Being and Time A Brief Summary.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
© Michael Lacewing The concept of a person Michael Lacewing.
Advertisements

A Student’s Guide to Methodology
The Subject-Matter of Ethics
Anselm On the Existence of God. “Nor do I seek to understand so that I can believe, but rather I believe so that I can understand. For I believe this.
The ontological argument. I had the persuasion that there was absolutely nothing in the world, that there was no sky and no earth, neither minds nor.
Descartes God.
How to Avoid Misusing Source Material in Your Written Work.
The ontological argument
Learning Style Research developed by:
Descartes’ cosmological argument
Descartes’ trademark argument Michael Lacewing
LECTURE 24 THE NATURE OF PERSONS PHYSICALISM AND DUALISM (“WHAT AM I?)
Meditations on First Philosophy
Huiming Ren Shandong University of China. What we could learn from the case of veridical perceptions.
Word of Life March 2011 “Here am I, the servant of the Lord; let it be with me according to your word“ (Lk 1,38)
Phil 160 Kant.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 8 Moore’s Non-naturalism
The Existence of God and the Problem of Evil
Idealism.
LOCKE ON SUBSTANCE (Part 1 of 2) Text source: Essay Concerning Human Understanding, bk. 2 ch. 23.
Aristotle and the Prime Mover
Descartes on Certainty (and Doubt)
The Rationalists: Descartes Certainty: Self and God
 The cosmological argument is, as it’s name sugessts (from the greek cosmos, meaning ‘universe’ or ‘world’). An a posteriori argument for the existence.
PHL 201 March 18, 2004  Quiz #3 Answers  Next Quiz – Mar. 26 (new format)  Essay Assignments  Chapter Four – The Self  Faculty Course Surveys.
Introduction to Linguistics and Basic Terms
LOCKE ON SUBSTANCE (Part 2 of 2) Text source: Essay Concerning Human Understanding, bk. 2 ch. 23.
Speech and Phenomena Philosophy 157 G. J. Mattey ©2002.
The ‘Ene’ in the Risale-i Nur. Related concepts: ‘ego’ and ‘I’  What is meant by ‘ego’ in English?  Several conceptions exist, including the philosophical,
Artificial intelligence. [I]f there had been such machines, possessing the organs and outward form of a monkey or some other animal without reason,
PHILOSOPHY OF THE BODY. I. Historical Considerations: The Problem of Dualism What is Dualism? Basically dualism which is introduced by Plato is a theory.
Epistemology Revision
THE ESSAY: THE 3 LEVELS OF COMPOSITION. AN OVERVIEW OF THE 3 LEVELS  I. LEVEL ONE = MOST THEORETICAL (INCLUDES YOUR THESIS)  II. LEVEL TWO = DEFINED.
Finding our way back  The initial result of Descartes’ use of hyperbolic doubt is the recognition that at least one thing cannot be doubted, at least.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
EXISTENTIALISM.
John Locke ( ) Influential both as a philosopher (Essay Concerning Human Understanding) and as a political thinker (Two Treatises on Government)
Dualism: epiphenomenalism
René Descartes ( AD) Meditations on First Philosophy (1641) (Text, pp )
Welcome to Ethics Ethics and citizens rights DR. BURTON A. AGGABAO Professorial lecturer
Philosophy 4610 Philosophy of Mind Week 8: Can a Computer Think?
Parts of Speech A Brief Review. Noun Person, Place, Thing, or Idea Common: begins with lower case letter (city) Proper: begins with capital letter (Detroit)
The argument from reason. leibniz’s law arguments 1)All Fs are G. 2)o is not G. 3)o is not an F.
Critical Social Theory “People with opinions. Where do they come from. These days it seems like a natural fact. What we think changes how we act” The Gang.
Arguments for God’s existence.  What are we arguing for?
Différance Philosophy 157 G. J. Mattey ©2002. The Sign as Deferred Presence In classic semiology, the sign represents something in its absence It defers.
Being and Time Introduction Chapter One Philosophy 157 G. J. Mattey ©2002.
Parts of Speech A Brief Review. Noun Person, Place, Thing, or Idea Common: begins with lower case letter (city) Proper: begins with capital letter (Detroit)
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence or how come we all exist? Is there a rational basis for belief in God?
Strengthening Your Interpersonal Relationships. 1. Don’t criticize, condemn, or complain about people.  There’s no faster way create resentment toward.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 13 Minds and Bodies #2 (Physicalism) By David Kelsey.
On Consciousness as Higher-Order Thought Charles Siewert Rice University.
The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel’s Idealism.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 8: Augustine and Self-Consciousness.
René Descartes (1596–1650) Cartesian Substance Dualism.
Further criticisms of Concept Empiricism Focus: To consider further criticisms of Concept Empiricism, alongside the criticism from Innatism.
An analysis of Kant’s argument against the Cartesian skeptic in his ‘Refutation of Idealism” Note: Audio links to youtube are found on my blog at matthewnevius.wordpress.com.
1. Don’t criticize, condemn, or complain about people. There’s no faster way create resentment toward you than to criticize or complain about a person.
An Outline of Descartes's Meditations on First Philosophy
“What is Enlightenment?” Immanuel Kant Michel Foucault.
This week’s aims  To test your understanding of substance dualism through an initial assessment task  To explain and analyse the philosophical zombies.
Lecture 8 Time: McTaggart’s argument
Lecture 5 Particulars: substratum and substance theories
Martin Heidegger and the Call of Conscience
Descartes’ trademark argument
Descartes’ proof of the external world
Problems with IDR Before the holidays we discussed two problems with the indirect realist view. If we can’t perceive the external world directly (because.
The ‘Ene’.
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit
The Logic of The Third Man
Presentation transcript:

Being and Time A Brief Summary

The Martin Heidegger Being and Time (1927) Heidegger’s work offers a thorough critique of this ego-subjectivity. The main metaphysical question in philosophy has been the question of “being.” What “makes it possible” for this (kind of) thing to be just the determinate and self-identical (kind of) thing it so definitely is, and that I can recognize it as being? What is the source or origin of a thing’s determinate identity, of its self-identical “Being,” as precisely the thing it is?

He noted that Descartes had divided being into three kinds of substances: “Entities in need of no other entity.” Res cogitans Res extensa But this conception has some problems . . .

First, this is an odd account of “being” because it points to an “infinite difference.” It imagines that the “being” one finds in all three of these is the same . . . But how can that be? Second, when Descartes speaks of “extensa” he points only to (in Heidegger’s words) “whatever substantial property belongs most pre-eminently to the particular substance.” Third, “the kind of being which belongs to entities within-the-world is something which they themselves might have been permitted to present; but Descartes does not let them do so. Instead, he prescribes for the world its ‘real’ being, as it were, on the basis of an idea of being whose source has not been unveiled and which has not been demonstrated in its own right—an idea in which being is equated with constant presence-at-hand. (B&T, 129)

“Descartes has narrowed down the question of the world to that of Things of Nature as those entities within-the-world which are proximally accessible. He has confirmed the opinion that to know an entity in what is supposedly the most rigorous ontical manner is our only possible access to the primary being of the entity which such knowledge reveals.” (B&T, 133) In this way of thinking, the res cogitans is not “the world” but the world is composed of all the “res extensa.”

Heidegger thought that the best way to get at the being question was to interrogate ourselves. We are that being —Dasein (Being-there). For Heidegger Dasein is being that asks itself what being is. Dasein is therefore a self-interpreting being; existence is self-interpretation. Dasein is, first and foremost, the being that says “I.” It has a sense of “mineness.”

In Being and Time Heidegger distinguished between three modes of being (with the understanding that “the being of entities ‘is’ not itself an entity”—p. 26): Dasein Presence-at-hand Readiness-at-hand See: p. 32 pp. 67-71 pp. 76-77 (especially 77)

Average everydayness is the normal mode of existence for Dasein Average everydayness is the normal mode of existence for Dasein. Living in this way it’s like my life is living me, not the other way around. But in certain moments I may be forced to reflect on why I am living in this way; if I resort to some kind of argument that it is somehow “necessary,” I am living as inauthentic Dasein because I’m sloughing responsibility off on some kind of higher power or principle. Such consolation is the defining mark of inauthenticity. But most of Dasein’s existences is neither authentic or inauthentic, it is lived in average everydayness.

Heidegger thinks most conceptions of the subject go wrong by converting the subject into an object. He believes that the alternative is to see it as “Being-in-the-World.” This environment is one in which Dasein is filled with things, not objects. (Pragmata, not res). A thing has meaning or significance in two sorts of assignments, or references: first, it is what it is in terms of the projects(s) within which it appears second, it is what is is in relation to other things also involved in such projects. So things are Zeug, or gear, for the accomplishments of such projects. As Zeug it has a particular kind of being: readiness-to-hand. In Heidegger’s account, then, the being of a thing is given to it (as that particular kind of thing) by the holistic context of back-and-forth references created both by some project of Dasein and by the other things likewise involved in that project. . . Things always already are what they are as a result of their place within a referential totality of other things given alongside them.

Dasein as the “They-self.” Dasein would be this maker of meaning only if Dasein were itself the ‘pure individual’—the fully self-present, unitary entity—that could serve as the significance-granting subject, and it is not. We don’t normally think of Dasein this way because it seems to us that “I” stands alone, even if nothing else exists, and because Dasein’s individuality seems to offer a unique kind of perspective. But this is a flawed perspective. Dasein is always in relationship to other things. It is always in a world inhabited already by other beings. Normally I thoughtlessly make use of a whole tableau of public understandings to get through life forgetting that those things are there for anyone to do or use. The gear is for others, too. My language, words, and projects are not for me alone. Dasein is they-self.

The “call of conscience” is what happens when Dasein is shocked into the value of existence, the publicness of they. It understands its life is a life into which it has been thrown by various contingencies. This produces a kind of “uncanniness,” a feeling of not being at home, a groundlessness.

When this happens the inauthentic response is to make claims to some sort of metaphysical warrant for identifying oneself with some particular set of one’s constitutive social practices. It conceals one’s own contingency. Authenticity would require acknowledging their Being as practices; that is as contingent ways of Dasein’s being that are always ranged alongside an indefinite number of other actual and possible ways of Dasein to Be. But most practices are self-concealing.