Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2008 Lecture 4 – Sept 11 2008.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
An Efficient Dynamic Auction for Heterogeneous Commodities (Lawrence M.Ausubel - september 2000) Authors: Oren Rigbi Damian Goren.
Advertisements

(Single-item) auctions Vincent Conitzer v() = $5 v() = $3.
Chapter 20 Violating Equivalence 1.Preferences for Risk 2.Asymmetric Valuations 3.Relaxing Independence 4.Differential Information 5.Collusion and Entry.
6.896: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture 20 Yang Cai.
Auction Theory Class 5 – single-parameter implementation and risk aversion 1.
Approximating optimal combinatorial auctions for complements using restricted welfare maximization Pingzhong Tang and Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 4 1.
CPS Bayesian games and their use in auctions Vincent Conitzer
Seminar in Auctions and Mechanism Design Based on J. Hartline’s book: Approximation in Economic Design Presented by: Miki Dimenshtein & Noga Levy.
Auctions. Strategic Situation You are bidding for an object in an auction. The object has a value to you of $20. How much should you bid? Depends on auction.
Chapter 25: Auctions and Auction Markets 1 Auctions and Auction Markets.
An Approximate Truthful Mechanism for Combinatorial Auctions An Internet Mathematics paper by Aaron Archer, Christos Papadimitriou, Kunal Talwar and Éva.
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2007 Lecture 2 – Sept
Multi-item auctions with identical items limited supply: M items (M smaller than number of bidders, n). Three possible bidder types: –Unit-demand bidders.
Auction. Types of Auction  Open outcry English (ascending) auction Dutch (descending) auction  Sealed bid First-price Second-price (Vickrey)  Equivalence.
Private-value auctions: theory and experimental evidence (Part I) Nikos Nikiforakis The University of Melbourne.
Auction Theory Class 3 – optimal auctions 1. Optimal auctions Usually the term optimal auctions stands for revenue maximization. What is maximal revenue?
Optimal auction design Roger Myerson Mathematics of Operations research 1981.
Upper hemi-continuity Best-response correspondences have to be upper hemi-continuous for Kakutani’s fixed-point theorem to work Upper hemi-continuity.
Game Theory 1. Game Theory and Mechanism Design Game theory to analyze strategic behavior: Given a strategic environment (a “game”), and an assumption.
Introduction to Game Theory
Theoretical Probability Distributions We have talked about the idea of frequency distributions as a way to see what is happening with our data. We have.
6.853: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Fall 2011 Matt Weinberg Lecture 24.
An Introduction to Game Theory Part I: Strategic Games
Bundling Equilibrium in Combinatorial Auctions Written by: Presented by: Ron Holzman Rica Gonen Noa Kfir-Dahav Dov Monderer Moshe Tennenholtz.
Yang Cai Sep 17, An overview of today’s class Expected Revenue = Expected Virtual Welfare 2 Uniform [0,1] Bidders Example Optimal Auction.
Todd and Steven Divide the Estate Problem Bargaining over 100 pounds of gold Round 1: Todd makes offer of Division. Steven accepts or rejects. Round.
Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion
An Introduction to Game Theory Part IV: Games with Imperfect Information Bernhard Nebel.
Lecture 1 - Introduction 1.  Introduction to Game Theory  Basic Game Theory Examples  Strategic Games  More Game Theory Examples  Equilibrium  Mixed.
Week 10 1 COS 444 Internet Auctions: Theory and Practice Spring 2008 Ken Steiglitz
Frugal Path Mechanisms by Aaron Archer and Eva Tardos Presented by Ron Lavi at the seminar: “Topics on the border of CS, Game theory, and Economics” CS.
Week 41 COS 444 Internet Auctions: Theory and Practice Spring 2010 Ken Steiglitz
Week 61 COS 444 Internet Auctions: Theory and Practice Spring 2009 Ken Steiglitz
Yang Cai Sep 15, An overview of today’s class Myerson’s Lemma (cont’d) Application of Myerson’s Lemma Revelation Principle Intro to Revenue Maximization.
Week 81 COS 444 Internet Auctions: Theory and Practice Spring 2009 Ken Steiglitz
Collusion and the use of false names Vincent Conitzer
Chapter 19 Equivalence Types of Auctions Strategic Equivalence
© 2009 Institute of Information Management National Chiao Tung University Lecture Note II-3 Static Games of Incomplete Information Static Bayesian Game.
Auction Seminar Optimal Mechanism Presentation by: Alon Resler Supervised by: Amos Fiat.
Nash equilibrium Nash equilibrium is defined in terms of strategies, not payoffs Every player is best responding simultaneously (everyone optimizes) This.
More on Social choice and implementations 1 TexPoint fonts used in EMF. Read the TexPoint manual before you delete this box.: AAA A Using slides by Uri.
Auction Theory תכנון מכרזים ומכירות פומביות Topic 7 – VCG mechanisms 1.
Yang Cai Oct 08, An overview of today’s class Basic LP Formulation for Multiple Bidders Succinct LP: Reduced Form of an Auction The Structure of.
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 4.
Topic 2: Designing the “optimal auction” Reminder of previous classes: Discussed 1st price and 2nd price auctions. Found equilibrium strategies. Saw that.
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2007 Lecture 3 – Sept
Yang Cai Oct 06, An overview of today’s class Unit-Demand Pricing (cont’d) Multi-bidder Multi-item Setting Basic LP formulation.
Static Games of Incomplete Information
Expectation. Let X denote a discrete random variable with probability function p(x) (probability density function f(x) if X is continuous) then the expected.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2007 Lecture 4 – Sept
6.853: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Fall 2011 Constantinos Daskalakis Lecture 22.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Algorithmic Mechanism Design Shuchi Chawla 11/7/2001.
Auctions serve the dual purpose of eliciting preferences and allocating resources between competing uses. A less fundamental but more practical reason.
Copyright © 2010 Pearson Education, Inc. Chapter 16 Random Variables.
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 1 A Quick Review of Game Theory and, in particular, Bayesian Games.
Incomplete Information and Bayes-Nash Equilibrium.
Advanced Subjects in GT Prepared by Rina Talisman Introduction Revenue Equivalence The Optimal Auction (Myerson 1981) Auctions.
 This will explain how consumers allocate their income over many goods.  This looks at individual’s decision making when faced with limited income and.
Oil Lease Auctions and the Winners’ Curse. Geologists’ estimates of value differ widely Company that makes highest estimate bids the highest. Often loses.
The Duality Theorem Primal P: Maximize
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1
What properties would we expect preferences to exhibit?
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1
Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1
Information, Incentives, and Mechanism Design
Presentation transcript:

Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory 1 Dan Quint Fall 2008 Lecture 4 – Sept

1 Today: Necessary and Sufficient Conditions For Equilibrium  Today: necessary and sufficient conditions for a particular bidding function to be a symmetric equilibrium

2 Tuesday’s big result was the Envelope Theorem  Theorem. Suppose that  For all t, x*(t) is nonempty  For all (x,t), g t (x,t) exists  For all x, g(x,-) is absolutely continuous  g t has an integrable bound: sup x  X | g t (x,t) |  B(t) for almost all t, with B(t) some integrable function Then for any selection x(s) from x*(s), V(t) = V(0) +  0 t g t (x(s),s) ds  Then we applied this to auctions with symmetric independent private values

3 Another fairly general necessary condition: monotonicity  In symmetric IPV auctions, equilibrium bid strategies will generally be increasing in values; how to prove?  Equilibrium strategies are solutions to the maximization problem max x g(x,t)  What conditions on g makes every selection x(t) from x*(t) nondecreasing?  Recall supermodularity and Topkis  If g(x,t) has increasing differences in (x,t), then the set x*(t) is increasing in t (in the strong set order)  For g differentiable, this is when   g /  x  t  0  But let t’ > t; if x* is not single-valued, this still allows some points in x*(t) to be above some points in x*(t’), so it wouldn’t rule out equilibrium strategies which are decreasing at some points

4 Single crossing and single crossing differences properties (Milgrom/Shannon)  A function h : T  R satisfies the strict single crossing property if for every t’ > t, h(t)  0  h(t’) > 0 (Also known as, “h crosses 0 only once, from below”)  A function g : X x T  R satisfies the strict single crossing differences property if for every x’ > x, the function h(t) = g(x’,t) – g(x,t) satisfies strict single crossing  That is, g satisfies strict single crossing differences if g(x’,t) – g(x,t)  0  g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’) > 0 for every x’ > x, t’ > t  (When g t exists everywhere, a sufficient (but not necessary) condition is for g t to be strictly increasing in x)

5 What single-crossing differences gives us  Theorem. * Suppose g(x,t) satisfies strict single crossing differences. Let S  X be any subset. Let x*(t) = arg max x  S g(x,t), and let x(t) be any (pointwise) selection from x*(t). Then x(t) is nondecreasing in t.  Proof. Let t’ > t, x’ = x(t’) and x = x(t).  By optimality, g(x,t)  g(x’,t) and g(x’,t’)  g(x,t’)  So g(x,t) – g(x’,t)  0 and  g(x,t’) – g(x’,t’)  0  If x > x’, this violates strict single crossing differences * Milgrom (PATW) theorem 4.1, or a special case of theorem 4’ in Milgrom/Shannon 1994

6 So now, given a symmetric equilibrium with the bid function b…  Define g(x,t) as the expected payoff, given bid x and value t, when everyone else uses the equilibrium bid function  If g satisfies strict single crossing differences, then b must be (weakly) increasing  And (from Tuesday), if g is absolutely continuous and differentiable in t with an integrable bound, then V(t) = V(0) +  0 t g t (b(s),s) ds

7 All these conditions are almost always satisfied by symmetric IPV auctions  Suppose b : T  R + is a symmetric equilibrium of some auction game in our general setup  Assume that the other N-1 bidders bid according to b; g(x,t) = t Pr(win | bid x) – E(pay | bid x) = t W(x) – P(x)  So g(x,t) is absolutely continuous and differentiable in t, with derivative bounded by 1  What about strict single crossing differences?  For x’ > x, g(x’,t) – g(x,t) = [ W(x’) – W(x) ] t – [ P(x’) – P(x) ]  When does this satisfy strict single-crossing?

8 When is strict single crossing satisfied by g(x’,t) – g(x,t) = [ W(x’) – W(x) ] t – [ P(x’) – P(x) ] ?  Assume W(x’)  W(x) (probability of winning nondecreasing in bid)  g(x’,t) – g(x,t) is weakly increasing in t, so if it’s strictly positive at t, it’s strictly positive at t’ > t  Need to check that if g(x’,t) – g(x,t) = 0, then g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’) > 0  This can only fail if W(x’) = W(x)  If b has convex range, W(x’) > W(x), so strict single crossing differences holds and b must be nondecreasing (e.g.: T convex, b continuous)  If W(x’) = W(x) and P(x’)  P(x) (e.g., first-price auction, since P(x) = x), then g(x’,t) – g(x,t)  0, so there’s nothing to check  But, if W(x’) = W(x) and P(x’) = P(x), then bidding x’ and x give the same expected payoff, so b(t) = x’ and b(t’) = x could happen in equilibrium  Example. A second-price auction, with values uniformly distributed over [0,1]  [2,3]. The bid function b(2) = 1, b(1) = 2, b(v i ) = v i otherwise is a symmetric equilibrium.  But other than in a few weird situations, g will satisfy strict single crossing differences, so we know b will be nondecreasing

9 In fact, b will almost always be strictly increasing  Suppose b(-) were constant over some range of types [t’,t’’]  Then there is positive probability (N – 1) [ F(t’’) – F(t’) ] F N – 2 (t’) of tying with one other bidder by bidding b* (plus the additional possibility of tying with multiple bidders)  Suppose you only pay if you win; let B be the expected payment, conditional on bidding b* and winning  Since t’’ > t’, either t’’ > B or B > t’, so either you strictly prefer to win at t’’ or you strictly prefer to lose at t’  Assume that when you tie, you win with probability greater than 0 but less than 1  Then you can strictly gain in expectation either by reducing b(t’) by a sufficiently small amount, or by raising b(t’’) by a sufficiently small amount

10 b will almost always be strictly increasing  In first-price auctions, equilibrium bid distributions don’t have point masses even when type distributions do  When there is a positive probability of each bidder having a particular value, they play a mixed strategy at that value  Otherwise, there’d be a positive probability of ties, and the same logic would hold – either prefer to increase by epsilon to win those ties, or decrease by epsilon if you’re indifferent about winning them  In second-price auctions, if the type distribution has a point mass, bidders still bid their valuations  Still a dominant strategy  So in that case, there are positive-probability ties

11 So to sum up, in “well-behaved” symmetric IPV auctions, except in very weird situations,  any symmetric equilibrium bid function will be strictly increasing,  and the envelope formula will hold  Next: when are these sufficient conditions for a bid function b to be a symmetric equilibrium?

12 Sufficient Conditions

13 What are generally sufficient conditions for optimality in this type of problem?  A function g(x,t) satisfies the smooth single crossing differences condition if for any x’ > x and t’ > t,  g(x’,t) – g(x,t) > 0  g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’) > 0  g(x’,t) – g(x,t)  0  g(x’,t’) – g(x,t’)  0  g x (x,t) = 0  g x (x,t+  )  0  g x (x,t –  ) for all  > 0  Theorem. (PATW th 4.2) Suppose g(x,t) is continuously differentiable and has the smooth single crossing differences property. Let x : [0,1]  R have range X’, and suppose x is the sum of a jump function and an absolutely continuous function. If  x is nondecreasing, and  the envelope formula holds: for every t, g(x(t),t) – g(x(0),0) =  0 t g t (x(s),s) ds then x(t)  arg max x  X’ g(x,t)  (Note that x only guaranteed optimal over X’, not over all X)

14 Why do we need smooth single crossing differences, not just strict s.c.d.?  Consider g(x,t) = (x – t) 3, x(t) = x, X = [0,1]  Clearly, x(t) is nondecreasing  And it satisfies the envelope theorem: since g t (x(t),t) = – (x(t) – t) 2 = 0 and g(x(t),t) = 0  But g(x,t) is maximized at x = 1, so x(t) = t is not a solution

15 Let’s prove the sufficiency theorem  Lots of extra terms due to the possibility of discontinuities – we’ll just do the case where x(t) is continuous (and therefore absolutely contin)  x(t) absolutely continuous means it’s differentiable almost everywhere  So almost everywhere, by the chain rule, d/dt g(x(t),t) = g x (x(t),t) x’(t) + g t (x(t),t)  But we know the envelope condition holds, so V’(t) = d/dt g(x(t),t) = g t (x(t),t)  So almost everywhere, g x (x(t),t) x’(t) = 0

16 Let’s prove the sufficiency theorem  Suppose at type t, instead of x(t), I played x(t’), with t’ > t  My gain from the change is g(x(t’),t) – g(x(t),t) =  t t’ g x (x(s),t) x’(s) ds  Now, we know from before that at almost every s, g x (x(s),s) x’(s) = 0, so either g x (x(s),s) = 0 or x’(s) = 0  If x’(s) = 0, then g x (x(s),t) x’(s) = 0 as well  If g x (x(s),s) = 0, then since x(s)  x(t), smooth single crossing differences says g x (x(s),t)  0 (recall t < s)  And we know x’(s)  0  So for almost every s > t, g x (x(s),t) x’(s) ds  0  So integrating up, the switch from x(t) to x(t’) can’t be good  The symmetric argument rules out t’ < t

17 So there you have it…  If g is differentiable and satisfies smooth single crossing differences, then x weakly increasing and satisfying the Envelope condition implies x(t) is optimal AMONG THE RANGE OF x  We haven’t said anything about other possible x outside the range of x  Now, when will smooth single crossing differences be satisfied in auctions?  Well, g(x,t) = t W(x) – P(x), so g x = t W’(x) – P’(x) is weakly increasing in t as long as W is nondecreasing in x  So as long as higher bids win more often, the only condition we have to worry about is g being differentiable wrt x

18 Applying this to auctions,  Let b be a bid function, g the implied expected payoff function  If  g is differentiable with respect to x  b is weakly increasing  b and g satisfy the envelope condition  then b(t) is a best-response among the range of b  Still need to check separately for deviations outside the range of b  If the range of b is convex, that is, T is convex and b is continuous, only really have to worry about highest type deviating to higher bids, lowest type deviating to lower bids

19 Pulling it all together,  Theorem (Constraint Simplification). Let g(x,t) be a parameterized optimization problem. Suppose that  g is differentiable in both its arguments  g t has an integrable bound  g satisfies strict and smooth single crossing differences  Let x : [0,1]  X be the sum of an absolutely continuous function and a jump function, and let X* be the range of x  Then x(t)  arg max x  X* g(x,t) for every t if and only if  x is nondecreasing  the envelope condition holds

20 And in well-behaved symmetric IPV auctions,  b : T  R + is a symmetric equilibrium if and only if  b is increasing, and  b (and the g derived from it) satisfy the envelope formula

21 Up next…  Recasting auctions as direct revelation mechanisms  Optimal (revenue-maximizing) auctions  Might want to take a look at the Myerson paper, or the treatment in one of the textbooks  If you don’t know mechanism design, don’t worry, we’ll go over it

22 (I probably won’t get to) First-Order Stochastic Dominance

23 When is one probability distribution “better” than another?  Two probability distributions, F and G  F first-order stochastically dominates G if  -   u(s) dF(s)   -   u(s) dG(s) for every nondecreasing function u  So anyone who’s maximizing any increasing function prefers the distribution of outcomes F to G  (Very strong condition.)  Theorem. F first-order stochastically dominates G if and only if F(x)  G(x) for every x.

24 Proving FOSD  “F(x)  G(x) everywhere”  Proof for differentiable u. Rewrite it using a basis consisting of step functions   (s) = 0 if s < , 1 if s    Up to an additive constant, u(s) =  -   u’(  )   (s) d   To see this, calculate u(s’) – u(s) =  -   u’(  ) (   (s’) –   (s)) d  =  s s’ u’(  ) d   So F FOSD G if and only if  -     (s) dF(s)   -     (s) dG(s) for every 

25 Proving FOSD  “F(x)  G(x) everywhere”  But  -     (s) dF(s) = Pr(s   ) = 1 – F(  ) and similarly  -     (s) dG(s) = 1 – G(  )  So if F(x)  G(x) for all x, E s~F u(s)  E s~G u(s) for any increasing u  “Only if” is because   (x) is a valid increasing function of x