I OUGHT, THEREFORE I CAN Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison Talk at Illinois State University, 2 April 2010.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
With examples from Number Theory
Advertisements

Hypotheticals: The If/Then Form Hypothetical arguments are usually more obvious than categorical ones. A hypothetical argument has an “if/then” pattern.
Freedom and Determinism
Reason & Argument Lecture 3. Lecture Synopsis 1. Recap: validity, soundness & counter- examples, induction. 2. Arguing for a should conclusion. 3. Complications.
CAN I KILL MY YOUNGER SELF? Time Travel and the Retro-Suicide Paradox Peter B. M. Vranas The University of Michigan 15 September 2000.
1 Is Abortion Wrong? I I. 2 Some Background 1 st Mo.2 nd Mo.3 rd Mo.4 th Mo.5 th Mo.6 th Mo.7 th Mo.8 th Mo.9 th Mo. Conception “Zygote” “Embryo” “Fetus”
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 20 Cohen & The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research By David Kelsey.
The Categorical Imperative
“Be kind, because everyone you meet is fighting a hard battle.” – Plato.
Meta-Ethics Slavery is evil Honesty is a virtue Abortion is wrong ‘Meta’ from Greek meaning ‘above’ or ‘after’
Categorical Imperative
Refutation, Part 1: Counterexamples & Reductio Kareem Khalifa Philosophy Department Middlebury College.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 11 Utilitarianism By David Kelsey.
KANT 2 IMPOSSIBLE TO UNIVERSALIZE IMMORAL PRINCIPLES.
Ethical Theory.
Phil 160 Kant.
The soft determinist response. the incompatibility argument 1)Determinism is true. 2)If Determinism is true, then none of our actions are free. 3)None.
Conductive Arguments in Ethical Deliberation Douglas Walton: University of Windsor Assumption Chair in Argumentation Studies Distinguished Research Fellow.
160 Ethics “Death” Thomas Nagel. Death, so what? In continuing the project of replacing moral sentiment with considered moral judgment, it is often necessary.
IN DEFENSE OF IMPERATIVE INFERENCE Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison Warsaw, 18 May 2012.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 6 Ayer and Emotivism By David Kelsey.
Metaethics and ethical language Michael Lacewing Michael Lacewing
Descartes on Certainty (and Doubt)
Substance dualism: do Descartes’ arguments work? Michael Lacewing
Logic and Proof. Argument An argument is a sequence of statements. All statements but the first one are called assumptions or hypothesis. The final statement.
BASIC CONCEPTS OF ARGUMENTS
Prescriptivism Michael Lacewing
The Ontological Proof (II) We have seen that, if someone wishes to challenge the soundness of the Modal Ontological, he denies the truth of the second.
thinking hats Six of Prepared by Eman A. Al Abdullah ©
Descartes I am essentially rational, only accidentally an animal ‘essentially’ = logically necessarily ‘essentially’ = logically necessarily Strictly speaking,
Utilitarian Approach. Utilitarianism The founder of classical utilitarianism is Jeremy Bentham. According to Bentham human beings always try to avoid.
EGOISM AND CRITIQUE 8.5 Forensic Philosophy December 16, 2013.
Section 1.3 The Laboratory of the Mind
FACTS AND VALUES 1. Extrinsic value vs. Intrinsic value  If something has an intrinsic value, it has the value by itself.  It has the value not because.
1 Abortion III Abortion. 2 Marquis’ Project Thesis: In the overwhelming majority of cases, deliberate abortions are seriously immoral. Don Marquis: “Why.
THEORIES OF ETHICS PART 2 OF CHAPTER 12 (ETHICS).
The idea of research is to study what others have published and form your own opinions. When you quote people, or even when you summarize or paraphrase.
Kantian ethics (& suicide): Kantian ethics (& suicide): Immanuel Kant ( ). A German philosopher. Ought implies Can Maxims Categorical Imperative.
1 Sections 1.5 & 3.1 Methods of Proof / Proof Strategy.
Categorical and Practical Imperative
Chapter 3: Knowledge Kant’s Revolution Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 20 Cohen & The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research By David Kelsey.
1 Is Abortion Wrong? III. 2 Brody’s Project Brody argues that, given Thomson’s presumption that the squidge has a full right to life, her argument that.
The Nature of Morality General Overview “We are discussing no small matter, but how we ought to live” (Plato in the Republic ca. 390B.C.)
Logical Reasoning:Proof Prove the theorem using the basic axioms of algebra.
Ethics.
LECTURE 17 THE MODAL ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT (A VARIANT OF HARTSHORNE’S VERSION)
Treasure hunt Part 3 Loving the unlovable. Treasure hunt Part 3 Loving the unlovable.
Anselm’s “1st” ontological argument Something than which nothing greater can be thought of cannot exist only as an idea in the mind because, in addition.
Objections to Kant’s ethics Michael Lacewing
‘Doing the Right Thing’ - Open Lecture Series 2015/16 Lecture 2: Moral Responsibility Dr Dorothea Debus Department of Philosophy University of York.
Certainty and ErrorCertainty and Error One thing Russell seems right about is that we don’t need certainty in order to know something. In fact, even Descartes.
An analysis of Kant’s argument against the Cartesian skeptic in his ‘Refutation of Idealism” Note: Audio links to youtube are found on my blog at matthewnevius.wordpress.com.
Dis- = not, none. What is the prefix that means not ?
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 16 Ethics #2: Utilitarianism By David Kelsey.
Identifying Premises and Conclusions How to diagram a complex argument.
At this time I admit nothing that is not necessarily true. I am therefore precisely nothing but a thinking thing Descartes.
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
Chapter 9: Abortion Pope John Paul II, “The Unspeakable Crime of Abortion” – Main argument: 1. The human fetus from conception is “an innocent human being.”
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
NEW FOUNDATIONS FOR IMPERATIVE LOGIC III: A General Definition of Argument Validity Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison.
Cosmological arguments from contingency
Meta-Ethics Objectives:
Testing for Validity and Invalidity
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 15 Ethics #1: Utilitarianism
Philosophy Sept. 14th Objective Opener
Outline the naturalistic fallacy
A NEW ARGUMENT FOR OUGHT-IMPLIES-CAN
Tooley’s Abortion and Infanticide
Presentation transcript:

I OUGHT, THEREFORE I CAN Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison Talk at Illinois State University, 2 April 2010

OVERVIEW Part 1 FORMULATING OIC Part 2 AN ARGUMENT FOR OIC Part 3 SIX OBJECTIONS TO OIC

FORMULATING OIC Ê 'Ought': objective, pro tanto obligation. Ë 'Can': ability plus opportunity. Ì 'Implies': conceptual entailment. Relate obligations at a time with abilities and opportunities at the same time. OIC: By virtue of conceptual necessity, if an agent at a time has an objective, pro tanto obligation to do something, then the agent at that time has both the ability and the opportunity to do the thing.

PART 2 Part 1 FORMULATING OIC Part 2 AN ARGUMENT FOR OIC Part 3 SIX OBJECTIONS TO OIC

AN ARGUMENT FOR OIC (P1) If an agent has an obligation to , then the agent has a reason to . (P2) If an agent has a reason to , then  -ing is a potential action of the agent. (P3) If  -ing is a potential action of an agent, then the agent can . __________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (OIC) If an agent has an obligation to , then the agent can .

PART 3 Part 1 FORMULATING OIC Part 2 AN ARGUMENT FOR OIC Part 3 SIX OBJECTIONS TO OIC

OBJECTION 1: YOU OUGHT TO FEEL "I know you hate her, but you ought to feel grateful to her: she saved your son's life." Reply: OIC is about obligations to do (to make yourself feel). "You ought to feel grateful" may: Ê Ascribe a feasible obligation: to try to make yourself feel grateful right now, or to gradually replace hatred with gratitude. Ë Ascribe no obligation, but blame you for being ungrateful, or stating it would be good if you felt grateful (ought to be, not to do).

OBJECTION 2: YOU NO LONGER CAN Case 1: A student idles her time away and becomes unable to turn in a paper by 9am. Case 2: A man boards a plane to NY at 8:30am and becomes unable to marry a woman at 9am. Case 3: A debtor is robbed at 8:58am and be- comes unable to repay a loan to a bank by 9am. Position 1 (anti-OIC): At 8:59am the student still has an obligation to turn in a paper by 9am. Position 2 (pro-OIC): At 8:59am the student no longer has an obligation to turn in a paper.

COMMON GROUND: OBLIGATIONS HAVE LIFETIMES l Sooner or later, the obligation expires: At 10am the student no longer has an obligation to turn in a paper by 9am. l So the question is not whether the obligation expires, but rather when it does:  Position 1 (anti-OIC): The obligation expires at 9am, after the inability sets in.  Position 2 (pro-OIC): The obligation expires before 9am, when the inability sets in.

WHY WOULD THE OBLIGATION EXPIRE AT 9AM? l Because 9am is in its content. Reply: It expires at 8am if the student turns in a paper at 8am. l Because at 9am it becomes impossible to fulfill. Reply: Before 9am it becomes practically impossible to fulfill. At 8:59am there are only exotic possibilities in which the obligation is fulfilled. l In sum: We need a demarcation line, and it is more plausible to draw it in terms of practical rather than strict impossibility.

THE RARE BOOK EXAMPLE l You have promised to return to Joe his copy of a rare book by 9am, but you cannot: it is in China. l At 8am you have an obligation to give Joe your copy of the book by 9am. l So if at 8am you also had the obligation to give Joe his copy by 9am, then at 8am you would have both obligations—but you don't. l So at 8am you no longer have the original obligation.

TWO RESPONSES Response 1: Why do you now have an obligation to apologize if you now no longer have an obligation to turn in a paper? My reply: Because you are blameworthy for having violated another obligation earlier on. Response 2: OIC has the consequence that one can get rid of unwanted obligations. My reply: This consequence is true; e.g., killing the teacher. OIC does not allow one to get rid of unwanted obligations without residue.

OBJECTION 3: ADDICTIVE BEHAVIORS The objection: Kleptomaniacs have an oblig- ation to refrain from stealing, but they cannot. My reply: Strictly speaking they can refrain, since they regularly do refrain. A response: One can conceive of a kleptomaniac who cannot refrain from stealing. My reply: Such kleptomaniacs would have no obligation to refrain from stealing. A rejoinder: They would still have a reason to refrain, so they falsify P2. Why?

ABILITY-INDEPENDENT THEORIES OF REASONS (Q1) Everyone has a reason to do whatever would be good for her. (Q2) Someone cannot do something that would be good for her. _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (Q3) Someone cannot do something she has a reason to do. My reply: Q1 is false. You have no reason to dis- prove a theorem even if it would be good for you. A response: Q1 is coherent, so P2 is false. My reply: (  Q1)&Q2 does not entail  Q3. One needs  Q1&Q2, but Q2 is false.

OBJECTION 4: OIC VERSUS IS/OUGHT (I/O*) No valid argument has a moral conclusion and consistent nonmoral premises. l Subject to counterexamples, so modify: (I/O) No valid argument has a singular moral conclusion and consistent nonmoral premises. l If OIC is true and R3 is a moral claim, then I/O is false because this argument is valid: (R1) S has a moral obligation to   S can . (R2) S cannot . _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (R3) S has no moral obligation to .

REPLY TO OBJECTION 4: OILP VERSUS IS/OUGHT (R1) S has a moral obligation to    (S  ’s). (R2) ~  (S  ’s). _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (R3) S has no moral obligation to . So: (1) If I/O contradicts OIC, then I/O contra- dicts OILP (ought-implies-logically-possible). But: (2) If I/O contradicts OILP, then I/O should be rejected. Thus: (3) If I/O contradicts OIC, then I/O should be rejected.

A : AGAINST OILP A RESPONSE: AGAINST OILP (1)   ((S has an atc obligation to  & S has an atc obligation to  )  S has an atc obligation to  &  ) (2)   (S has an atc obligation to  & S has an atc obligation to ~  ). _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (3)   (S has an atc obligation to  &~  ) My reply: (2) is false because an agent cannot have two distinct all-things-considered (as opposed to pro tanto) obligations.

OBJECTION 5: OIC VERSUS DETERMINISM (S1)   (S has an obligation to   S can  ) (S2)   (S can   S  ’s). _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (S3)   (S has an obligation to   S  ’s) l S1 is OIC. S2 is true if hard determinism is possible. Paul Saka (2000) argues that S3 is false because its negation follows from S4: (S4) (Every murderer has an obligation to refrain from murdering but does not refrain) _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (~S3)   (S has an obligation to  & ~(S  ’s))

REPLY TO OBJECTION 5 (S4) (Every murderer has an obligation to refrain from murdering but does not refrain) _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (~S3)   (S has an obligation to  & ~(S  ’s)) Ê The inference from S4 to ~S3 relies on the assumption that necessarily some agent is a murderer. But this assumption is false. Ë S3 is true: It is conceptually possible that only perfect agents exist, who always fulfill their obligations.

OBJECTION 6: OIC VERSUS PAP (T1) (S is morally blameworthy for  -ing   t(at t, S has a moral obligation to ~  )) (T2)   t(at t, S has a moral obligation to ~   at t, S can ~  ) _________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ (T3) (S is morally blameworthy for  -ing   t(at t, S can ~  )) l T2 follows from OIC. T3 is a special case of PAP (the Principle of Alternate Possibilities) and is subject to “Frankfurt-type examples”.

REPLY TO OBJECTION 6: AGAINST T1 l T1 is false because: (T4) An agent who inexcusably violates a subjective moral obligation is morally blameworthy for doing so even if she violates no objective moral obligation. l T4 avoids common counterexamples:  A demon makes you strangle your neighbor’s canary.  A Nazi mercifully spares the life of a Jewish child.

A RESPONSE: FRANKFURT-TYPE EXAMPLES l You kill your aunt to inherit her, but a “coun- terfactual intervener” was monitoring your brain and would have made you decide to kill her if your brain waves had not shown that you were going to decide on your own to kill her. l So you cannot avoid killing her; but you have a moral obligation to avoid killing her, so OIC is false. l This is a direct counterexample to OIC, without relying on T1.

REPLY TO THE RESPONSE l You have no moral obligation to avoid killing your aunt. A factor which deprives you of an ability (e.g., a leg injury) can also deprive you of an obligation (e.g., to rescue someone). l Rejoinder: The leg injury is actual, but the counterfactual intervener does not actually intervene. l My reply: The presence of the intervener actually deprives you of the ability to avoid killing. Cf. sharks in water.