Homosexuality. the question Yesterday we discussed whether homosexual marriage is acceptable.  We were not focusing exclusively on moral acceptability,

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
FATE v. FREE WILL. Fatalism The idea of fatalism coincides with destiny. This means that everything in our lives is predestined by fate. In other words,
Advertisements

Believing Where We Cannot Prove Philip Kitcher
General Argument from Evil Against the Existence of God The argument that an all-powerful, all- knowing, and perfectly good God would not allow any—or.
The Subject-Matter of Ethics
The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
The Same Sex Marriage Debate
Hypotheticals: The If/Then Form Hypothetical arguments are usually more obvious than categorical ones. A hypothetical argument has an “if/then” pattern.
Is Same-Sex Marriage Wrong?
Hume’s Problem of Induction 2 Seminar 2: Philosophy of the Sciences Wednesday, 14 September
1 Is Abortion Wrong? I I. 2 Some Background 1 st Mo.2 nd Mo.3 rd Mo.4 th Mo.5 th Mo.6 th Mo.7 th Mo.8 th Mo.9 th Mo. Conception “Zygote” “Embryo” “Fetus”
When is an argument a good one? A cogent argument is an argument in which the premises are rationally acceptable and provide rational support for the conclusion.
Application of Ethical Reasoning
Same-sex Marriage. pop quiz 1. Does Wedgewood argue for or against the acceptability of same-sex marriage? 2. Summarize Wedgewood’s argument. 3. Does.
 Assertions: unsupported declaration of a belief  Prejudice: a view without evidence for or against  Premises: explicit evidence that lead to a conclusion.
NOTE: CORRECTION TO SYLLABUS FOR ‘HUME ON CAUSATION’ WEEK 6 Mon May 2: Hume on inductive reasoning --Hume, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, section.
BIRDS FLY. is a bird Birds fly Tweety is a bird Tweety flies DEFEASIBLE NON-MONOTONIC PRESUMPTIVE?
Phil 148 Fallacies of Relevance and Vacuity. Fallacies of Relevance When we give reasons to believe a claim, it is understood (or conversationally implied)
Phil 160 Kant.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 8 Moore’s Non-naturalism
Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Computer Ethics PHILOSOPHICAL BELIEF SYSTEMS Chapter 1 Hassan Ismail.
Moral Relativism, Cultural Differences and Bioethics Prof. Eric Barnes.
AND THE SLIPPERY SLOPE same-sex marriage. The Slippery Slope Argument If marriage is redefined to include two men in love, on what possible principled.
Philosophy 220 Corvino on the ‘Naturalness’ of Homosexuality.
Chapter 6 Lecture Notes Working on Relevance. Chapter 6 Understanding Relevance: The second condition for cogency for an argument is the (R) condition.
Lincoln-Douglas Debate An Examination of Values. OBJECTIVES: The student will 1. Demonstrate understanding of the concepts that underlie Lincoln-Douglas.
The Perfect God Anselm’s clever trick.
Marriage. in-class activity What is marriage? x is married to y iff … ? … Provide justification for each of the conditions that you take to be necessary.
Promiscuity. Promiscuity must be distinguished from polyamory. Polyamory is having multiple romantic love relationships (possibly involving sexual activity)
Adultery. the nature of adultery An activity A by x is adultery iff (i) A-ing involves x engaging in sexual activity with y, (ii) x is not married to.
Consensual Sex. sexual morality The main question about sexual morality is:  Under what conditions is it morally acceptable/ unacceptable to engage in.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 7 The argument from evil By David Kelsey.
Divine Omnipotence.  Why would people be concerned to specify the nature of the divine?  What are they relating it to?  What does it have to do with.
Capstone Seminar Mr. Dana Linton. Logical fallacies are common errors of reasoning. If an argument commits a logical fallacy, then the reasons that it.
Is Same-Sex Marriage Wrong?
 In this argument the one arguing states that something is true or better because it is old and/or traditional.  In other words, how true a statement.
 Read the following argument. Examine it closely. Do you think it is logically sound? Why?  [T]he acceptance of abortion does not end with the killing.
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 19 Regan & The Case for Animal Rights By David Kelsey.
Natural Law AS Revision
Natural Law Theory and Homosexuality. NLT and Homosexuality  As Catholic social teaching exemplifies, homosexuality is frequently condemned by adherents.
Logical Fallacies A Brief Review. Argumentum ad hominem This is the error of attacking the character or motives of a person who has stated an idea, rather.
“There's intelligent life on other planets.” Would you accept this claim? Accept the claim as TRUE Reject the claim as FALSE SUSPEND JUDGMENT.
Debate: Reasoning. Claims & Evidence Review Claims are statements that serve to support your conclusion. Evidence is information discovered through.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
“Does God Exist?” Think with me for a moment: What is the most important question of anyone’s life? “From where did I come?” “Where am I going?” “Who am.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
1 Is Abortion Wrong? III. 2 Brody’s Project Brody argues that, given Thomson’s presumption that the squidge has a full right to life, her argument that.
The Problem of Evil: McCabe, “The Statement of the Problem”
Welcome to Ethics Ethics and citizens rights DR. BURTON A. AGGABAO Professorial lecturer
Logical Fallacies1 This line of "reasoning" is fallacious because pity does not serve as evidence for a claim Just to get a scholarship does not justify.
1 Problem/Solution Proposals English 2010 Intermediate Writing.
CLARKE & ROWE (pp ) IS A NECESSARY BEING REALLY NECESSARY?
Arguments for God’s existence.  What are we arguing for?
PHIL/RS 335 God’s Existence Pt. 1: The Ontological Argument.
Logic Fallacies Debate Class Production Spain Park High School
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Logical Fallacies Guided Notes
Errors in Reasoning. Fallacies A Fallacy is “any error in reasoning that makes an argument fail to establish its conclusion.” There are two kinds of fallacies.
Invitation to Critical Thinking Chapter 10
Logical Fallacies A logical fallacy is an element of an argument that is flawed If spotted one can essentially render an entire line of reasoning invalid.
Chapter 3: Sexual Morality and Marriage
KANTIANISM AND EUTHANASIA ATTITUDES TO KEY ISSUES.
Ad Hominem (Personal Attack) An attempt to discredit the argument by discrediting the character of the person advancing it.
Logical Fallacies Overview Logical fallacies are instances of “broken reasoning.” Fallacies avoid the actual argument. We want to avoid fallacies, be.
The Cosmological Argument for God’s Existence
Chapter 3: Sexual Morality and Marriage
Errors in Reasoning.
More on Argument.
Errors in Reasoning.
How to Think Logically.
Avoiding Ungrounded Assumptions
Presentation transcript:

Homosexuality

the question Yesterday we discussed whether homosexual marriage is acceptable.  We were not focusing exclusively on moral acceptability, but on acceptability more generally (social, legal, political, etc). Today we will be discussing moral acceptability specifically: not of homosexual marriage, but rather of homosexual relationships, whether married or not.  For this discussion, the legal, social, or political acceptability or unacceptability of homosexual relationships is entirely irrelevant. Homosexual relationships must be distinguished from homosexual acts:  Homosexual acts often occur between two people in a homosexual relationship, but the relationship is more than just the acts. Our question is: are homosexual relationships morally acceptable?

the PIB challenge One of the most popular arguments against the moral acceptability of homosexual relationships is what is often referred to as the PIB argument: P1) If homosexual relationships are morally acceptable, then polygamous, incestuous, and bestial relationships (PIB) are morally acceptable as well. P2) Polygamous, incestuous, and bestial relationships (PIB) are not morally acceptable. C) Therefore, homosexual relationships are not morally acceptable. The idea behind the argument is simple:  Homosexual relationships and PIB all share a common moral status.

the PIB challenge in full a) Homosexual, polygamous, incestual, and bestial relationships all possess some feature(s) F which adult heterosexual relationships do not possess. b) If homosexual relationships are acceptable, then all other relationships with feature F are also acceptable. C1/P1) Therefore, if homosexual relationships are acceptable, then polygamous, incestual, and bestial relationships (PIB) are also acceptable. P2) Polygamous, incestual, and bestial relationships are not acceptable. C2) Therefore, homosexual relationships are not acceptable. The connection between homosexual relationships and PIB is supposed to be logical: that is, there is no principled reason to accept homosexual relationships, yet forbid PIB. Since the argument is valid, the only way to refute it is to show that P1 and/or P2 is false.

in-class activity 1. What is (are) the most plausible candidate(s) for the feature(s) that homosexual relationships and PIB share in common – but is (are) lacking in all adult heterosexual relationships? 2. Explain why you think that this (these) feature(s) are possessed by homosexual relationships and PIB but not adult heterosexual relationships. 3. Explain why you think that this (these) feature(s) might be relevant to the moral status of these relationships.

response 1 1. Slippery Slope Response It is common to reject the PIB argument as an example of the slippery slope fallacy. But that is too quick, since P1 does not claim any sort of unsupported causal relation exists between the antecedent and the consequent.  Rather the relation is supposed to be logical: there is no principled reason to accept homosexual relationships, yet forbid PIB.

response 2 2. Gays Really Exist Response Another response is that homosexuality is a constitutive feature of human identity in a way that PIB are not. There are three ways to understand this claim: a. Homosexuality is immutable. Note that in order to show that P1 is false, it is not enough to show that homosexuality has a feature that PIB lacks (or vice versa).  One must also show that the feature is relevant to the moral status of homosexuality. Given this, it is not enough to say that homosexuality is immutable, whereas PIB are not.  Unless it can be shown that immutability is relevant to the moral status of homosexuality, this difference (if it exists) does not challenge P1.

response 2, cont. b. Homosexuality is important to the homosexual person’s self- concept. The same point applies here:  it is not enough to say that homosexuality is important to the homosexual person’s self-concept, whereas PIB are not;  unless it can be shown that important to the homosexual person’s self-concept is relevant to the moral status of homosexuality, this difference (if it exists) does not challenge P1. In addition, it is false that PIB are never important to the PIB persons’ self- concepts. c. Homosexuality is intimately tied up with the homosexual person’s capacity to love. The prohibition of PIB doesn’t deny love to anyone that the prohibition of homosexual relationships for most homosexuals. This is basically the “equal-options” response…

response 3 3. Equal Options Response Homosexuality differs from PIB in that compared to heterosexuals, homosexuals are asking for “equal options” (namely, a relationship with someone that they love), whereas PIB people would be asking for “extra options” (additional spouses, etc).  In all fairness, it seems that homosexuals should be granted equal options. The problem is that the PIB challenger is quite comfortable denying equal options to those people whose behavior they judge to be morally unacceptable. Again, it is not enough to say that homosexuality is intimately tied up with the homosexual person’s capacity to love, whereas PIB are not;  unless it can be shown that this is relevant to the moral status of homosexuality, this difference (if it exists) does not challenge P1.

response 4 4. Shifting the Burden Response Why should we suppose that homosexual relationships and PIB all share a common moral status?  PIB relationships can be either homosexual or heterosexual. Given this, it is not at all obvious that homosexuality has anything to do with PIB. Instead of arguing that P1 is false, this response simply observes that P1 must be justified before it should be accepted. Since the burden of proof is on whoever wants to establish a claim, the burden is on the PIB challenger.  After all, it is his argument that is trying to establish that homosexual relationships are morally unacceptable. Of course, the PIB challenger could argue that the link between homosexual relationships and PIB is one that has a long history, and thus it is the default position:  we need not be argued into it – rather, we must be argued out of it.

response 4, cont. Corvino attempts to undermine the claim that this is the default position by giving an independent argument that homosexual relationships are morally acceptable: H1) If some heterosexual relationships between sterile partners are morally acceptable (because they realize some moral goods G), then some homosexual relationships are also morally acceptable (because they also realize G). H2) Some heterosexual relationships between sterile partners are morally acceptable. HC) Therefore, some homosexual relationships are also morally acceptable. The moral goods realized by both sorts of relationships could be:  pleasure, communication, emotional growth, personal stability, long-term fulfillment, love, trust, friendship, sexual intimacy, and so on (see p.512). Traditionalists (like Finnis) will deny H1. (We will consider the traditionalist view momentarily.)

response 5 5. Quantifier Ambiguity Response There are four ways to interpret P1: P1a) If all homosexual relationships are morally acceptable, then all PIB are morally acceptable as well. P1b) If all homosexual relationships are morally acceptable, then some PIB are morally acceptable as well. P1c) If some homosexual relationships are morally acceptable, then all PIB are morally acceptable as well. P1d) If some homosexual relationships are morally acceptable, then some PIB are morally acceptable as well. Only P1d is relevant here.

response 5, cont. The result is that the PIB challenge loses much of its rhetorical force. For suppose that we were to grant P1d—is it really so horrible to imagine that some PIB relationships are morally acceptable? After all, imagine that someone presented you with the following premise: P1e) If some heterosexual relationships between sterile partners are morally acceptable, then some polygamous, incestuous, and bestial relationships (PIB) are morally acceptable as well. It seems reasonable to assume that our confidence in the moral acceptability of heterosexual relationships between sterile partners would not be shaken. Nor would we want to deny the moral acceptability of heterosexual relationships between sterile partners just in order to deny the moral acceptability of PIB relationships.

Traditionalism Recall that traditionalists (for example, see Finnis) deny H1: H1) If some heterosexual relationships between sterile partners are morally acceptable (because they realize some moral goods G), then some homosexual relationships are also morally acceptable (because they also realize G). They do so because they hold that there is a moral good realized in heterosexual relationships (even non-procreative ones) that cannot be realized in homosexual relationships.  This good is the marital good. Since even non-procreative heterosexual relationships can realize the marital good, they are morally acceptable. Since homosexual relationships cannot realize the marital good, they are not morally acceptable. So, there is a difference between non-procreative heterosexual relationships and homosexual relationships that is relevant to their moral status.

The Traditionalist Argument The Traditionalist thus offers the following argument against the moral acceptability of homosexuality: T1) A romantic relationship is morally acceptable only if it is capable of realizing the marital good, which requires (i) engaging in sexual activities of the procreative-type and (ii) achieving friendship. T2) Homosexual relationships do not involve sexual activities of the procreative-type. TC1) Therefore, homosexual relationships are not capable of realizing the marital good. TC2) Therefore, homosexual relationships are not morally acceptable.

Finnis: “The plain fact is that those who propound a homosexual ideology have no principled moral case to offer against (prudent and moderate) promiscuity, indeed the getting of orgasmic sexual pleasure in whatever friendly touch or welcoming orifice (human or otherwise) one may opportunely find it.” Corvino objects that T1 of the above argument is false:  He claims that it rests on a “bad phenomenology of sexual desire.” In short, the objection is that there are many goods that can be realized in romantic relationships, and the fact that a given romantic relationship cannot realize one of these goods does not by itself make that relationship morally unacceptable.  After all, the relationship may realize many other goods, goods which independently make it morally acceptable.

all or nothing Traditionalists typically hold that an incapacity to realize the marital good makes a relationship morally unacceptable because they believe that: D) A relationship is either capable of realizing the marital good or it is merely self-gratifying. Plausibly, relationships that are merely self-gratifying are morally unacceptable whereas relationships capable of realizing the marital good are morally acceptable. So, if only these two options exist, we are forced to conclude that the only relationships that are morally acceptable are the ones that are capable of realizing the marital good – just as T1 asserts.

neither all nor nothing D is a false dilemma: a relationship may have many characteristics other than those listed in D. For instance, a relationship may be incapable of realizing the marital good and fail to be merely self-gratifying.  Instead, it might allow two people to achieve intimacy or love, etc. The Traditionalist must argue that allowing two people to achieve intimacy or love, etc. cannot make a relationship morally acceptable. Until this argument has been successfully made, we have no reason to accept T1 – and thus no reason to accept the conclusion of the Traditionalist argument. In such a case, we have no reason to reject H1 – and thus no reason to reject response 4, and thus no reason to accept the PIB challenge.

polygamy, incest, and bestiality Some remaining questions: Are PIB always wrong, or are some PIB morally acceptable? Can the Traditionalist give an argument against the moral acceptability of PIB (especially adult consensual incest) that is not available to the defender of the moral acceptability of homosexual relationships?