Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Decision Making, Sensitivity Analysis, and the Value of Information Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
DECISION MAKING Make fantastic decisions using the DECIDE process:
Advertisements

Our final decision… By, The AWESOME class of room 403!
Exploring Career Paths Chapter 10. Objectives  Assess personal qualities that influence career choices  Explain the purpose of career clusters  Evaluate.
Decision Analysis Introduction Chapter 6. What kinds of problems ? Decision Alternatives (“what ifs”) are known States of Nature and their probabilities.
The Distributive Property Section 5.4 Simplifying Expressions 3(4+x)+ x Like terms.
Fraction story. Learning intention: Fraction word problems Adding and simplifying fractions Fraction story word problem using voki 5- Use stories in maths.
Utility Axioms Axiom: something obvious, cannot be proven Utility axioms (rules for clear thinking)
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Utility Functions, Utility Elicitation, and Risk Attitudes Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
Arrow's Impossibility Theorem Kevin Feasel December 10, 2006
1 Introduction to Decision Analysis for Public Policy Decision-Making Ross D. Shachter Management Science and Engineering Stanford University Introduction.
Evaluating Variable Expressions Students will be able to evaluate variable expressions.
MAT 1221 Survey of Calculus Section 7.1 Integration by Parts
Room Planning Living Area 1.
Functions (Notation and Evaluating). Definitions RelationA relationship between sets of information. Typically between inputs and outputs. FunctionA relation.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Introduction: Decision Analysis and Human Judgment Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
 The Distributive Property states that multiplying a sum by a number gives the same result as multiplying each addend by the number and then adding the.
1 Brand Decision Process Speaking to the Head and the Heart To acquire, retain, and grow customers, companies need to know how customers make brand decisions.
Functions, Function Notation, and Composition of Functions.
Integration by Substitution Undoing the Chain Rule TS: Making Decisions After Reflection & Review.
Integrating Exponential Functions TS: Making decisions after reflection and review.
Purpose of the New Member Benefits Guide A set of benefits for new members-packaged specifically for New Members. Benefits that provide immediate value.
Multiple Choice A carpenter wants to drill a hole that is just slightly larger than ¼ inch in diameter. Which of these is the smallest, but still greater.
Notes Over 2.8 Rules for Dividing Negative Numbers. ( Same as Multiplying ) If there is an even number of negative numbers, then the answer is Positive.
Section 3.5 Implicit Differentiation 1. Example If f(x) = (x 7 + 3x 5 – 2x 2 ) 10, determine f ’(x). Now write the answer above only in terms of y if.
Adding SubtractingMultiplyingDividingMiscellaneous.
Presented by Karen Porter UM School of Business Administration & ImpactOnlineMarketing.com Advertising on Facebook Presented by Karen Porter Department.
6 th Grade Chapter 1 Lesson 3 Making Responsible Decisions.
● In this lesson you will learn ● Six steps to making good decisions ● Definitions of success and persistence.
Integers and Absolute Value COURSE 3 LESSON 1-3 Graph the points 2, –3, and 1 on a number line. 1-3.
Chapter 16 March 25, Probability Theory: What an agent should believe based on the evidence Utility Theory: What the agent wants Decision Theory:
1 Automated Planning and Decision Making 2007 Automated Planning and Decision Making Prof. Ronen Brafman Various Subjects.
DADSS Lecture 6: Introduction to Decision Analysis John Gasper.
Molly’s Recess Story Example of a PowerPoint relationship narrative to Introduce a Possible Change in a Child’s Life.
Evaluating Algebraic Expressions 4-1Exponents AF2.1 Interpret positive whole-number powers as repeated multiplication and negative whole-number powers.
Solving Equations involving Fractions
§ 1.5 Equations of Lines.
Section 2-4: Adding Integers using Rules
13.2 Complements and Unions of Events
Instructions for Choice from Envelope
Functions (Notation and Evaluating)
§ 1.5 Equations of Lines.
Properties of Logarithms
Powers and Exponents Simplify 35 – (3 • 2)2. 35 – (3 • 2)2 = 35 – (6)2
Limits – Part 2     Use when a specific value “c” is given to evaluate…
تحليل الحساسية Sensitive Analysis.
Solving Systems using Substitution
Retailing Objectives.
Adding and Subtracting Integers
Decision Analysis Objective
4.6 Cramer’s Rule System of 2 Equations System of 3 Equations
Evaluate the expression if w = -4, x = 2, y = ½, and z = |6 + z| - |7| Original problem. |6 + (-6)| - |7| Substitute values for the variables.
Functions (Notation and Evaluating)
How do Vikings make decisions that are healthy? Vikings keep active!
An algebraic expression that defines a function is a function rule.
Evaluating Expressions
My Personal Education Plan
6.2 – Patterns and Expressions
Decision Analysis Objective
The Mojave tribe By Jackson.
Relations and Functions
Around the room Orders of operations.
Adding with 9’s.
Adding with 10’s.
4.3 Writing Functions Objectives
Agri-science Mr. Bailey
Ethical Decision Making
Adding ____ + 10.
Splash Screen.
Speaking practice 2 Questions
Evaluating an expression with one variable
Presentation transcript:

Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Decision Making, Sensitivity Analysis, and the Value of Information Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.

Personal Decision Making: The Party Problem Joseph K. invites his friends to a party, but needs to decide on the location: –Outdoors (O) on the grass (completely open) –On the Porch (P) (covered above, open on sides) –Inside (I) the living room If the weather is sunny (S), outdoors is best, followed by Porch and Indoors; if it rains (R), the living room is best, followed by Porch and Outdoors

The Party Problem: An Ordered Preferences List O-S (best) P-S I-R I-S P-R O-R (worst)

Evaluating The Prospects O-S (best) P-S I-R I-S P-R O-R (worst) 1 0 B W B W B W B W B W 0 1 B W      

The Party Problem: Adding Probabilities O P I S 0.4 R 0.6 S 0.4 R 0.6 S 0.4 R 0.6

The Party Problem: Substituting Prospects O P I S 0.4 R 0.6 S 0.4 R 0.6 S 0.4 R B W 0 1 B W B W B W B W B W

The Party Problem: Simplifying The Relationship to Preference Probabilities O P I B W B W B W

The Party Problem: Using the Choice Rule O P I B W B W B W <=

Expected Preference-Probability Values O P I S 0.4 R 0.6 S 0.4 R 0.6 S 0.4 R 0.6 Preference Probability 1 0 E-value = E-value= 0.57 E-value=

Computation With Decision Trees: Making the Decision Decision trees are “folded back” to the top most (leftmost, or initial) decision Computation is performed by averaging expected utility (in this case, preference probability) recursively over tree branches from right to left (bottom up), maximizing utility for every decision made and assuming that this is the expected utility for the subtree that follows the computed decision

The Value of Information (VI) We often need to decide what would be the next best piece of information to gather (e.g., within a diagnostic process); that is, what is the best next question to ask (e.g., what would be the result of a urine culture?); Alternatively, we might need to decide how much, if at all, is a paticular additional piece of information worth The Value of Information (VI) of feature f is the marginal expected utility of an optimal decision made knowing f, compared to making it without knowing f The net value of information (NVI) of f = VI(f)-cost(f) NVI is highly useful when deciding what would be the next information item, if any, to investigate

Computing the Value of Information: Requirements Decision Makers are often faced with the option of getting additional information for a certain cost To assess the value of additional information to the decision maker, we need a continuous, real valued utility measure, such as money Thus, we need to map preference probabilities to a monetary scale or an equivalent one (such as time)

Introducing Monetary Values: Bringing in The Wizard We ask the decision maker for her willingness to pay for a change from any state to any other state, assuming we have a wizard who can perform the change instantaneously We can thus create a 1:1 correspondence between preference probabilities and $ values

The Party Problem: Adding Monetary Values Prospect Preference Probability $ Value O-S (best)1 100 P-S I-R I-S P-R O-R (worst) 00

Joseph K.’s Utility Curve $0 $34 $50K $100K Utility + Money Note: Once we know JK’s utilility curve, we can compute his certain equivalent for ANY deal, e.g., a ( deal, which happens to be $34, using graphical or other methods; or the $ certain equivalent of any outcome (e.g., Outdoor location)

The Value of Clairvoyance To compute the value of information, we assume a clairvoyant who knows with certainty all outcomes and always tells the truth However, clairvoyance has a price! Thus, the question is, How Much should we pay the clairvoyant for her forecast (e.g., for telling Joseph K. if it will rain or not)

Computing the Value of Clairvoyance We build a decision tree comparing the optimal decision without clairvoyance to the optimal decision given that the clairvoyant prophesies any of the possible outcomes (in this case, with 100% accuracy) We need to deduct the cost of clairvoyance from the $ value of all outcomes and role the decision tree back as we did before, to determine the expected value of the decision given clairvoyance (and paying for it!) We compute e-values using u-values (which represent the decision maker’s utility for each $ value) At the end (root node) we convert u-values to $ values We then know whether the clairvoyance is worth its cost

Computing The $ Value of Clairvoyance O P I $value U value O P I O P I “S” “R” No clairvoyance U=0.63 (  $46) Buy clairvoyance for $15 U =0.67 (  $51) $value $value-$cost S 0 R 0.4 S 0.6 R 0.4 S 0.6 R 0.4 S 1 S 0 R 1 S 0 S 1 R 0 S $85 U= 0.40  $26 U= 0.57  $40 U= 0.63  $46 $75 $25 $-15 $ 5 $35 U= 0.92  $85 U= 0.50  $35

The Value of Partial Clairvoyance Assume we have a rain detector which, when the weather is going to be sunny or rainy, predicts Rain or Sun 80% of the time, correspondingly; is it worth $10 to use it? In order to compute the value of an uncertain piece of information, we first need to calculate the probability for rain or sun, given each corresponding prediction of the detector This involves reversing the tree in which the detector information is usually given, using Bayes theorem

Computing The Value of Partial Clairvoyance (I): Representing the Detector’s Profile 0.8 “S” 0.2 “R” 0.2 “S” 0.8 “R” 0.4 S 0.6 R

Computing The Value of Partial Clairvoyance (II): Calculating Accuracy by Reversing the Tree S R S R 0.44 “S” 0.56 “R”

Computing The Value of Partial Clairvoyance (III): Calculating the Optimal Decision With and Without Clairvoyance To actually calculate the value of uncertain information, we compare the expected utility of the best decision without the information to the expected utility of the decision with the information, as we did before We use the distribution of real world states given the semi- clairvoyant’s prediction (using our accuracy calculation) In this particular case (80% accuracy), the value without detector is U = 0.627, or $45.83; the value with partial information is U = 0.615, or $44.65 Thus, for Joseph K., this particular detector is not worth the money

Sensitivity Analysis The main insights into a decision are often given by an analysis of the influence of the given probabilities and utilities on the final decision and its value We thus get a sense as to how sensitive the expected utility and optimal decisions are to each parameter, and can focus our attention (and perhaps, further elicitation efforts) on the most important aspects of the problem

The Party Problem: Sensitivity Analysis O P I S p R 1-p S p R 1-p S p R 1-p 1 0 U = p U = p U = p $value U value

Sensitivity Analysis of the Party Problem U $ P O:p 90 P: p I: p Free clairvoyance: p The value of information

Tornado Diagrams We can calculate the lower and upper bounds on the expected utility E(U) of the optimal decision for the full range of changes in each parameter X i while leaving all other parameters at their nominal (default) value We get a quick sense of the potential influence of each parameter on the expected utility But: –It ignores the change distribution –It ignores the dependencies between parameters X4 X12 X3 X5 X7 X