Social Choice Session 3 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Chapter Thirty-One Welfare Social Choice u Different economic states will be preferred by different individuals. u How can individual preferences be.
Advertisements

A Simple Proof "There is no consistent method by which a democratic society can make a choice (when voting) that is always fair when that choice must be.
Arrow’s Conditions and Approval Voting
6.896: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture 18 Constantinos Daskalakis.
Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
1 Public choice Alexander W. Cappelen Econ
1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 3 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 3 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Algorithmic Game Theory Uri Feige Robi Krauthgamer Moni Naor Lecture 9: Social Choice Lecturer: Moni Naor.
NOTE: To change the image on this slide, select the picture and delete it. Then click the Pictures icon in the placeholder to insert your own image. CHOOSING.
Public Finance (MPA405) Dr. Khurrum S. Mughal.
Computational Democracy: Algorithms, Game Theory, and Elections Steven Wolfman 2011/10/27.
How “impossible” is it to design a Voting rule? Angelina Vidali University of Athens.
IMPOSSIBILITY AND MANIPULABILITY Section 9.3 and Chapter 10.
CS 886: Electronic Market Design Social Choice (Preference Aggregation) September 20.
Social Choice Session 6 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
Voting Theory.
Arrow’s impossibility theorem EC-CS reading group Kenneth Arrow Journal of Political Economy, 1950.
Frank Cowell: Welfare Basics WELFARE: BASICS MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Useful, but optional Consumption basics Useful, but optional.
Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Welfare: Basics MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Useful, but optional Consumption basics Useful, but optional.
Motivation: Condorcet Cycles Let people 1, 2 and 3 have to make a decision between options A, B, and C. Suppose they decide that majority voting is a good.
Arrow's Impossibility Theorem Kevin Feasel December 10, 2006
Social Choice Session 2 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
Alex Tabarrok Arrow’s Theorem.
CPS Voting and social choice
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Social Choice Theory By Shiyan Li. History The theory of social choice and voting has had a long history in the social sciences, dating back to early.
On the Aggregation of Preferences in Engineering Design Beth Allen University of Minnesota NSF DMI
1 Manipulation of Voting Schemes: A General Result By Allan Gibbard Presented by Rishi Kant.
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = truthful voting Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University.
Dr. Alexandra I. Cristea CS 319: Theory of Databases: C3.
Social choice (voting) Vincent Conitzer > > > >
Overview Aggregating preferences The Social Welfare function The Pareto Criterion The Compensation Principle.
Decision Theory CHOICE (Social Choice) Professor : Dr. Liang Student : Kenwa Chu.
Chapter 9 Political Economy
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem
Social Choice Session 4 Carmen Pasca and John Hey.
Microeconomics 2 John Hey. Lecture 9 Today I am going to start by reviewing the main points from Chapter/Lecture which I regard as the most important.
Collective Action and Collective Decision Making
Arrow’s theorem and the problem of social choice.
CPS Voting and social choice Vincent Conitzer
1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 1 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Elections and Strategic Voting: Condorcet and Borda E. Maskin Harvard University.
Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Design Basics MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Welfare Basics Almost essential Welfare.
Total Output, x “Stylized” view of production functions – long run and short run Long-run Production with 2 variable inputs (v 1, v 2 ): v1v1 v2v2 v11v11.
1 Elections and Manipulations: Ehud Friedgut, Gil Kalai, and Noam Nisan Hebrew University of Jerusalem and EF: U. of Toronto, GK: Yale University, NN:
1 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 2 EC9A4 Social Choice and Voting Lecture 2 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science.
Part 4: Voting Topics - Continued
Session 3 Review Distributions Pen’s parade, quantile function, cdf Size, spread, poverty Data Income vector, cdf Today Inequality and economics Welfare.
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Lecture 04: Theory of Automata:08 Transition Graphs.
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem. Question: Is there a public decision making process, voting method, or “Social Welfare Function” (SWF) that will tell us.
Decision Theory Lecture 4. Decision Theory – the foundation of modern economics Individual decision making – under Certainty Choice functions Revelead.
AS Ethics Utilitarianism Title: - Preference Utilitarianism To begin… What is meant by preference? L/O: To understand Preference Utilitarianism.
Social Choice Lectures 14 and 15 John Hey. Lectures 14 and 15: Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem and other matters Plan of lecture: Aggregation of individual.
Arrow’s Conditions 1.Non-Dictatorship -- The social welfare function should account for the wishes of multiple voters. It cannot simply mimic the preferences.
Social Choice Lecture 16 John Hey. More Possibility/Impossibility Theorems Sen’s Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal Gibbard’s theory of alienable rights.
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem
Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem: A Presentation By Susan Gates
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Social choice theory = preference aggregation = voting assuming agents tell the truth about their preferences Tuomas Sandholm Professor Computer Science.
Applied Mechanism Design For Social Good
Algorithmic Analysis of Elections: Voting Rules and Manipulability (minicourse) Piotr Faliszewski AGH University Kraków, Poland.
Impossibility and Other Alternative Voting Methods
Introduction If we assume
Alex Tabarrok Arrow’s Theorem.
Voting systems Chi-Kwong Li.
Voting and social choice
CPS Voting and social choice
Arrow’s Conditions and Approval Voting
Presentation transcript:

Social Choice Session 3 Carmen Pasca and John Hey

Plan for this session We start with a review of Arrow’s theorem – using now Jen’s preferences to give completeness and showing that this leads to her being the dictator. Then, within the same framework (ordinal preferences) we explore how we may weaken Arrow’s assumptions and possibly get some possibility. After a short break we will invite comments from you as to other ways to get possibility. (Note: in session 6 we explore the implications of cardinality/measurability of preferences – so we do not do this today.)

Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem In social choice theory, Arrow’s impossibility theorem... states that, when voters have three or more discrete alternatives (options), no voting system can convert the ranked preferences of individuals into a community-wide ranking while also meeting a certain set of criteria. These criteria are called unrestricted domain, non-dictatorship, Pareto efficiency, and independence of irrelevant alternatives. (Wikipedia) We remind you of Arrow’s famous result and explore more its implications. We again draw inspiration from John Bone at York and borrow some of his slides.

Arrow Arrow’s conditions are these: Universal Domain: is applicable to any profile. Consistency: produces a complete, transitive ordering of available alternatives. Pareto: if everyone prefers x to y then so should society. Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives: orders x and y on the basis only of individual preferences on x and y. Can we replace/eliminate/weaken any of these? This is the question we address today.

Back to session 2 briefly We go back to where we had to assume some society’s preferences in order to get completeness......and we take an alternative way. We go to slide number 12 of the PowerPoint presentation of session 2...session 2... after which we once again shamelessly use John Bone’s thoughts and slides.

Universal Domain: is applicable to any profile Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions? Perhaps there are some profiles at which we might not require a social ordering at all? Especially for profiles of (e.g. malicious) preferences. But perhaps also for profiles of welfare rankings. For example if x and y are different allocations of economic goods, and J is allocated more of every good under x than under y, then it might be reasonable to ignore any hypothetical profile in which J ranks y above x. Might this be enough to escape the problem?

Pareto: if everyone prefers x to y then so should society Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions? Perhaps for similar reasons as with Universal Domain A Sen, “The impossibility of a Paretian Liberal”, Journal of Political Economy, vol 78 (1970), A single copy of Lady Chatterley’s Lover a: Ken (Prude) reads itb: Jen (Liberal) reads itc: neither reads it a b cJen c a bKen Pareto →aPbaPb Liberalism → bPcbPc cPacPa Ignore “meddlesome” preferences? (We will return to Sen shortly.)

Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions? Whatever determines the relative merits of x and y should not include individual welfare data regarding z …... but should instead be intrinsic to x and y. So at any two profiles in which the individual welfare data regarding (only) x and y is the same, the social ordering of x and y should also be the same. This becomes problematic when the individual welfare data comprises only rankings that is, comprises only ordinal welfare data

Consistency: complete transitive ordering Can we plausibly relax Arrow’s conditions? So why require a complete, transitive social ordering of all available alternatives ? We may only have to decide which of the available alternatives should be (socially) chosen. This is equivalent to requiring the social choice to be consistent across different (hypothetical) sets of alternatives Whatever determines the relative merits of x and y should not include the availability or otherwise of z …... but should instead be intrinsic to x and y.

A single copy of Lady Chatterley’s Lover a: Ken reads itb: Jen reads itc: neither reads it a b cJen c a bKen choose:a from {a,b} b from {b,c} c from {a,c} ? from {a,b,c} Whatever is the choice from {a,b,c}, there is inconsistency. But so what?

a b cJen c a bKen choose:a from {a,b} b from {b,c} c from {a,c} ? from {a,b,c} Whatever is the choice from {a,b,c}, there is inconsistency. But so what? b c aLen Choose x from {x,y} iff more people prefer x to y than prefer y to x. Majoritarianism

Sen’s Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal The idea is that each individual has the right to determine things ‘locally’ – that is, those things that concern only him or her. So individuals are decisive over local issues. For example, I should be free to choose whether or not I read Lady Chatterley’s Lover. He gives a nice example, which we have already seen. Three alternatives, a, b and c, and two people A and B. a: Mr A (the prude) reads the book; b: Mr B (the lascivious/liberal) reads the book; c: Neither reads the book.

Lady C. Mr A (the Prude): c > a > b Mr B (the Lascivious): a > b > c Now assume that Mr A is decisive over (a,c) and that Mr B is decisive over (b,c). So from A’s preferences c > a and from B’s preferences b > c. From unanimity a > b. Hence we have b > c (B) and c > a (A) and a > b (unanimity)! WEIRD! (Intransitive).

Sen’s Theorem Condition U (Unrestricted domain): The domain of the collective choice rule includes all possible individual orderings. Condition P( Weak Pareto): For any x, y in X, if every member of society strictly prefers x to y, then xPy. Condition L* (Liberalism): For each individual i, there is at least one pair of personal alternatives (x,y) in X such that individual i is decisive both ways in the social choice process. Theorem: There is no social decision function that satisfies conditions U, P and L*.

Proof P indicates Society’s preference and P i that of individual i. Suppose i is decisive over (x,y) and that j is decisive over (z,w). Assume that these two pairs have no element in common. Let us suppose that xP i y, zP j w, and, for both k=i,j that wP k x and yP k z. From Condition L* we obtain xPy and zPw. From Condition P we obtain wPx and yPz. Hence it follows that xPy yPz zPw and wPx. Cyclical.

Gibbard’s Theory of Alienable Rights Background... Going back to the Lady C example, Mr A may realise that maintaining his right to decisiveness over (a,c) leads to an impasse/intransitivity. He cannot get c (his preferred option) because Mr B has rights over that and renouncing his right to decisiveness over (a,c), society will end up with a (which is preferred by Mr A to b – his least preferred). (Might Mr B think similarly (mutatis mutandis) and give up his right to decisiveness?)

Gibbard’s own example Three persons: Angelina, Edwin and the ‘judge’. Angelina prefers marrying Edwin but would marry the judge. Edwin prefers to remain single, but would prefer to marry Angelina rather than see her marry the judge. Judge is happy with whatever Angelina wants. Three alternatives: x: Edwin and Angelina get married y: Angelina and the judge marry (Edwin stays single) z: All three remain single Angelina has preference: x P A y P A z Edwin has preference: z P E x P E y

The problem and its solution Angelina has a libertarian claim over the pair (y,z). Edwin has a claim over (z,x). Edwin and Angelina are unanimous in preferring x to y. So we have a preference cycle: yPz, zPx, xPy. If Edwin exercises his right to remain single, then Angelina might end up married to the judge, which is Edwin’s least preferred option. ‘Therefore’ it will be in Edwin’s own advantage to waive his right over (z,x) in favour of the Pareto preference xPy.

Gibbard’s Theory of Alienable Rights Condition GL: Individuals have the right to waive their rights. Gibbard’s rights-waiving solution: There exists a collective choice rule that satisfies conditions U, P and GL. The central role of the waiver is to break a cycle whenever there is one but the informational demands are high.

Now a short break After the break we invite you to suggest other ways of breaking Arrow’s impossibility......within the ordinal preferences framework. Note that we could dispense with the notion of trying to find society’s preferences we could immediately think about a decision rule of society which depends upon individual preferences Like doing something if a majority of the population want to do it. Problems with this? Intransitivity?

Conclusions So what do we conclude from all of this? Essentially that, whatever way we do the aggregation, there is no method, that does not have objections, to aggregate individual preferences into a set of social preferences. Is this surprising? What are its implications? That we cannot leave a computer in charge of society. We need decision-making bodies with flexibility and some autonomy but also somehow under the control of the members of society.