The Categorical Imperative

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Immanuel Kant Reason in Ethics.
Advertisements

March 27, 2012 Kantian Deontology. Act Utilitarianism An action is morally wrong if and only if there is an alternative action that produces a greater.
Non-Consequentialism
What matters is the motive
What is deontology?.
Deontology ‘Deontology’ come from the Greed word deontos, which means ‘duty.’ This moral tradition is centered around always doing one’s duty. It is ultimately.
Lecture 8: Freedom, Work and the Body Outline: 1.Self-Positing and Freedom: Toward a Solution 2.Freedom and Work 3.Work and the Body 4.Fichte and Marx.
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
Categorical Imperative
Kantian Ethics (Duty and Reason)
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
KANT 2 IMPOSSIBLE TO UNIVERSALIZE IMMORAL PRINCIPLES.
Deontology: the Ethics of Duty
Ethical Theory.
Kant. Kant desire Kant desire impulse Kant desire impulse incentive.
Phil 160 Kant.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative and Euthanasia
Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
Kant’s deontological ethics
Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals Immanuel Kant Enriquez | Lee | Lim | Montano | Rombaoa.
An Introduction to Ethics Week Three: Deontology and Kant.
Kant’s Ethics of Duty 3 insights form the basis for his theory  An action has moral worth if it is done for the sake of duty. (DUTY)  An action is morally.
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Kantian Ethics Introduction to Philosophy Jason M. Chang.
Kant’s Deontological Ethics. The Plan  What is Deontology?  Good Wills and Right Actions  The Categorical Imperative  Examples and Applications.
Immanuel Kant ( ) Defends a deontological approach to morality. Everyone must admit that if a law is to be morally valid…then it must.
Kantianism/Deontology: Non-Consequentialism
Kantian ethics (& suicide): Kantian ethics (& suicide): Immanuel Kant ( ). A German philosopher. Ought implies Can Maxims Categorical Imperative.
1 Kant’s Understanding of Skepticism and Imperatives: Immanuel Kant’s ( ): Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals: Survey of Section II: Transition.
Kant What Gives An Act Moral Worth? Consequences: No. Why? 1.Control 2.Persons have intrinsic value, not instrumental value Motives: Yes.
Immanuel Kant. Two worlds Reason is part of the intelligible world Sensible (Lesser faculty) Part of the world of nature (empirical)
Categorical and Practical Imperative
Immanuel Kant Duty Ethics The moral worth of an action depends on motive (do the right thing for the right reason)
Duties, Rights, and Kant Ethics Dr. Jason M. Chang.
Kant’s Ethics Kant’s quotes are from FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS.
Deontological Morality IMMANUEL KANT. ARGUMENT 1 VS. HAPPINESS (395) 1) Telic Principle: In an organized being suitably adapted to the purpose of life,
Ethical Principles: “Good” vs. “Right” Current Issues – LHS.
Lecture 6 Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant ( )
Immanuel Kant Deontological Ethics.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant By David Kelsey.
The law is the study of how to break contracts!
Class 6 Kant. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) From Königsberg, Germany.
© Michael Lacewing Kant’s Categorical Imperative Michael Lacewing
The Moral Philosophy of Immanuel Kant The Ethics of Duty and Reason
The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Immanuel Kant.
Immanuel Kant and the moral law. Kant (1) Kant’s ethics are those of the deist, rather than the theist. He was an important thinker in the deist project,
Immanuel Kant The Categorical Imperative The Age of Reason Immanuel Kant.
Standard Form ► 1. State your position ► 2. 1 st Premise (Fact 1: State fact and source) ► 3. 2 nd Premise (Fact 2: State fact and source) ► 4. 3 rd Premise.
Kant and the Role of Reason Two things fill me with constantly increasing admiration and awe, the longer and more earnestly I reflect on them: the starry.
Chapter 7: Ethics Morality and Practical Reason: Kant
Lesson Objective Key Words Lesson outcomes Hypothetical Categorical Imperatives Freedom To evaluate the differences between the Hypothetical and Categorical.
KANTIAN ETHICS Immanuel Kant ( ).
Immanuel Kant and the Enlightenment Immanuel Kant: German ( ) Enlightenment: 1700's (18th Century) Applies the new rational scientific method of.
KANTIANISM AND EUTHANASIA ATTITUDES TO KEY ISSUES.
Lecture 13 Kantian ethics Immanuel Kant ( )
EECS 690 January 27, Deontology Typically, when anyone talks about Deontology, they mean to talk about Immanuel Kant. Kant is THE deontologist.
Duty Ethics.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant
Kant’s theory of imperatives
Kant’s Categorical Imperative
Immanuel Kant.
Kant’s Categorical Imperative
Immanuel Kant’s ethics
Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals
Absolutism.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Immanuel Kant The Categorical Imperative.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 14 Immanuel Kant
Think Pair Share “Evaluating Kant’s Duties and Inclinations by Ranking Actions”
History of Philosophy Lecture 17 Immanuel Kant’ Ethics
Presentation transcript:

The Categorical Imperative Immanuel Kant

Overview Nothing but a morally good will is unconditionally good. Moral goodness depends on principle, not consequences. Supreme moral principle: Categorical Imperative First formulation: Act only according to maxims that you would be willing to make into universal laws. Second formulation: Always treat humanity in yourself or in others as an end and not merely as a means.

A Good Will It is impossible to think of anything at all in the world, or indeed even beyond it, that could be considered good without limitation except a good will. Not to mention that an impartial spectator can take no delight in seeing the uninterrupted prosperity of a being graced with no feature of a pure and good will, so that a good will seems to constitute the indispensable condition even of worthiness to be happy.

Moral Worth Action from duty has its moral worth not in the purpose to be attained by it but in the maxim in accordance with which it is decided upon. [Moral worth] can lie nowhere else than in the principle of the will without regard for the ends that can be brought about by such an action.

Duty Duty is the necessity of an action from respect for law. An action from duty is to put aside entirely the influence of inclination.

Law Nothing other than the representation of the law in itself, which can of course occur only in a rational being. . . can constitute the preeminent good we call moral. Everything in nature works in accordance with laws. Only a rational being has the capacity to act in accordance with the representation of laws, that is, in accordance with principles, or has a will.

Hypothetical vs. Categorical If the action would be good merely as a means to something else the imperative is hypothetical. If the action is represented as in itself good, hence as necessary in a will in itself conforming to reason, as its principle, then it is categorical.

Happiness There is one end that can be presupposed as actual in the case of all rational beings (insofar as imperatives apply to them, namely as dependent beings), and therefore one purpose that they not merely could have but that we can safely presuppose they all actually do have by a natural necessity, and that purpose is happiness.

Happiness The imperative that refers to the choice of means to one’s own happiness, that is, the precept of prudence, is still always hypothetical; the action is not commanded absolutely but only as a means to another purpose.

The Categorical Imperative There is only a single categorical imperative and it is this: Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law.

Duties: Example 1 Someone feels sick of life because of a series of troubles that has grown to the point of despair, but is still so far in possession of his reason that he can ask himself whether it would not be contrary to his duty to himself to take his own life.

Duties: Example 1 Maxim: From self-love I make it my principle to shorten my life when its longer duration threatens more troubles than it promises agreeableness. A nature whose law it would be to destroy life itself by means of the same feeling whose destination is to impel toward the furtherance of life would contradict itself and would therefore not subsist as nature; thus that maxim could not possibly be a law of nature and, accordingly, altogether opposes the supreme principle of all duty.

Duties: Example 2 Another finds himself urged by need to borrow money. He well knows that he will not be able to repay it but sees also that nothing will be lent him unless he promises firmly to repay it within a determinate time.

Duties: Example 2 Maxim: When I believe myself to be in need of money I shall borrow money and promise to repay it, even though I know that this will never happen. The universality of a law that everyone, when he believes himself to be in need, could promise whatever he pleases with the intention of not keeping it would make the promise and the end one might have in it itself impossible, since no one would believe what was promised him but would laugh at all such expressions as vain pretenses.

Duties: Example 3 A third finds in himself a talent that by means of some cultivation could make him a human being useful for all sorts of purposes. However, he finds himself in comfortable circumstances and prefers to give himself up to pleasure than to trouble himself with enlarging and improving his fortunate natural predispositions.

Duties: Example 3 Maxim: Neglect all my natural gifts other than those that would promote my own amusement. A nature could indeed always subsist with such a universal law, although. . . [one] cannot possibly will that this become a universal law. . . for as a rational being he necessarily wills that all the capacities in him be developed, since they serve him and are given to him for all sorts of possible purposes.

Duties: Example 4 A fourth, for whom things are going well, sees that others (whom he could very well help) have to contend with great hardships.

Duties: Example 4 Maxim: What is to me? Let each be as happy as heaven wills or as he can make himself; I shall take nothing from him nor even envy him; only I do not care to contribute anything to his welfare or to his assistance in need! If such a way of thinking were to become a universal law the human race could admittedly very well subsist. It is still impossible to will that such a principle hold everywhere as a law of nature. For, a will that decided this would conflict with itself, since many cases could occur in which one would need the love and sympathy of others and in which, by such a law of nature arisen from his own will, he would rob himself of all hope of the assistance he wishes for himself.

An End in Itself But suppose there was something the existence of which in itself has an absolute worth, something which as an end in itself could be a ground of determinate laws; then in it, and in it alone, would lie the ground of a possible categorical imperative, that is, of a practical law.

An End in Itself The human being and in general every rational being exists as an end in itself, not merely as a means to be used by this or that will at its discretion. Instead he must in all his actions, whether directed to himself or also to other rational beings, always be regarded at the same time as an end.

An End in Itself Beings the existence of which rests not on our will but on nature, if they are beings without reason, still have only a relative worth, as means, and are therefore called things.

An End in Itself Whereas rational beings are called persons because their nature already marks them out as an end in itself, that is, as something that may not be used merely as a means. If all worth were conditional and therefore contingent, then no supreme practical principle for reason could be found anywhere.

Categorical Imperative as Practical Imperative Rational nature exists as an end in itself. The human being necessarily represents his own existence in this way. Every other rational being also represents his existence in this way consequent on just the same rational ground that also holds for me.

Categorical Imperative as Practical Imperative The practical imperative will therefore be: So act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means.

Duties: Example 1 (II) Suicide: A human being is not a thing and hence not something that can be used merely as a means, but must in all his actions be regarded as an end in itself. I cannot, therefore, dispose of a human being in my own person by maiming, damaging, or killing him.

Duties: Example 2 (II) False promise: He whom I want to use for my purposes by such a promise cannot possibly agree to my way of behaving toward him, and so himself contain the end of this action.

Duties: Example 3 (II) Laziness/Pleasure-Seeking: There are in humanity predispositions to greater perfection, which belong to the end of nature with respect to humanity in our subject. To neglect these might admittedly be consistent with the preservation of humanity as an end in itself but not with the furtherance of this end.

Duties: Example 4 (II) Selfish Passivity toward Others: Humanity might indeed subsist if no one contributed to the happiness of others but yet did not intentionally withdraw anything from it. However. . . The ends of a subject who is an end in itself must as far as possible be also my ends, if that representation is to have its full effect in me.