WHO IS IN CHARGE OF CAUSATION? Olaf Dekkers/20-11-2014 Dept Clinical Epidemiology Aarhus and Leiden.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Introductory Mathematics & Statistics for Business
Advertisements

Andrea M. Landis, PhD, RN UW LEAH
Deriving Biological Inferences From Epidemiologic Studies.
Holland on Rubin’s Model Part II. Formalizing These Intuitions. In the 1920 ’ s and 30 ’ s Jerzy Neyman, a Polish statistician, developed a mathematical.
Statistics.  Statistically significant– When the P-value falls below the alpha level, we say that the tests is “statistically significant” at the alpha.
LSU-HSC School of Public Health Biostatistics 1 Statistical Core Didactic Introduction to Biostatistics Donald E. Mercante, PhD.
The counterfactual logic for public policy evaluation Alberto Martini hard at first, natural later 1.
Copyright EM LYON Par accord du CFC Cession et reproduction interdites Research in Entrepreneurship- The problem of unobserved heterogeneity Frédéric Delmar.
 Assertions: unsupported declaration of a belief  Prejudice: a view without evidence for or against  Premises: explicit evidence that lead to a conclusion.
ABCWINRisk and Statistics1 Risk and Statistics Risk Assessment in Clinical Decision Making Ulrich Mansmann Medical Statistics Branch University of Heidelberg.
Causation – Seminar Jørn Olsen 20 November, 2014 Causation – Seminar Jørn Olsen 20 November, 2014.
Event Causation Daniel von Wachter
By Dr. Ahmed Mostafa Assist. Prof. of anesthesia & I.C.U. Evidence-based medicine.
EVIDENCE BASED MEDICINE
Comparative Research.
Designing Clinical Research 2009 Confounding and Causal Inference Warren Browner.
Study Designs By Az and Omar.
Why Take This Course? How to answer policy and management questions –What is our clinical pathways program doing? Should we keep it? –Should we fund the.
Tests of significance & hypothesis testing Dr. Omar Al Jadaan Assistant Professor – Computer Science & Mathematics.
 Be familiar with the types of research study designs  Be aware of the advantages, disadvantages, and uses of the various research design types  Recognize.
The problem of sampling error It is often the case—especially when making point predictions—that what we observe differs from what our theory predicts.
Epidemiology The Basics Only… Adapted with permission from a class presentation developed by Dr. Charles Lynch – University of Iowa, Iowa City.
Today's topics ● Causal thinking, theories, hypotheses ● Independent and dependent variables; forms of relationships ● Formulating hypothesis; hypothesis.
What’s in the news right now related to science???? Flesh eating bacteria.
FRAMING RESEARCH QUESTIONS The PICO Strategy. PICO P: Population of interest I: Intervention C: Control O: Outcome.
ECON ECON Health Economic Policy Lab Kem P. Krueger, Pharm.D., Ph.D. Anne Alexander, M.S., Ph.D. University of Wyoming.
 Is there a comparison? ◦ Are the groups really comparable?  Are the differences being reported real? ◦ Are they worth reporting? ◦ How much confidence.
Julio A. Ramirez, MD, FACP Professor of Medicine Chief, Infectious Diseases Division, University of Louisville Chief, Infectious Diseases Section, Veterans.
CONFOUNDING DEFINITION: A third variable (not the exposure or outcome variable of interest) that distorts the observed relationship between the exposure.
Hypothesis Testing Hypothesis Testing Topic 11. Hypothesis Testing Another way of looking at statistical inference in which we want to ask a question.
No criminal on the run The concept of test of significance FETP India.
Testing Theories: The Problem of Sampling Error. The problem of sampling error It is often the case—especially when making point predictions—that what.
V13: Causality Aims: (1) understand the causal relationships between the variables of a network (2) interpret a Bayesian network as a causal model whose.
HSRP 734: Advanced Statistical Methods July 31, 2008.
통계적 추론 (Statistical Inference) 삼성생명과학연구소 통계지원팀 김선우 1.
EXPERIMENTAL EPIDEMIOLOGY
MSA830: Introduction Petter Mostad
Study designs. Kate O’Donnell General Practice & Primary Care.
Do Now  What does logos appeal to in an advertisement?  Give three examples.
Health and Disease in Populations 2002 Sources of variation (1) Paul Burton! Jane Hutton.
1 Health and Disease in Populations 2002 Session 8 – 21/03/02 Randomised controlled trials 1 Dr Jenny Kurinczuk.
Compliance Original Study Design Randomised Surgical care Medical care.
Making Randomized Clinical Trials Seem Less Random Andrew P.J. Olson, MD Assistant Professor Departments of Medicine and Pediatrics University of Minnesota.
Scientific Explanation  Suppose we assume that explanation and prediction of phenomena are the goals/purposes of science  Suppose we also assume that.
Summary: connecting the question to the analysis(es) Jay S. Kaufman, PhD McGill University, Montreal QC 26 February :40 PM – 4:20 PM National Academy.
The inference and accuracy We learned how to estimate the probability that the percentage of some subjects in the sample would be in a given interval by.
P1) X has properties a, b, c, and z. P2) Y also has properties a, b, and c. C) By analogy, Y has property z. X: primary analogue Y: secondary analogue.
1 Basics of Inferential Statistics Mark A. Weaver, PhD Family Health International Office of AIDS Research, NIH ICSSC, FHI Lucknow, India, March 2010.
Validity in epidemiological research Deepti Gurdasani.
A quick reference to literature searches
Ellen S. Cohn and Wendy J. Coster
Chapter 9 -Hypothesis Testing
CHAPTER 4 Designing Studies
CHAPTER 4 Designing Studies
Types of Research Studies Architecture of Clinical Research
Statistical Core Didactic
Confidence Intervals and p-values
Quasi Experimental Methods I
Chapter 4: Inductive Arguments
Explanation of slide: Logos, to show while the audience arrive.
If You Aren’t Dong Arguments, You Aren’t Doing Evidence
Statistics for Business and Economics (13e)
Lecture 3: Introduction to confounding (part 1)
11/20/2018 Study Types.
Comparative Research.
How EBM brings the connection between evidence and measurement into focus. Benjamin Smart.
Interpreting Basic Statistics
Statistical Reasoning December 8, 2015 Chapter 6.2
CHAPTER 4 Designing Studies
Chapter 3 Hernán & Robins Observational Studies
Presentation transcript:

WHO IS IN CHARGE OF CAUSATION? Olaf Dekkers/ Dept Clinical Epidemiology Aarhus and Leiden

Le Malade Imaginere (1673), Act III

Basic problem I  We don’t usually see that x causes y  Causal judgement is based on inference

Basic problem II  Inferences can be wrong  Statistics do not differentiate between association and cuasation

Basic problem III  We are taught, over and over, to be sceptical  Why most research findings are false. Ioannidis 2005  Am J Epidemiology does not allow the use of the word ‘effect(s)’ to denote association(s) It may promise more than an observational study can deliver Only studies in which there is an intervention to change exposure can study causes It misleads the uncritical reader

So…  Making causal inferences in clinical research is not straightforward (old news)  But we should not refrain from searching for causes, as clinical research aims to improve health

Where do we stand today? Theories of causation -Regularity theories (Hume) -Probabilistic theories -Counterfactual theories -Interventionism

Counterfactual theory of causation

Counterfactual theory cf Paul LA Counterfactual theories Intuitive interpretation: If it is the case that Y occurs after X and that Y does not occur in the absence of X, than X is a cause of Y More formally: “X causes Y because the counterfactual ‘if not X then not Y’ is true.”

“X causes Y”  Counterfactual thinking is intuitively appealing  Italy lost the game (Y), because the referee was not objective (X)  She was late (Y), because of the snow (X)  She/he fell deeply in love with him/her (Y), because of his beautiful eyes (X)  Attacking Pearl Harbor (X), caused the USA to enter WWII (Y)

Why do we need causation theories?  What is a philosophical theory of causation giving an account for?  The theory facilitates causal inference, and gives an answer to the question how we can know whether X is a cause of Y (epistemic notion) In epidemiology the epistemic notion is more relevant  The theory might facilitate our understanding of what causation (in general) stands for (semantic/ontologic notion)

Epistemic notion of causation  Epistemic notion  Obesity (x) is a cause of mortality (y) because the counterfactual ‘if not X then not Y’ is true (in a least one person) (Counterfactual theory)  Obesity (x) is a cause of mortality (y) because being obese increases mortality probability (Probability theory)

Ontologic notion of causation  Semantic/ontologic notion  There are no working forces, there are only probabilities (Probability theory)  This notion is in a counterfactual framework difficult as the theory refers to non-occurring situations (or even worse: non-existing worlds)

Counterfactuals: philosophical problems  Pre-emption (see next slide) Counterfactual dependence is not a necessary condition for causation  Prevented causes Think of a new extremely powerful weapon (X) causing world-destruction (Y). Causation cannot be judged in a counterfactual framework  Many irrelevant causes Counterfactual dependence is not a sufficient condition for causation

Pre-emption Smoking Hypertension AMI

An unstable christmas tree Counterfactual theory needs many auxillary theories to keep it upright

Counterfactuals in epidemiology  What makes the theory so appealing in epidemiology?  Counterfactuals point towards non-existing situations: ‘If not X, etc’  In medical research counterfactuals do not exist  Even not in cross-over studies  But: we are used to control groups  Control group as approximation for the counterfactual  Counterfactual thinking resembles the way we do studies

Counterfactual in epidemiology BUT  No practical decision rule to infer causality  Refers to non-occurring situations  There is however a set of basic assumptions for causal inference in the counterfactual framework (cf Hernan):  ‘Exchangeability’  ‘Positivity’  X=1 and X=0 (exposure contrast) should be well-defined

Counterfactuals and exchangeability Patients (X=1) Outcome Y=y|X=1 Patients (X=0) Outcome Y=y|X=0

Counterfactuals and exchangeability Patients (X=1) Outcome Y=y|X=1 Patients (X=0) Outcome Y=y|X=0 Counterfactual definition of causation: If it is the case that Y occurs after X and that Y does not occur in the absence of X, than X is a cause of Y This can be inferred from a comparison under exchangeability: Two groups would have had an identical outcome (Y=y) if the exposure (X=1 or X=0) would have been the same

Exchangeability  Two groups would have had an identical outcome (Y=y) if the exposure (X=1 or X=0) would be the same  If the baseline prognosis is the same, then a difference in outcome between groups has a causal interpretation  This is threatened by confounding in observational studies

Confounding and selection-bias  Causal question Z in an observational study  Epidemiological answer: bias and confounding unlikely  Then we are (philosophically speaking) referring to a counterfactual theory of causation

RCTs: a counterfactual paradigm

A RCT

DREAM

RCTs  The randomized design fits the counterfactual framework  The control group approaches the counterfactual situation by design (randomization)  It is deprived from theory

RCTs  The randomized design fits the counterfactual framework  It gives decision rule for causation:  if a treatment x is randomized, then a difference in outcome Y between two groups has logically a causal interpretation because the counterfactual statement holds

RCT: a counterfactual paradigm  The counterfactual model and the RCT fit well  Stop here: don’t move philosophically further

Epistemic reduction?  The counterfactual model and the RCT fit well  That does not mean that we can only have causal inference in case of randomization  Reason: the counterfactual model is (as we have seen) neither sufficient nor necessary to infer causality

Ontologic reduction?  The counterfactual model and the RCT fit well  A reason for some to accept only interventions as true causes (interventionism)  This does not mean that there is only causation in case of a (randomized) intervention  Things you can hardly intervene like SES

Interventionism  Makes causation human-like  Many phenomenon difficult to capture in an interventionist framework  Big Bang  Volcano Eruptions  Postulation of hypothetical interventions (which do not differ from counterfactuals)

Who is in charge of causation?

Where do we stand today?

What do we believe?  Option 1: Roziglitazone reduces blood glucose level because the counterfactual (if not X then not Y) is true?  Option 2: Roziglitazone reduces blood glucose level because of an intrinsic drug capacity to do so?

Counterfactual theory presupposes causation  If we adopt option 2:  The counterfactual notion is true because x is a cause of y, and not the other way round  Counterfactual thinking can still be used to judge causality as it is be derived from causality  But: it can not be the only argument for causation

How foolish are we today?  This was not shown in a RCT  We have no ultimate counterfactual proof

How foolish are we today? JAMA 1982  RR roken – myocardinfarct = 2.0  Risico normaliseert niet na weghalen risicofactor

We (researchers) have to do more  There are reasons to think that risk factors and drugs have some inherent effects  But we have to do more for causal inference  Experiments (thinking along the lines of counterfactual theories is helpful)  Explaining why x causes y  Stating the conditions under which x causes y  This means that the philosopher is not in charge of causation

In summary  Counterfactual thinking fits epidemiology, probably because we use preferably a controlled study design  Counterfactuals can be helpful when thinking how to design/perform/analyze a study  Causality can not be reduced to counterfactual dependence, and causal inference requires more than counterfactual dependence