intersession 2013 MTWHF 10:00 – 12:00 ASA0118C Steven A. Miller Day 4.
Propositions and Truth Tables
Deduction, Proofs, and Inference Rules. Let’s Review What we Know Take a look at your handout and see if you have any questions You should know how to.
Translating English ‘or’ into ‘v’ Some uses of ‘or’ suggest an exclusive meaning: (1) My wife is in London or in Oxford (2) Isabel is my daughter or Lily.
Logic and Philosophy Alan Hausman PART ONE Sentential Logic Sentential Logic.
1 Chapter 7 Propositional and Predicate Logic. 2 Chapter 7 Contents (1) l What is Logic? l Logical Operators l Translating between English and Logic l.
Logical Arguments. Strength 1.A useless argument is one in which the truth of the premisses has no effect at all on the truth of the conclusion. 2.A weak.
Chapter 1 Section 1.2 Symbolic Logic. Sentences vs Statements A truth value is one of two words either true (T) or false (F). A statement is a particular.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 15 Writing Philosophy Papers By David Kelsey.
Chapter 3: Introduction to Logic. Logic Main goal: use logic to analyze arguments (claims) to see if they are valid or invalid. This is useful for math.
Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic Chapter 5 Language, Proof and Logic.
David Over Festschrift, London, September Iterated Conditionals Shira Elqayam* David E Over** Simon J Handley*Jonathan StBT Evans* Alison M Bacon*
Introduction to Logic Lecture 12 An introduction to Sentence Logic By David Kelsey.
Introduction to Logic Lecture 12 An introduction to Sentence Logic By David Kelsey.
L = # of lines n = # of different simple propositions L = 2 n EXAMPLE: consider the statement, (A ⋅ B) ⊃ C A, B, C are three simple statements 2 3 L =
PHIL102 SUM2014, M-F12:00-1:00, SAV 264 Instructor: Benjamin Hole
Cosmological arguments from contingency
Religious language: cognitive or non-cognitive?
2. The Logic of Compound Statements Summary
Knowledge Representation and Reasoning
Deductive Arguments.
Relevance Premises are relevant to the conclusion when the truth of the premises provide some evidence that the conclusion is true Premises are irrelevant.
Fallacies of Logic A Mr. C Production.
Explaining the universe
Jesus Heals Dec 31.
Common logical forms Study the following four arguments.
Today’s Outline Discussion of Exercise VI on page 39.
REPORTED SPEECH.
Meta-Ethics Objectives:
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Chapter 1 The Foundations: Logic and Proof, Sets, and Functions
Truth Tables Hurley
Logic, Philosophical Tools Quiz Review…20 minutes 10/31
CS201: Data Structures and Discrete Mathematics I
Introducing the Ideas One of Six Traits:
Truth Trees.
Distinguish valid from invalid arguments and sound from unsound
Natural Deduction.
Propositional Logic.
What can you remember? Why did we say Justification is necessary for knowledge? What did we say some of the issues with saying truth is necessary for.
The Big Picture Deductive arguments - origins of the ontological argument Deductive proofs; the concept of ‘a priori’. St Anselm - God as the greatest.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 3a Evaluating an argument
The Logic of Declarative Statements
Bodacious Body Paragraphs
Deductive Arguments: Checking for Validity
Conditionals: If __________ [then] __________ statements
Introductory Logic PHI 120
Philosophical Methods
8C Truth Tables, 8D, 8E Implications 8F Valid Arguments
Week 2: Critical Thinking
FCAT Science Standard Arianna Medina.
Validity.
CS201: Data Structures and Discrete Mathematics I
ID1050– Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning
Evaluating Deductive Arguments
Introducing Natural Deduction
Validity and Soundness, Again
Substitution.
Counterfactuals (also known as subjunctive conditionals)
The conditional and the bi-conditional
Presentation transcript:

Dorothy Edgington Paris June 2019 Conditionals Lecture 1 Dorothy Edgington Paris June 2019

Overview of 4 lectures 1. When is a conditional true? 2. When is a conditional probable? 3. Counterfactual/subjunctive conditionals 4. Embedded conditionals, uncertainty and indeterminacy

Varieties of Conditional The basic case: take a sentence in the indicative mood, suitable for making a statement: ‘We’ll be home by ten’; ‘Tom cooked the dinner’. Add a conditional clause: ‘We’ll be home by ten if the train is on time’ ‘If Mary didn’t cook the dinner, Tom cooked it’. These are called indicative conditionals, or sometimes ‘open conditionals’.

First contrast ‘Subjunctive’ or ‘counterfactual’ conditionals. Tom would have cooked the dinner if Mary had not done so. We would have been home by ten if the train had been on time. Argument for big difference: If Oswald didn’t kill Kennedy someone else did If Oswald hadn’t killed Kennedy someone else would have

Argument against big difference ‘Don’t go in there: if you go in you will get hurt’ Ceiling collapses. ‘You see, if you had gone in you would have got hurt. I told you so’ Similarly for the earlier examples, and countless others.

Second contrast As well as conditional statements, there are conditional commands, promises, offers, questions, etc. As well as conditional beliefs there are conditional desires, hopes, fears, etc. For instance I can have the desire that if I’m offered the job, no one be told immediately. It turns out to be quite a stiff test: which theory of conditional statements /beliefs extends to a good theory of these other conditional speech acts/mental attitudes

Conditionals and Reasoning 1. Deductive reasoning. Much controversy over which principles of deductive reasoning using conditionals are valid. E.g. transitivity: ‘If A, B; and if B, C; so, if A, C’. Putative counterexample: If Smith is elected, Brown will resign immediately afterwards. If Brown dies before the election, Smith will be elected. So, if Brown dies before the election, Brown will resign immediately afterwards.

Non-demonstrative reasoning They are not at home; because the lights are off; and if they had been at home the lights would have been on. I think the patient took arsenic; for he has [such-and-such] symptoms; and these are the symptoms he would have if he had taken arsenic.

Practical reasoning If I do x, such-and such will happen. Care is needed about which conditionals provide reasons for acting. Tom has heart disease. He is taking medication to lower the chance of a heart attack. Yet from another perspective: if he’s taking this medication he’s more likely to get a heart attack than if he isn’t.

Truth conditions A dominant tradition in the philosophy of language is to explain meaning in terms of truth conditions. We have devices for building a complex sentence out of one or more simpler sentences. One-place sentence operators include: it is not the case that/possible that/probable that/surprising that/known that.

Two-place sentence operators Let A be ‘Ann went to Paris’. Let B be ‘Bob went to Paris. We can form sentences A and B; A or B; if A, B; A before B; A because B; if it had been the case that A, it would have been the case that B. According to the dominant tradition, we need to explain how the truth-conditions of the whole depend in a systematic way of the truth conditions of the contained sentences.

Truth-functionality Ground-level logic deals with the operators which have the peculiarly simple property that the truth value(s) of the contained sentence(s) determine the truth value of the resultant sentence: not; or; and; ?if?—this last being controversial. Write these as ¬A, AB, A&B, AB.

Truth table for ‘If A, B’ A B AB ¬AB A¬B 1. T T T T F 2. T F F T T 3. F T T T T 4. F F T F T AB = ¬A or B = ¬(A&¬B) ¬(A&B) = A¬B A or B = ¬AB

Non-truth-functional truth conditions A B AB AB 1. T T T T [? T or F] 2. T F F F [?? T or F] 3. F T T T or F 4. F F T T or F NB this is not a theory, but the upshot of some theory about what makes a conditional true, which is non-truth-functional

Example: Stalnaker ‘Consider a possible world in which A is true and otherwise differs minimally [if at all] from the actual world. ‘If A, B’ is true (false) if B is true (false) in that possible world. i.e 6 possibilities, not 4 or 8, for Stalnaker. (See previous slide)

Arguments for truth-functionality 1. The inferences from (A or B) to (if not A, B), and from not(A&B) to (if A, not B) can seem very compelling. They are valid truth-functionally, but invalid non-truth-functionally 2. Conditional proof: from premises X, Y it follows that Z. So, from premise X it follows that if Y, Z. Now from premises ¬(A&B), A it follows that B. So, from premise ¬(A&B) it follows that if A, B. Valid only on the truth-functional reading.

Minimal non-truth-functionality A B AB ¬AB A¬B T T T T/F F T F F T/F T F T T/F T T/F F F T/F F T/F

Arguments against truth-functionality 1. Notoriously, all conditionals with false antecedents are true! And all conditionals with true consequents are true. But I am surely not inconsistent when I believe the Republicans won’t win, but reject the claim that if they win they will double income tax. And I can consistently believe that Sue is lecturing just now, while rejecting the thought that if she had a heart attack today, she is lecturing just now.

Other absurdities A ‘proof’ of the existence of God: If God does not exist, then it is not the case that if I pray my prayers will be answered. I do not pray. Therefore God exists.

Switches Paradox If (A&B) then C; therefore, either (if A then C) or (if B then C) If you press switch A and you press switch B, the light will go on. Therefore, either, if you press A the light will go on, or, if you press B the light will go on. If it’s a triangle and its equi-angular, then it’s equilateral. Therefore, either, if it’s a triangle it’s equilateral, or, if it’s equi-angular it’s equilateral. Valid for the truth-functional conditional.

More absurdities The following are tautologies: (If A, B) or (If B, A) (If A, B) or (if B, C) (If A, B) or (If not A, B)

Grice’s pragmatic defence There are many ways of speaking the truth yet misleading your audience. One way is to say something weaker than some other relevant thing you are in a position to say. That’s why we don’t say ‘If A, B’ when we just believe ¬A; or when we just believe B. The same phenomenon applies to disjunctions, and negated conjunctions: He’s either in the pub of the library You won’t eat those and live

But Unlike the case of disjunctions and conjunctions, nobody thinks that believing ¬A is sufficient reason to believe ‘if A, B’, or that they are doing anything wrong if they reject A and also reject if A, B. Also Grice’s suggestion doesn’t address the full range of counterintuitive results.