Animal Rights.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Animals as Machines.
Advertisements

Introduction to Environmental Engineering Dr. Glass Environmental Ethics.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 19 Regan & The Case for Animal Rights
Review for Final Exam. Exam Format multiple choice questions multiple choice questions Three essay questions from a choice of five Three essay.
Personhood. Debate Cigarette smoking should be banned in public areas Support:Oppose: FishIda JuliusLok Kit.
(afternoon class) Answer ONE of the following questions: 1)What qualities do you think are necessary to be a “person”? 2) Do you think a chimpanzee would.
Animals as Machines. Descartes René Descartes ( ) French philosopher, mathematician and scientist Discourse on Method (1637) Part 5 discusses.
Do animals have rights?. Approaches to animal rights (1) Aristotle believed that animals existed only to provide for human needs. They were not able to.
Environmental Ethics. Definitions Moral Agents Those who have the freedom and rational capacity to be responsible for choices Those capable of moral reflection.
The Human Conscience in Animal Rights “Discrimination on the basis of sex, it has been said, is the last universally accepted form of discrimination, practiced.
Our Duties to Animals Animal Liberation: All Animals Are Equal —Peter Singer  A prejudice or bias toward the interests of members of one’s own species.
Animal Testing Robert Hovhanessian. Statistics (U.S.) 3/4 for medical purposes and the rest to test various products. An estimated eight million are used.
A Rational Defense of Animal Research Nathan Nobis, Ph.D. Philosophy Department University of Alabama, Birmingham
Animal Welfare and Animal Rights Based on Kernohan, A. (2012). Environmental ethics: An interactive introduction. Buffalo, NY: Broadview Press, Chapters.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 20 Cohen & The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research By David Kelsey.
HUMANS AND NON-HUMANS A Spectrum “ Western ” paradigm emphasizes gulf between humans and animals ■ Religious traditions: humans as “the crown of creation”,
The Moral Status of Animals Kant, Singer, Steinbock.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Ethics of Whaling In search of the right thing to do.
The Case for Animals Singer’s Utilitarian Argument  What is morally relevant?  What makes someone/somethi ng worthy of moral consideration?  What.
Secular Responses Use of the Embryo. Utilitarianism Based on the idea of the greatest happiness for the greatest number or majority Also based on hedonism.
Animals and Society: An Introduction to Human-Animal Studies
The Moral Status of the Non- Human World: Singer and Cohen.
Philosophy 220 The Moral Status of the Non-Human World: Cohen and Warren.
Ethics and ethical systems 12 January
Environmental Ethics. Definitions Moral Agents –Those who have the freedom and rational capacity to be responsible for choices –Those capable of moral.
1 I I Animal Rights. 2 Singer’s Project Singer argues we should extend to other species the “basic principle of equality” that most of us recognize should.
Animal Rights.
Animals and Persons (cont.). Tom Regan Contemporary American Philosopher Deontologist, in the tradition of Kant Specialist in animal rights The Case for.
The treatment of animals Michael Lacewing
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 19 Regan & The Case for Animal Rights By David Kelsey.
Chapter Eleven: Animal Rights and Environmental Ethics
Why Philosophy?. Philosophy: A study of the processes governing thought and conduct. A system of principles for the conduct of life. A study of human.
Business Ethics Lecture Rights and Duties 1.
Utilitarianism or Consequentialism Good actions are those that result in good consequences. The moral value of an action is extrinsic to the action itself.
Peter Singer: “All Animals are Equal ”
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 20 Cohen & The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research By David Kelsey.
© Michael Lacewing Abortion and persons Michael Lacewing
Philosophy 220 Animal Rights. Regan and Animal Rights Tom Regan makes clear his commitment to the animal rights movement. As he articulates it, that movement.
Business Ethics Chapter # 3 Ethical Principles, Quick Tests, and Decision-Making Guidelines  The best kind of relationship in the world is the one in.
Chapter Eleven: Animal Rights and Environmental Ethics Review Applying Ethics: A Text with Readings (10 th ed.) Julie C. Van Camp, Jeffrey Olen, Vincent.
Animals and Persons. Ethical status for animals Kantian and utilitarian ethics traditionally extended to all people, but only people Kant: all rational.
1 III Animal Rights. 2 Background This paper is a condensed version of the central argument presented in Regan’s 1983 book, The Case for Animal Rights.
Unit Eight Seminar Animal Rights. Old Business!  Welcome Back! Only one seminar remaining!  Unit 7 Papers.
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
Chapter 13: World Hunger and Poverty Garrett Hardin, “Lifeboat Ethics” – The lifeboat metaphor: Rich nations are lifeboats full of rich people and poor.
MODERN UTILITARIANISM AND GENETIC ENGINEERING IS IT WRONG TO INTERFERE WITH NATURE? CAN WE JUSTIFY THE SACRIFICE OF A FEW LIVES TO SAVE MANY? DO ANIMALS.
Chapter 8: The Ethical Treatment of Animals Gaverick Matheny, “Utilitarianism and Animals” – Matheny's main 2-part argument (part 1): 1. Being sentient.
Animal rights and personhood Studium Generale October 4, 2016Bernice Bovenkerk.
Philosophical approaches to animal ethics
Chapter 9: The Ethical Treatment of Animals
Humanist perspective: Animal welfare
Philosophical approaches to animal ethics
Michael Lacewing Eating animals Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
universalizability & reversibility
Review for Final Exam.
Animals and Persons.
Utilitarianism: Modern Applications of the theory
On Whiteboards: Do animals have any moral status (should they be considered when making moral decisions)? Whether you answered yes or no, say why. On what.
Do animals have rights?.
Lecture 08: A Brief Summary
Lecture 09: A Brief Summary
Should Animals Have Rights?
Kant’s view on animals is ‘anthropocentric’ in that it is based on a sharp distinction between humans and non-human animals. According to Kant, only.
Kat Angelini & Miranda Chapman
Kant, Anderson, Marginal Cases
Animal Suffering and Rights
All Animals are Created Equal
Kant and Regan.
Speciesism and the Idea of Equality
Presentation transcript:

Animal Rights

Direct vs. Indirect duties towards animals Direct duties: duties owed to the animals themselves (treating animals welfare as an intrinsic good) Indirect duties: duties to act in certain ways towards animals for the sake of ourselves, others or society (treating animal welfare as an instrumental good)

Examples of indirect duties towards animals: Duty to respect private property (animals that belong to someone) Duty to avoid cruelty because it encourages a cruel nature in us, which might then be expressed towards other people Duty not to hurt the feelings of people who love animals by abusing animals Duty to maintain the health of biosystems and nature in general, for our own good Duty to preserve beautiful creatures, for the enjoyment of others and future generations Duty to preserve species that may be sources of other instrumental goods, e.g. medicine

Ethical status for animals Animal welfare as an intrinsic good Kantian and utilitarian ethics traditionally extended to all people, but only people Kant: all rational beings are ends in themselves assumption: only humans are rational (or maybe humans, angels and extraterrestrials) Utilitarianism: the pleasures and pains of all conscious beings are of equal importance assumption (?): only humans are conscious/have pleasure and pain But note: Jeremy Bentham, early utilitarian (pre-Mill): “The question is not, Can they reason?, nor Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?” (Bentham 1789)

Peter Singer Contemporary Australian philosopher Professor of bioethics at Princeton Preference utilitarian Famous advocate of animal rights Animal Liberation (1975) “All Animals are Equal” (1989) (and humans are animals)

Animal Liberation Singer sees ethics as evolving. In the past, slaves, women and people of other races were often not treated as persons, and their interests were not given consideration. Now we recognize all people as persons and extend equal consideration to all people. Now we should extend equal ethical consideration to animals as well.

Speciesism Discrimination against animals is “speciesism”, analogous to racism To discriminate on the basis of species membership, or even on the basis of intelligence or rationality, is like discriminating on the basis of skin color What matters is sentience. Any animal that is sentient (can feel pleasure or pain) counts as a moral subject. All pleasure or pain, or preferences, should count equally, whether they are the pleasures of preferences of humans or animals

The argument from borderline cases Borderline cases: babies, the severely mentally retarded, psychopaths Argument from analogy: borderline cases are similar to (some) animals (in terms of abilities, sentience, capacity for pleasure and pain), so animals should be treated similarly We routinely grant importance to the interests to human borderline cases – not full rights (e.g. the right to vote), but the right to have their preferences treated as morally important and the right not to be mistreated Animals are not equal to normal adults, and therefore cannot have truly equal rights, but their preferences (e.g. the desire to avoid pain) should be given equal consideration

Equal consideration, not equal rights We don’t discriminate between people on the basis of intelligence or ability. So we should not discriminate against animals because they are less intelligent or lack certain abilities. We treat babies and the severely brain damaged better than we treat animals, but we shouldn’t. Animals have just as much right to consideration as babies (or more!) E.g. an adult ape is more aware, more self-directing and has at least as much capacity for suffering as a baby.

Implications Pro vegetarian: taking away a life for a insignificant benefit (satisfying a person’s tastes) is unjustified. Although, Singer allows that it is possible to raise animals ethically for food, if they are raised to have a pleasant and enjoyable life. An animal without a life plan does not suffer from death, and a happy animal can be replaced by another happy animal without net loss to the world. Anti-vivisection: the utilitarian arguments we raise to justify using animals this way would not be accepted as justification for human vivisection, and therefore are not accepted for the case of animals either (except in extreme cases).

Implications (cont.) Individual animals have moral standing, not species or biosystems. Thus, killing two common deer would be a greater sin than killing one endangered tiger. An animal’s rights are potentially as important as a human’s. Where to draw the line? At sentience. Where is the borderline of sentience? Singer’s guess: between the clam and the shrimp.

Tom Regan Contemporary American Philosopher Deontologist, in the tradition of Kant Specialist in animal rights The Case for Animal Rights (1983) “Animal Rights, Human Wrongs” (1980)

Animal Rights Utilitarians are wrong to focus only on pleasure and pain. What is important is respecting the dignity of others, and to treat those with moral standing as ends in themselves, not means (c.f. Kant). What is wrong with eating veal, for example, is not that the animal suffers, rather: “the fundamental wrong is the system that allows us to view animals as our resources, here for us, to be eaten, or surgically manipulated, or put in our cross hairs for sport or money.”

Moral Standing Distinguishes “moral agents” from “moral patients” Moral agents typified by competent human adults Moral patients include everything that has interests, e.g. babies, the mentally incompetent and animals. Both moral agents and moral patients have moral standing, i.e. are ends of themselves and are subject to rights What has interests? Subjects-of-a-life.

Subjects-of-a-life “To be the subject-of-a-life … involves more than merely being alive and more than merely being conscious. To be the subject-of-a-life is to … have beliefs and desires; perception, memory, and a sense of the future, including their own future; an emotional life together with feelings of pleasure and pain; preference and welfare-interests; a psychophysical identity over time; and an individual welfare in the sense that their experiential life fares well or ill for them, independent of their utility for others.” Not all animals, but only animals that meet these criteria. Typically “mentally normal mammals of a year or more”, although potentially other animals with the relevant cognitive capacity.

Implications The following violate animals’ rights: Raising animals for food or fur Hunting for sport or money Keeping pets Keeping animals in circuses or zoos Vivisection Like Singer, holds that only individuals have moral standing, not species or biosystems. More inclusive than Singer as to what causes harm to animals – e.g. pets, raising well-cared-for animals for food, keeping happy animals in a zoo, etc. Not as inclusive as Singer as to which animals matter: mostly only mammals of over a year old compared to everything that is at least as sentient as a shrimp

Against rights for animal Carl Cohen Contemporary American philosopher Theoretical: rights are reciprocal, among moral agents or members of a community of moral agents Practical: Medical research Animals in the wild

Medical research Animal used for vaccines, treatments, of human diseases, e.g. polio, malaria But this research would not be allowed if animals had rights Rights entail duties Rights trump interests absolutely

Rights trump duties Regan agrees: “The harms others might face as a result of the dissolution of [some] practice or institution is no defense of allowing it to continue. . . . No one has a right to be protected against being harmed if the protection in question involves violating the rights of others. . . . No one has a right to be protected by the continuation of an unjust practice, one that violates the rights of others. . . . Justice must be done, though the . . . heavens fall.” (Regan, The Case for Animal Rights, 1983) “On the rights view, we cannot justify harming a single rat merely by aggregating ‘the many human and humane benefits’ that flow from doing it. . . . Not even a single rat is to be treated as if that animal's value were reducible to his possible utility relative to the interests of others.” (Regan, The Case for Animal Rights, 1983)

Animals in the wild If animals have rights, we have the duty to protect those rights, even in the wild. But this is impossible. And undesirable. Should we protect prey from predators? Should we inoculate wild animals from disease? Should we shoot some members of overpopulated herds (e.g. deer) to prevent mass starvation? How can we judge between competing interests/rights? Would we want to?

Other objections to Singer and Regan Cohen’s objection is that rights for animal is too inclusive: only humans should count. Other argue that Singer and Regan are not inclusive enough: should include all animals, maybe even plants (Goodpaster: anything alive should have moral standing) Ironically animal rights is criticized as being essentially anthropocentric – still maintains that only persons count, but some animals count as persons What about species, biosystems, larger ecological systems?

Readings Thomas Nagel (1974), “What is it like to be a bat?”, The Philosophical Review, LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974), 435-50 at: http://organizations.utep.edu/Portals/1475/nagel_bat.pdf