Causal relations, constitutive relations, and interlevel experiments

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Mechanisms and Explanation Phyllis McKay and Jon Williamson University of Kent.
Advertisements

Evidence for Complex Causes
The Contextual Character of Evidence for Causal Claims Mauricio Suárez CaEitS conference, University of Kent, 7 September 2012.
Levels of causation and the interpretation of probability Seminar 2 Federica Russo Philosophy, Louvain & Kent.
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF SCIENCE?
Elena Popa.  Children’s causal learning and evidence.  Causation, intervention, and Bayes nets.  The conditional intervention principle and Woodward’s.
Stuart Glennan Butler University.  The generalist view: Particular events are causally related because they fall under general laws  The singularist.
A Conditional View of Causality Friedel Weinert University of Bradford.
Causality, Mechanisms and Modularity: Structural Models in Econometrics Damien Fennell Centre for the Philosophy of Natural and Social Science London School.
GOAL: UNDERSTAND CAUSAL AND INFLUENCE NETWORKS IN COMPLEX ADAPTIVE SYSTEMS IN ORDER TO CONTROL THEM.
Mechanisms and the Metaphysics of Causation Peter Fazekas Peter Fazekas School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences, The University of Edinburgh.
16 Days and 16 Fallacies II The Metaphysics of Human Origins.
Kent Where causal dualism comes from Monika Koeppl Causality, Cognition and the Constitution of Scientific Phenomena Department of Philosophy University.
Comparative Research.
The Research Design.
Chapter 01 Lecture Outline
CHAPTER 3 RESEARCH TRADITIONS.
Research Methods in Crime and Justice Chapter 5 Causality.
Stuart Glennan Butler University September  Terminological Questions: What is history?  A Selective Survey of Models of Explanation – their Problems.
Marcin Miłkowski, IFiS PAN NCN SONATA BIS Grant #14/E/HS1/00803.
Causation and the Rules of Inference Classes 4 and 5.
Today's topics ● Causal thinking, theories, hypotheses ● Independent and dependent variables; forms of relationships ● Formulating hypothesis; hypothesis.
Explanatory mechanisms: The contribution of systems thinking and critical realism Professor John Mingers Kent Business School University.
Study Questions: 1) Define biology and science.. Study Questions: 1)Define biology and science. - Biology: The scientific study of living systems - Science:
Chapter 13 Models, Mechanisms, & Middle-Range Theory
Debate: Reasoning. Claims & Evidence Review Claims are statements that serve to support your conclusion. Evidence is information discovered through.
Chapter 2 Developmental Psychology A description of the general approach to behavior by developmental psychologists.
An Examination of Science. What is Science Is a systematic approach for analyzing and organizing knowledge. Used by all scientists regardless of the field.
CAUSAL INFERENCE Presented by: Dan Dowhower Alysia Cohen H 615 Friday, October 4, 2013.
“Facts are not science – as the dictionary is not literature” –Martin H. Fischer If science is not facts, what is it?
V13: Causality Aims: (1) understand the causal relationships between the variables of a network (2) interpret a Bayesian network as a causal model whose.
Methodology Matters: Doing Research in the Behavioral and Social Sciences ICS 205 Ha Nguyen Chad Ata.
The Structure of Inquiry Research Design.
Mechanisms, Modularity and Constitutive Explanation Mechanisms and Causality in the Sciences University of Kent, Canterbury, UK Jaakko Kuorikoski.
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF SCIENCE?. SCIENTIFIC WORLD VIEW 1.The Universe Is Understandable. 2.The Universe Is a Vast Single System In Which the Basic Rules.
1 Science!. 2 Science Suppose you knew nothing about science. How would you explain how it rains? Suppose someone did not believe your explanation. Could.
Intro to Scientific Research Methods in Geography Chapter 2: Fundamental Research Concepts.
Research Methods in Psychology Chapter 2. The Research ProcessPsychological MeasurementEthical Issues in Human and Animal ResearchBecoming a Critical.
Biology and “The Nature of Science ” What makes science different from other kinds of human activity? Chapter 1: The Science of Biology.
Distributed Models for Decision Support Jose Cuena & Sascha Ossowski Pesented by: Gal Moshitch & Rica Gonen.
Chapter 10 Lecture Notes Causal Inductive Arguments.
Graduate School for Social Research Autumn 2015 Research Methodology and Methods of Social Inquiry socialinquiry.wordpress.com Causality.
LECTURE 23 MANY COSMOI HYPOTHESIS & PURPOSIVE DESIGN (SUMMARY AND GLIMPSES BEYOND)
Signals of bimodality in fragmentation induced by 3.65 A GeV 12C B.Grabez Institute of Physics Zemun.
1.3: Scientific Thinking & Processes Key concept: Science is a way of thinking, questioning, and gathering evidence.
Introduction to Research
Chapter 1 Section 2 Review
An Introduction to Scientific Research Methods in Geography Chapter 2: Fundamental Research Concepts.
Public Finance and Public Policy Jonathan Gruber Third Edition Copyright © 2010 Worth Publishers 1 of 24 Copyright © 2010 Worth Publishers.
Pag. Jan Lemeire ETRO dept., Vrije Universiteit Brussel Causality in the World vs Causality in the Mind Examples that puzzle philosophers 1.Me not watering.
RESEARCH METHODS Lecture 7. HYPOTHESIS Background Once variables identified Establish the relationship through logical reasoning. Proposition. Proposition.
Mechanistic explanation and the integration of insights from the humanities and cognitive sciences Machiel Keestra, Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies,
Causal truthmakers vs Causal interpretations Federica Russo Philosophy, Kent.
The Scientific Method. Scientifically Solving a Problem Observe Define a Problem Review the Literature Observe some More Develop a Theoretical Framework.
Scientific Inquiry A Look at the processes that tell how Science is Done.
Chapter 6 Selecting a Design. Research Design The overall approach to the study that details all the major components describing how the research will.
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF SCIENCE?
TIME AND CAUSATION: WHERE (AND HOW) DOES CAUSATION ARISE IN THE ARCHITECTURE OF THE COSMOS Jenann Ismael University of Arizona.
Giving the Devil His Due: Relevance in Mechanistic Explanation
For Thursday, read (and write about) Barry Loewer’s “Mental Causation, or Something Near Enough” (chapter 12).
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF SCIENCE?
Causation Analysis in Occupational and Environmental Medicine
Property dualism: objections
Chapter 1 Definition Theory Causality
WHAT IS THE NATURE OF SCIENCE?
Scientific Method.
Comparative Research.
Introduction.
Unit 0 Science Fundamentals.
The Logic of Declarative Statements
Presentation transcript:

Causal relations, constitutive relations, and interlevel experiments Bert Leuridan Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science Ghent University Bert.Leuridan@UGent.Be MaCitS 2009 Canterbury

Craver C.F. (2007), Explaining the Brain. Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Clarendon Press. CLAIM 1: Mutual manipulability is not a sufficient condition for constitutive relevance CLAIM 2: This gives rise to further inferential challenges for (interlevel/intralevel) experimental practice (problem of underdetermination)

Outline 1. Mechanisms 2. Intralevel causal relations 3. Interlevel constitutive relations 4. Mutual manipulability not sufficient for constitutive relevance 4.1. parthood as spatial containment: virus and general 4.2. causal feedback in biology 4.3. measuring synchronicity 4.4. causal-constitutive propagation

1. Mechanisms

Mechanisms A mechanism is a set of entities and activities organized such that they exhibit the phenomenon to be explained. (Craver 2007, 5) More precisely Entities are the components or parts in mechanisms. They have properties that allow them to engage in a variety of activities. [...] Activities are the causal components in mechanisms. [...] Finally, the entities and activities in mechanisms are organized together spatially, temporally, causally, and hierarchically [...] The behavior of the mechanism as a whole requires the organization of its components [...]. (Craver 2007, 5-6) (Carl Craver (2007) Explaining the Brain. Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Clarendon Press.)

Mechanisms S-ing X22-ing X11-ing X44-ing X33-ing A phenomenon (top) and its mechanism (bottom) (from Craver 2007, p. 7)

2. Intralevel causal relations

Mechanisms Question: How should activities be characterized? Answer: Woodward’s manipulationist theory of causation (Craver 2007, chapter 3)

Intralevel causation Manipulationism: The central idea is that causal relationships are distinctive in that they are potentially exploitable for the purposes of manipulation and control. More specifically, variable X is causally relevant to variable Y in conditions W if some ideal intervention of X in conditions W changes the value of Y (or the probability distribution over possible values of Y). (Craver 2007, 94)

Ideal (etiological) interventions U (Craver 2007, p. 97) X S Y I C

Ideal (etiological) interventions An ideal intervention I on X with respect to Y is a change in the value of X that changes Y, if at all, only via the change in X. More specifically, this requirement implies that: (I1) I does not change Y directly; (I2) I does not change the value of some causal intermediate S between X and Y except by changing the value of X; (I3) I is not correlated with some other variable M that is a cause of Y; and (I4) I acts as a ‘switch’ that controls the value of X irrespective of X’s other causes, U. (Craver 2007, 96; adapted from Woodward and Hitchcock 2003a)

Mechanisms S-ing X22-ing X11-ing X44-ing X33-ing A phenomenon (top) and its mechanism (bottom) (from Craver 2007, p. 7)

3. Interlevel constitutive relations

Interlevel constitutive relations Question: how should constitutive relations be characterized? Answer: Negative: constitutive relations are not causal! Positive: constitutive relevance as mutual manipulability Craver (2007, chapter 4) Craver & Bechtel (2007) “Top-down causation without top-down causes,” Biology and Philosophy 22: 547-563.

Constitutive relations Constitutive relations are not causal: Symmetry: All constitutive relations are symmetric; (most) causal relations are asymmetric Synchronicity: All constitutive relations are synchronic; if causes must precede their effects, causal relations are diachronic Logic: mechanisms and their components are not distinct; causal relations ought to involve distict relata

Mutual manipulability Question: When is a part of S a component in the mechanism of S’s - ing? (Craver 2007, 140) When is a part constitutively relevant? Not all parts are components! Craver: Working Account (sufficient condition) [A] component is relevant to the behavior of a mechanism as a whole when one can wiggle the behavior of the whole by wiggling the behavior of the component and one can wiggle the behavior of the component by wiggling the behavior as a whole. The two are related as part to whole and they are mutually manipulable. (Craver 2007, 153)

Mutual manipulability X is a component of the mechanism for S’s -ing if: (i) X is part of S; (ii) in the conditions relevant to the request for explanation there is some change to X’s -ing that changes S’s -ing; and (iii) in the conditions relevant to the request for explanation there is some change to S’s -ing that changes X’s -ing. (Craver 2007, 153)

Mutual manipulability (CR1) When  is set to the value 1 in an ideal intervention, then  takes on the value f(1). (Craver 2007, 155) [Moreover] there should be an ideal intervention on X's -ing that changes the value of S's -ing under the conditions (CR1a) that the intervention, I, leaves all of the other dependency relations in S’s -ing unchanged and (CR1b) that other interventions have removed the contributions of other redundant components. (Craver 2007, 156-157) (CR2) [I]f  is set to the value 1 in an ideal intervention, then  takes on the value f(1). (Craver 2007, 159)

Ideal (interlevel) interventions An ideal intervention I on  with respect to  is a change in the value of  that changes , if at all, only via the change in . This implies that: (I1c) the intervention I does not change  directly; (I2c) I does not change the value of some other variable * that changes the value of  except via the change introduced into ; (I3c) that I is not correlated with some other variable M that is causally independent of I and also a cause of ; and (I4c) that I fixes the value of  in such a way as to screen off the contribution of ’s other causes to the value of . (Craver 2007, 154)

Ideal (interlevel) interventions S-ing I X22-ing X11-ing X44-ing X33-ing

Ideal (interlevel) interventions S-ing I (I4C) X22-ing X11-ing X44-ing X33-ing

Ideal (interlevel) interventions S-ing M (I3C) I (I4C) X22-ing X11-ing X44-ing X33-ing

Ideal (interlevel) interventions S-ing M (I3C) I (I2C) (I4C) X22-ing X11-ing X44-ing X33-ing

Ideal (interlevel) interventions S-ing M (I3C) (I1C) I (I2C) (I4C) X22-ing X11-ing X44-ing X33-ing

4. Mutual Manipulability not sufficient

Constitutive relevance (recap) X is a component of the mechanism for S’s -ing if: (i) X is part of S; (ii) in the conditions relevant to the request for explanation there is some ideal intervention to X’s -ing that changes S’s -ing; and (iii) in the conditions relevant to the request for explanation there is some ideal intervention to S’s -ing that changes X’s -ing. Claim: is this not a sufficient condition for componency start: when is X part of S?

Parthood as spatio-temporal containment? Question: when is X part of S? (NOT “when is X a component of S?” Suggestion: when X is spatio-temporally contained in S

Parthood as spatio-temporal containment? The virus and the general: When a virus kills a general, this seems to be an interlevel causal interaction. [...] However, the general and the virus are not at different mechanistic levels. The virus is not a component in any of the myriad mechanisms composing the general. This is simply a case where things of different sizes interact. (Craver and Bechtel 2007, 556) In practice: virus seems constitutively relevant token virus spatially contained in token general virus’s presence/absence and general’s presence/absence are mutually manipulable virus  general : evident general  virus : cf. the mass extinction of stock to suppress epidemics in agriculture

More than a toy-example Virus & General: toy-example However: examples of causal feedback are legion in the biological, including neuroscience, and the social sciences: mutual manipulability causal feedback is even considered one of the motors generating biological complexity and higher level phenomena – the very phenomena Carl Craver wants to explain (Mitchell forthcoming, 34-44). (Note: causal feedback in figure 1.1, Craver 2007, 7)

Tree of problems IF X part of S AND X and S mutually manipulable, THEN X component of S Parthood as spatial containment Virus a component of the general? Solution 1: virus and general distinct Solution 2: Distinct notion of parthood Solution 3: Relation is diachronic Measuring synchronicity Begs the question Which? Causal-constitutive propagation

Measuring synchronicity Causal, Time-lag Causal, Time-lag Causal, Time-lag Causal, Time-lag Craver (2007, 146) Even if constitutive relations are synchronic, they may look like diachronic relations in practice

Causal-constitutive propagation Even if constitutive relations are synchronic, they may look like diachronic relations in practice Bottom up: do(i=i*)  =’: constitutive, synchronic do(i=i*)  j =g(i*): causal, diachronic j=g(i*)   =’’: constitutive, synchronic Top down: analogously This is not a case of redundancy/recovery! And it is not ruled out by CR1a and CR1b

Causal-constitutive propagation S-ing =f(’1, ’2, ’3) X11-ing 1=’1 X22-ing 2=’2 X33-ing 3=’3

Causal-constitutive propagation S-ing =f(1*, ’2, ’3) X11-ing do(1=1*) X22-ing 2=’2 X33-ing 3=’3 t

Causal-constitutive propagation S-ing =f(1*, g(*1), ’3) X11-ing do(1=1*) X22-ing 2=g(1*) X33-ing 3=’3 t

Causal-constitutive propagation S-ing =f(1*, g(*1), g’(g(1*))) X11-ing do(1=1*) X22-ing 2=g(1*) X33-ing 3=g’(g(1*)) t

Causal-constitutive propagation An intervention on Xi’s i-ing induces, diachronically, a change in S’s -ing An intervention on S’s -ing induces, diachronically, a change in Xi’s i-ing Xi is spatially contained in S Is Xi a component of S? Or are Xi and S mutually causally related?

Conclusion Mechanisms involve intralevel causal relations and interlevel constitutive relations Both are characterized by means of ideal interventions Claim 1: mutual manipulability (+ parthood) not sufficient for constitutive relevance Claim 2: problem of underdetermination in experimental practice: suppose that X is spatially contained in S X and S are mutually manipulable Question: is X a component of S? or are X and S mutually causally related

References Craver (2007), Explaining the Brain : Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Craver and Bechtel (2007), “Top-down causation without top-down causes,” Biology and Philosophy 22: 547-563. Mitchell (forthcoming), Unsimple Truths: Science, Complexity and Policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Woodward (2003), Making Things Happen. A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Woodward and Hitchcock (2003), “Explanatory Generalizations, Part I: a Counterfactual Account,” Nous, 37: 1-24.

Argument from symmetry I endorse the claim that all constitutive relations are symmetric But some Woodward-causal relations are symmetric : Ideal gas law Causal feedback in biological/social sciences Therefore: Argument from symmetry shows a distinction at the conceptual level But provides no way to distinguish between symmetric causal relations and constitutive relations

Argument from synchronicity I endorse the claim that all constitutive relations are synchronic But some Woodward-causal relations are synchronic : ideal gas law? pendulum? Problems: Problem of measuring synchronicity Problem of causal-constitutive propagation Therefore: Argument from synchronicity shows a distinction at the conceptual level But provides no way to distinguish between synchronic causal relations and constitutive relations

Argument from non-distinction I endorse the claim that all causal relations must involve distinct relata Therefore: The argument provides a way to distinguish between causal relations and constitutive relations: if X and Y are related as part and whole, none is a cause of the other Problem: how do we know that X is part of Y?

A note on etiological invariance If invariance under interventions is to count as a sufficient condition for causal relevance (Woodward) Then it should be complemented with the addendum that the relata are not related as part and whole (not currently in Woodward) Otherwise: constitutive relevance implies causal relevance