Phenomenology and Reflexivity Getting clear(er) about “self- representational” theories of consciousness.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Commentary on Katalin Balog, In defense of the phenomenal concept strategy Assistant Prof. István Aranyosi, Bilkent University, Ankara, Turkey.
Advertisements

Consciousness and Thought: Wrap-Up Talk
Phenomenal Concepts and the Explanatory Gap
R & R David Chalmers. Triangle object content phenomenology.
Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers.
Constructing the World Week 4 David Chalmers. The Case for Scrutability (1) PQTI and the Cosmoscope (2) The Cosmoscope Argument (3) Empirical Scrutability.
Joe Levines Purple Haze. Physical/Phenomenal Gaps P = the complete microphysical truth Q = a phenomenal truth Q1: Is there an epistemic gap between.
Varieties of Representationalism David J. Chalmers.
65,536 Definitions of Physicalism David J. Chalmers.
The Varieties of Self- Awareness David Chalmers. Self-Awareness Self-awareness = awareness of oneself One is self-aware if one stands in a relation of.
The Fregean Content of Perception. Varieties of Representationalism Representationalism: Phenomenal property = representing content C in manner M Pure.
Freges The Thought Meaning of true –Grammatically appears as an adjective –So a thing cannot be true, but a picture or idea about it might be The thing.
The Extended Mind.
Summer 2011 Tuesday, 8/9. Clark and Chalmers on the Extended Mind Where does the mind stop and the rest of the world begin? What are C & C asking here?
Theories of Knowledge Knowledge is Justified-True-Belief Person, S, knows a proposition, y, iff: Y is true; S believes y; Y is justified for S. (Note:
Summer 2011 Tuesday, 8/ No supposition seems to me more natural than that there is no process in the brain correlated with associating or with.
Libertarianism A Libertarian, such as Taylor:
Ambiguous contents? Arvid Båve, Higher seminar in Theoretical Philosophy, FLoV, Gothenburg University, 8 May 2013.
Meditations on First Philosophy
Huiming Ren Shandong University of China. What we could learn from the case of veridical perceptions.
Kant’s Transcendental Idealism according to Henry E. Allison Itzel Gonzalez Phil 4191 March 2, 2009.
Universals, Properties, Kinds
EPM: Chs V & VI Pete Mandik Chairman, Department of Philosophy Coordinator, Cognitive Science Laboratory William Paterson University, New Jersey USA “RED!”
Albert Gatt LIN3021 Formal Semantics Lecture 5. In this lecture Modification: How adjectives modify nouns The problem of vagueness Different types of.
Kant, Transcendental Aesthetic
CAS LX 502 Semantics 1b. The Truth Ch. 1.
LOCKE ON SUBSTANCE (Part 2 of 2) Text source: Essay Concerning Human Understanding, bk. 2 ch. 23.
Speech and Phenomena Philosophy 157 G. J. Mattey ©2002.
Philosophy of Mind Matthew Soteriou. Physicalism The physicalist answer to the question of the relation between the mental and the physical: The mental.
Conceptual modelling. Overview - what is the aim of the article? ”We build conceptual models in our heads to solve problems in our everyday life”… ”By.
Intentionality and Biological Functions Ingvar Johansson, Institute for Formal Ontology and Medical Information Science, Saarbrücken
2013/2014 RELATIONS OF CHAPTER “EMOTIONS” (In the Book of Robert Nozick “Examined Life”) Lezione 22 31/3/14 by Gabriele Buratti & Maria Teresa Carini.
The Introduction to the Elements of the Philosophy of Right: Right, Will and Freedom.
Philosophical Foundations Chapter 26. Searle v. Dreyfus argument §Dreyfus argues that computers will never be able to simulate intelligence §Searle, on.
Philosophy of Mind Lecture 6 The Phenomenology of Experience and the Objects of Perception.
The physical reductive explainability of phenomenal consciousness and the logical impossibility of zombies Marco Giunti University of Cagliari (Italy)
1 5 Frege’s Anti-Psychologism. 2 The Rejection of Psychologism See Dummett 1993: ch.4 See Dummett 1993: ch.4 Frege’s statements: “Always separate sharply.
Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 3 20/9/2007 Text: Introduction (III-IX) Claus Beisbart The Power of Judgment.
Discrete dynamical systems and intrinsic computability Marco Giunti University of Cagliari, Italy
How to color McTaggart Benj Hellie University of Toronto the Beach II 25 February 2007.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
Philosophy 224 Persons and Morality: Pt. 1. Ah Ha! Dennett starts by addressing an issue we’ve observed in the past: the tendency to identify personhood.
René Descartes ( AD) Meditations on First Philosophy (1641) (Text, pp )
LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY Both logic and ontology are important areas of philosophy covering large, diverse, and active research projects. These two areas overlap.
EPM: Ch XII Pete Mandik Chairman, Department of Philosophy Coordinator, Cognitive Science Laboratory William Paterson University, New Jersey USA.
Husserl III. Phenomenology as Transcendental Philosophy Philosophy 157 G. J. Mattey ©2002.
The Turn to the Science The problem with substance dualism is that, given what we know about how the world works, it is hard to take it seriously as a.
Husserlian Phenomenology Dr. James A. Snyder Postmodern Philosophy.
Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 7 2/10/2007 Text: Critique of the Aesthtical Power of Judgment (9-17) Claus.
Descates Meditations II A starting point for reconstructing the world.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 7 Mackie & Moral Skepticism
Need worksheet from yellow folder – arg from perceptual variation.
Intertheoretic Reduction and Explanation in Mathematics
On Consciousness as Higher-Order Thought Charles Siewert Rice University.
The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel’s Idealism.
An analysis of Kant’s argument against the Cartesian skeptic in his ‘Refutation of Idealism” Note: Audio links to youtube are found on my blog at matthewnevius.wordpress.com.
The Chinese Room Argument Part II Joe Lau Philosophy HKU.
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE Some topics and historical issues of the 20 th century.
The Nature of God Nancy Parsons. Attributes- Nature of God Candidates should be able to demonstrate knowledge and understanding of: 1.God as eternal,
The philosophy of Ayn Rand…. Objectivism Ayn Rand is quoted as saying, “I had to originate a philosophical framework of my own, because my basic view.
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
The zombie argument: responses
Joe Levine’s Purple Haze
If You Aren’t Dong Arguments, You Aren’t Doing Evidence
Do we directly perceive objects? (25 marks)
Metaphysics & Epistemology
"CONSCIOUSNESS AND QUALITIES"
ROMANTIC HERMENEUTICS
ROMANTIC HERMENEUTICS
Presentation transcript:

Phenomenology and Reflexivity Getting clear(er) about “self- representational” theories of consciousness

One of the oldest phenomenological ideas about consciousness is that it has a reflexive or self- presentational aspect. (precedents: Aristotle, Brentano, Kant, Husserl, Sartre, Heidegger) This aspect might help in explaining the “for-me”- ness (subjective character) of consciousness, or its phenomenal content (qualitative character), or both Self-representational theories plausibly solve many objections to HOT and HOM theories. Self-representational theories (first approximation) hold that: A (representational) state is conscious iff it represents itself, or some aspect of itself. Self-representational theories (e.g. Kriegel 2009, Kriegel and Williford 2006, Smith 1986, 2005)

Types of self-representational theories Structural (proper part): A conscious state has, as a separable proper part of its structure, an element that represents all or part of that state Indexical-involving: A conscious state has a part that makes indexical (or quasi-indexical) reference to that very state. Structural (improper part): A conscious state has an essential or inseparable part or aspect that represents all or part of that state

Things to get clearer on What sense of “representation”? (many linguistic expressions, e.g., are self- representing, but this doesn’t make them conscious) What is self-representation? How is this reflexive relation achieved? Infinite regress worries Token-type problems

Self-representational theories and the justification of phenomenal beliefs It’s reasonable to think that any good reflexive theory of consciousness must explain the justification of phenomenal beliefs: for instance, my belief that I am now having a state with a certain phenomenal character R. Also it seems plausible that the self-representation of the state should play a role in this justification. But on any of these views, all that is available to play a role in the justification of such a belief is a phenomenal- state token: it is not clear how we get from the self- representation of a token state to general beliefs (about types and what falls under them).

Self-representation and the phenomenal concept strategy On the phenomenal concept strategy (PCS), occurrent phenomenal states “figure in” or are parts of (occurrent) judgments about them, either as components of concepts used or directly as parts of the judgments themselves. At least some PCS theories are reasonably construed as self-representational theories: in figuring in judgments about it a phenomenal state represents (or presents) itself.

Using self-representation to explain phenomenal judgments “The first-order phenomenal state, being self-presenting in the way that only phenomenal states can be, figures directly in the belief, as a mode of presentation of itself…. That is, [the] first-order mental state-token is deployed, qua predicative constituent of the belief, to refer to a phenomenal type that the token presents itself as belonging to” –Horgan, Tienson, and Graham 2006 If this is correct, then we can explain the justification of phenomenal judgments in terms of the occurrence (or being-presented) of phenomenal states: the mere occurrence of the phenomenal state is sufficient to present it under a “mode of presentation” which can then be used to make a judgment about it However, if “mode of presentation” is anything like a Fregean sense (i.e. something ideal, with content-conferring properties), this won’t quite do, since we have no account of HOW something like a (token) phenomenal state can work as a “mode of presentation” of itself.

Improving the theory: some phenomenological suggestions There are some terminological and conceptual improvements we can make to the basic self- representational theory by switching to the terminology of Husserl’s phenomenology There are substantive reasons for these changes, but they can also be taken just as terminological suggestions, if preferred

First suggestion: Presentation, not representation What we are interested in with reflexive theories of consciousness is how states can present themselves to subjects (along with, perhaps, also presenting external objects). This might be embedded within a general theory of cognitive “representation,” but if we do not presuppose physicalism there is no obvious reason it must be. Additionally, talking about presentation rather then representation avoids the need to posit re- presentational features of the relevant states and avoids begging questions, e.g. against the possibility of perceptual direct realism.

Second suggestion: Acts, not states In Husserl’s special sense of the term, an “act” is any experience with intentional (presentational) content for a subject. However, because presentational acts present something as something, they are inherently (in one sense) “concept-involving”. It might be thought that this begs questions by assuming a prior “theory of intentionality”. However, it is reasonable to suppose that an account of the reflexive structure of consciousness doesn’t have to solve this problem.

The modified theory With these modifications, we have the following: An act is conscious if and only if it is an act that (in addition to whatever else it presents also) presents itself. For Husserl, it is definitional that all acts are conscious. So it might be better to build reflexiveness into the definition of an act: A (self-conscious) act is a presentation (of something) that also presents itself.

Disclaimers The point of a theory of this kind isn’t to give an account of sufficient conditions for a state (conceived, say, in functional or neurophysiological terms) to be conscious. It also isn’t to give an account of how something that is conceived already as representational becomes a conscious representation. The point is just, given the phenomenologically plausible datum that conscious acts present themselves to us in some way, to model this self- presentation.

Act Self-presentation How can we model phenomenologically this self- presentational structure of the act? It is helpful to consider the structure of the “transcendental epoche”, the means by which we gain insight into the phenomenological structure of acts, according to Husserl Although the is epoche is used in deliberate, explicit reflection, we can also gain insight into the “pre-reflective” but nevertheless reflexive structure of the acts themselves.

The transcendental epoche In the transcendental epoche, insight into the structure of the act itself is achieved by “bracketing” – or putting out of commission -- the “positing” of the ordinary intentional object. According to Husserl, this converts the structure of the act from a “pre-objective” to an “object” status. We achieve explicit access to both noetic (really immanent) and noematic (ideal) aspects of the act. The transcendental epoche yields access to the whole domain of experience, which survives even the “bracketing” of the whole (spatiotemporal) world

Transcendental epoche and reflexivity The explicit reflection that occurs in the performance of the transcendental epoche is itself only possible because of an “implicit” reflexivity (or self-presenting aspect) already there in ordinary conscious acts. It is plausible that, if my current act is one of presenting some content, it is possible (given that I also have a general concept of experience) for me to know that this act is one that presents this content. Thus, even if the explicit consideration of the (first-order) act in the epoche is (in some sense) a new act, it is possible only because this first-order act already (in some way) presents itself (even if only implicitly and non-objectively) Cf. Husserl: “In the very essence of an experience lies determined not only that, but also whereof it is a consciousness, and in what determinate or indeterminate sense it is this.”

“In the case of an experience directed to something immanent …(so-called ‘internal’ perception), perception and perceived form essentially an unmediated unity, that of a single concrete cogitatio. Here the perceiving includes its Object in itself in such a manner that it only can be separated abstractively, only as an essentially non-selfsufficient moment, from its Object.” (Husserl 1913, pp ). “…there is a certain, extraordinarily important two-sidedness in the essence of the sphere of mental processes, of which we can also say that in mental processes there is to be distinguished a subjectively oriented side and an objectively oriented side…” (Husserl 1913 p. 161)

Conclusion: Husserl’s theory is a self- presentational act theory that holds that acts have an inseparable part -- or essential aspect-- that presents the act itself This part or aspect presents the act’s noematic (ideal and content-determining) as well as its noetic (real) features. It is probably best to construe the self- presentational part itself as an ideal (noematic) rather than a real part.

Noema and Sense In 1969, Dagfinn Føllesdal drew an analogy between Husserl’s noemata (or noematic senses) and Fregean senses: – Noema (or noematic sense) is a generalization of the notion of meaning (Sinn) – The intentional act presents its object by means of its noema (thus the notion of noema also generalizes the notion of a mode of presentation) – Noema determines object but not conversely – One and the same noema may be shared by different token acts: thus the noema is not a real component of the token act. It’s, rather, an ideal (or abstract) part.

Another analogy: Epoche and quotation (Thomasson 2006) The kind of explicit reflective access that we get in performing the epoche might be compared to quotation or “semantic ascent” We “quote” the content in order to get access to the content-conferring properties of the act, the properties in virtue of which it has and presents its content Even if most conscious states aren’t explicitly “quoted” in this way, they must, structurally, be quotable

Taking both analogies seriously: A (conscious) act which presents an (ordinary) content also presents, inexplicitly, the ideal (noematic) features of itself in virtue of which it presents that content On this kind of view, a conscious act which presents a content is also implicitly self- presented as the kind of act that has that kind of content. Thus, the act, which involves a mode of presentation of the object, also presents the mode of presentation itself This allows us to make an explicit phenomenal judgment: “I am having an experience of that type” (i.e. an experience that presents its (ordinary) content in that way).

This accounts for the subjective (for-me-ness) aspect of consciousness but it might also help to account for the qualitative aspect as well. In particular, if we accept transparency, it is reasonable to suppose that the self-presenting state, in presenting itself, presents itself as the kind of state that presents an object having certain properties Thus, the judgment that I am having an experience of phenomenal type R might simply result from a reflective modification of the act in which I present an object with a related or identical property Qualitative Aspect and Transparency

Self-(re)presentational theories and the hard problem Do self-(re)presentational theories help us understand the hard problem, in the sense that they help to explain why there should be at least an explanatory gap between functional/structural features and consciousness? Ans: Possibly, but only if the self-(re)presentational aspect of a state (in virtue of which it is conscious) doesn’t make a functional/causal/structural difference This will be the case iff a state’s presenting itself isn’t a further functional/structural relationship (not even one borne to itself)

On structural (proper part) theories, the part of the token state that presents the whole state is a real and separable part, so it seems that if we remove it we make a structural/functional difference. On indexical-involving theories, the indexical presentation of a state also seems to make a structural/functional difference However, a structural (improper part) theory might work better. On such a theory, since the self- presentational part of the state is not a real part, it plausibly doesn’t make a structural/functional difference.

How can a state present itself without this self-presentation making a structural/functional difference? We’ll get the right kind of theory if the features of the state in virtue of which it presents itself aren’t further structural/functional parts, but rather formal features But how do we model this self-presentation in virtue of formal features?

One possibility: set self-membership On this approach, we model a state, A, with the (first-order) content B as : A= {A, B}, using (non- well-founded) set membership to model presentation We might then hold that extensionally we just have A and B and the functional relations between them, but there is an additional formal relation of presentation But it’s hard to see how this formal relation could be realized And it’s not clear that we avoid the infinite- regress problem

A Gödelian analogy? (cf. Hofstadter 2006) Consider the Gödel sentence G: G  ~Prov(“G”) This sentence is essentially “self-quoting” where the device of quotation is Gödel numbering The availability of the quotational device allows it to present – in addition to the straightforward number- theoretical claim it makes – itself. We might call this “implicit” self-quotation Roughly speaking, the quotational device yields access to the (syntactic) properties in virtue of which the sentence has the (first-order) content it does

For the Gödel sentence, there is a sense in which even a complete description of its intra-systematic (i.e. syntactic) properties leaves open the question of its truth Analogously, if conscious states are implicitly self-quotational (in something like the Gödel sense) then even a complete description of their real, intra-systematic (i.e. functional/structural) properties might leave open the question of whether they’re conscious

Further questions In the Gödel case, (implicit) self-quotation is achieved by the device of using Gödel numbers to encode syntactic properties. What’s the analogous device in the consciousness case? In the Gödel case, we only achieve an insight into its truth by “jumping out” of the system and considering systematic properties of the whole. How do we achieve (the analogue to) this “jumping out” in the consciousness case?

Conclusions Taking up insights of phenomenology, it’s reasonable to construe conscious states as acts that (implicitly) present their own ideal content- determining properties. This kind of self-presentational theory solves problems that arise for (other) self- representational theories If we can make sense of such self-presentation in virtue of ideal content-determining properties, we might be able to account for the existence of an explanatory gap