© University of Reading 2008www.reading.ac.uk Figurative Meaning and the Semantics/Pragmatics Divide Emma Borg ‘Go figure’ workshop, June 2013.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Hyperintensionality and Impossible Worlds: An Introduction
Advertisements

Summer 2011 Tuesday, 8/9. Clark and Chalmers on the Extended Mind Where does the mind stop and the rest of the world begin? What are C & C asking here?
Aristotle “Liveliness is got by using the proportional type of metaphor and by making our hearers see things. We have still to explain what we mean by.
The Said and the Unsaid meets Figuration Steve Barker (Nottingham) A speech-act theoretic treatment of metaphor and irony.
CAS LX 502 Semantics 9b. Presupposition, entailments, and implicatures 10.2, 11.
Cooperation and implicature.
Summer 2011 Tuesday, 8/ No supposition seems to me more natural than that there is no process in the brain correlated with associating or with.
Pragmatics II n Non-Literal Communication. Pragmatics II n Non-Literal Communication n Overstatement: No one understands me. A pig wouldn’t eat this food.
Conversational Implicature (Based on Paltridge, chapter 3)
Review Exercises 1) Do the COMPONENTIAL analysis (not the compositional one) of the following words: hen b) rooster Componential analysis 2) Does ‘A’
CAS LX 502 Semantics 10b. Presuppositions, take
SEMANTICS.
The Cooperative Principle
Philosophy 103 Linguistics 103 Introductory Logic: Critical Thinking Fall 2007 Dr. Robert Barnard.
Albert Gatt LIN1180 – Semantics Lecture 10. Part 1 (from last week) Theories of presupposition: the semantics- pragmatics interface.
ICLCE 3, Institute of English Studies, University of London, July 2009 Understanding English Intonation Billy Clark Tim Wharton
CAS LX b. Questions. Seeking truth Much of what we’ve done this semester has to do with characterizing (our knowledge of) the conditions under which.
Says who? On the treatment of speech attributions in discourse structure Gisela Redeker & Markus Egg University of Groningen.
Suppressing valid inferences with conditionals Ruth M.J. Byrne, MRC Applied Psychology Unit, Cambridge (1987, 1988, 1989) Ruth M.J. Byrne, MRC Applied.
CAS LX 502 Semantics 1b. The Truth Ch. 1.
Speech Acts Lecture 8.
Pragmatics.
The Linguistic Turn To what extent is knowledge in the use of language rather than what language is about? MRes Philosophy of Knowledge: Day 2 - Session.
Game Theory and Grice’ Theory of Implicatures Anton Benz.
1 Today Null and alternative hypotheses 1- and 2-tailed tests Regions of rejection Sampling distributions The Central Limit Theorem Standard errors z-tests.
Various Definitions of Pragmatics. Morristhe study of the relations of signs to interpreters (1938) deals with the origin, uses, and effects of signs.
Some observations on the pragmatics of humorous interpretations: a relevance theoretic approach CARMEN CURCÓ Professor: 鍾榮富 Presenter: 李羿霈 NA1C0014.
Presupposition and Entailment James Pustejovsky September 23, 2005.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
02 Truth and Rationality Philosophy. 2 Part I: Sentences and Propositions.
Procedural meaning: problems and perspectives UNED, Madrid, October 2009 Prosody: conceptual and procedural meaning; natural and non-natural meaning Tim.
Meaning. Deictics  Are words, phrases and features of grammar that have to be interpreted in relation to the situation in which they are uttered such.
Pragmatics.
LECTURE 2: SEMANTICS IN LINGUISTICS
ORAL COMMUNICATION SKILLS Discussion skills and Presentation skills The course is designed to improve students’ speaking skills in English by: activating.
MLS 570 Critical Thinking Reading Notes Fogelin: Ch. 1 Fall Term 2006 North Central College Dr. Sally Fowler.
SEMANTICS VS PRAGMATICS Semantics is the study of the relationships between linguistic forms and entities in the world; that is how words literally connect.
Presentation about pragmatic concepts Implicatures Presuppositions
 The value of certainty.  Foundationalists suppose that true beliefs held with certainty (indubitable) together with logical and linguistic analysis.
Michelle C. Delos Reyes. meaning of a word = concept It may appear as a constituent of a logical form. It appears as an.
Welcome Back, Folks! We’re travelling to a littele bit far-end of Language in Use Studies EAA remains your faithful companion.
UNIT 2 - IMPLICATURE.
Teaching Writing.
Critical Reasoning.
Lecture 2 (Chapter 2) Introduction to Semantics and Pragmatics.
ADRESS FORMS AND POLITENESS Second person- used when the subject of the verb in a sentence is the same as the individual to.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
Randolph Clarke Florida State University. Free will – or freedom of the will – is often taken to be a power of some kind.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
What does the speaker mean when s/he utters a sentence? Berg (1993): “What we understand from an utterance could never be just the literal meaning of the.
3/15/2016 Context Dependence (such as it is) Kent Bach Presenters: Zhiqi Gong & Lin Xiao University at Albany.
Introduction to Linguistics
Implicature. I. Definition The term “Implicature” accounts for what a speaker can imply, suggest or mean, as distinct from what the speaker literally.
Aristotel‘s concept to language studies was to study true or false sentences - propositions; Thomas Reid described utterances of promising, warning, forgiving.
PRIMENJENA LINGVISTIKA I NASTAVA JEZIKA II 2 nd class.
COMMUNICATION OF MEANING
The basic assumption in conversation is that the participants are adhering to the cooperative principle and the maxims Wife: I hope you brought the bread.
COOPERATIVE PRINCIPLE:
COOPERATION and IMPLICATURE
Language, Logic, and Meaning
Discourse and Pragmatics
Linguistic Structure and Inferential Communication Deirdre Wilson
The Cooperative Principle
Media Communications Richard Trombly Contact :
Nofsinger. R., Everyday Conversation, Sage, 1991
How to Avoid Redundant Object-References
The Cooperative Principle
RELEVANCE THEORY Group Members Sana saif Huma Wazir Junaid Ahmed
Meaning Out There Nayuta Miki (JSPS/Nihon University)
Nofsinger. R., Everyday Conversation, Sage, 1991
Presentation transcript:

© University of Reading 2008www.reading.ac.uk Figurative Meaning and the Semantics/Pragmatics Divide Emma Borg ‘Go figure’ workshop, June 2013.

Structure of the talk: Aim: to explore the models of meaning and communication in minimalism and pragmaticism, outlining how figurative language is handled in each model. To raise some questions for the pragmaticist approach. 1.The Gricean Model 2.The Minimalist Model 3.The Pragmaticist Model 4.How do we constrain free pragmatic effects? 5.Do we really need explicatures? 6.Minimalism and communication

The Gricean Model Total signification of an utterance (a)What is said - Compositional linguistic meaning - Plus:  Disambiguation  Reference assignment - Propositional (a)= what is asserted (semantics) (b) What is implicated -various forms of implicature: conventional, generalised conversational, particularised conversational -(a) & conversational maxims allow hearer to infer (b) (b) = what is merely implied (pragmatics)

Objections to the Gricean model: 1.Fails to match on-line processing, e.g. ignores ‘direct access metaphors’, etc. 2.(a) doesn’t fit with intuitive judgements of what a speaker asserts: asserted content is often pragmatically enhanced content. 3.Problems with the maxims (e.g. doesn’t work for non- literal uses where speaker only ‘makes as if to say’, how many maxims?)

The Minimalist model (a) and (b) = different types of meaning, underpinned by different kinds of cognitive process. Total signification of an utterance (a) What the sentence means Compositional linguistic meaning - Plus:  Disambiguation  Reference assignment - Propositional (a) = what is literally expressed (semantics) (b) What the speaker means -usually pragmatically enhanced -includes both minor and major alterations to (a) -often indeterminate -includes figurative meaning (b) = what is conveyed (pragmatics)

Objections to the Minimalist model 1.Words and structure alone always/often/sometimes fail to yield propositions 2.Model fails to fit with on-line processing 3.Ignores important divisions between different types of speaker meaning.

The Pragmaticist model FPEs = top-down pragmatic effects, e.g. modulation and unarticulated constituents. Total signification of an utterance (a) Linguistically encoded content - Compositional linguistic meaning Always/often/ sub- propositional. (a) = linguistic semantics (b) explicit content of the utterance: explicature - proposition the speaker directly communicates -an expansion or development of (a), involving reference assignment and certain free pragmatic effects (FPEs) (b) = what is asserted (c) what is implicated further relevant propositions hearers can infer on basis of (b) (c) = what is merely implied

What is an explicature? i.A pragmatically inferred development of logical form (where implicatures are wholly pragmatically derived); S&W 1986: 182, Carston 2009: 41 ii.The content the speaker intends to communicate directly; S&W 1986: 183, Carston 2009: 36 iii.The first content hearers recover via relevance processing; S&W 1986:184-5 iv.The essential premise for inferring further (implicated) propositions; Carston 2009: 41 v.The proposition on which S’s utterance is judged true or false; Carston 2009: 36

Example A: ‘How was the party?’ B: ‘There was not enough drink and everyone left’ Explicature: there was not enough alcoholic drink to satisfy the people at [the party] i and so everyone who came to [the party] i left [the party] i early. Implicature: the party was no good. (Carston 2009: 35)

Figurative uses On the RT model there exists a continuum of loose uses, with minor alterations at one end of the scale and metaphor at the other end (or perhaps involving a special, meta-representational process; Carston). Irony is off the scale. Example: “Robert is a computer”: Explicature: Robert is a computer* (via modulation) Implicatures: Robert lacks feelings, processes information well… (Wilson 2011: 180) Problem: How do we individuate explicature-relevant FPEs?

1) How many kinds of FPEs? Why do we need both modulation and UCs? E.g. why treat ‘in London’ as an added UC in “It’s raining” as opposed to allowing the meaning of ‘rain’ to be modulated (either narrowed or loosened)? Carston & Hall 2012 reject a modulation treatment for the locations in weather predicates, but I’m not quite clear why. Since it isn’t clear what the constraints on broadening/narrowing of senses are, it is unclear whether there remains any role for UCs. If it’s all modulation, is this occasionalism? If it’s all modulation, how does this fit with idea of ‘developing LF’?

2) What constrains explicature -relevant FPEs? What stops ‘snow is white’ literally expressing (on some occasion) the proposition ‘snow is white & 2+2=4’? Availability Principle, Scope Principle, appeal to Relevance? A recent suggestion (Hall 2008, Carston & Hall 2012) appeals to ‘the derivational distinction between local and global pragmatic inference’. An effect which modifies a part of the utterance content counts as part of its literal meaning, one which modifies a whole proposition does not.

Problems for locality? A:Do you want to have dinner? B:I’m going to the cinema. How should B’s utterance content be modulated? –Narrowed from GOING-TO-THE-CINEMA to GOING- TO-THE-CINEMA-TONIGHT –Narrowed from GOING-TO-THE-CINEMA to GOING- TO-THE-CINEMA-AT-A-TIME-THAT-MAKES- HAVING-DINNER-WITH-A-IMPOSSIBLE Both of these are local effects, but they give different accounts of what the speaker has literally asserted vs. only implied. Perhaps problems with isolating explicature-relevant effects are instructive.

Do we need the notion of an explicature? (1) i.Explicatures need not be what a speaker intends to communicate directly as may not be psychologically real for her. Thoughts are just as underdetermined as utterances (if S utters ‘pass me the red pen’ she need not have internally specified that she wants the pen that writes in red, the one that contains red ink, the one that is red on the lid, the one that says ‘red’ on it, etc. Compare ‘I want to travel to London’.) ii.Explicatures need not be psychologically real for the audience: all hearers may consciously entertain is ‘implicature’ content.

Do we need explicatures? (2) As theorists explicatures do play a role in a rational reconstruction of a route from literal meaning to conveyed content, but why should we think hearers must or even typically do follow this route, either explicitly or implicitly? Soliciting judgements of truth/falsity for utterance content is inappropriate, it influences the phenomena it is supposed to be uncovering (a kind of ‘quantum effect’):

Truth/Falsity Judgements Is B’s utterance true in a situation where there was more wine but it was held in a locked cabinet? –there wasn’t enough easily available alcoholic drink and everyone at the party left after one hour Is it true in a situation where there was plenty of crème de menthe available at the party, or where those hosting the party didn’t leave? –there wasn’t enough available and attractive alcoholic drink and everyone who came to the party as the result of an invitation left early. In asking these questions we prompt the audience to sharpen the original content of the utterance, but these are decisions about how to sharpen not an uncovering of material which is already somehow present.

Minimalism and communication (1) Perhaps then we just need the standard Kripkean distinction (adopted by minimalism) between what a sentence means and what a speaker says. Socio-linguistic structures allow a direct move from literal meaning to communicated content (it’s not understanding a language which requires understanding a way of life but understanding a speaker). Assertion can go either with what is literally expressed (e.g. legal discourse: ‘use a firearm’) or what is pragmatically conveyed.

Minimalism and communication (2) Speakers can demur from any content attributed on the non-literal side without contradiction, but they do not have final veto on what is communicated (consider libel cases). There is a threshold of tolerance within which differences between the propositional content assigned by speaker and hearers as communicated content can simply be ignored. The boundaries of tolerance are set in context, depending in part on the kind of conversational exchange in which agents are engaged.

Minimalism and communication (3) “[T]he process through which [speakers and hearers] determine which values to assign is not governed by a ‘uniform rule’ but is shaped by a common goal: successful communication…It is unsurprising that accommodation and negotiation should be central to this enterprise, and it is equally unsurprising that so many ‘factors’ should be involved…[T]here is in fact no limit to the information on which the speaker and her audience may draw as they attempt to converge.” -- Heck, forthcoming, ‘Semantics and Context- dependence’, draft p.40

Minimalism and communication (4) If a proposition risks falling outside the contextually determined limits of tolerance, there are two options: i.the speaker/hearer puts her interpretation on the record (‘are you saying…?’/‘did you mean…?’) and interlocutors negotiate over the content to be added to the conversational record. ii.the potential divergence between speaker and hearers take on the communicated content goes unnoticed and communication fails.

Conclusion It is in this sense that all communicated content is ‘an expedition abroad’, no longer part of linguistic understanding per se but instead relying on a culturally entrenched network of beliefs and practices. Metaphor, etc, may be a rather more exotic trip but all non-literal content is a journey way beyond linguistic understanding.