Health Prioritarianism Peter Vallentyne University of Missouri.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Choosing services Integrating Concerns for Cost-Effectiveness, Financial Protection, and the Worse Off Ole F. Norheim Professor in Medical Ethics and Philosophy.
Advertisements

Value Incommensurability and Vagueness Two items are incommensurable in value iff neither is better than the other nor are they equally good. The Small-Improvement.
Naïve Bayes. Bayesian Reasoning Bayesian reasoning provides a probabilistic approach to inference. It is based on the assumption that the quantities of.
M. Azhar Hussain, Mette Møller Jørgensen & Lars Peter Østerdal Refining Population Health Comparisons: A Multidimensional FOD Approach M. Azhar Hussain.
Equity, Pigou-Dalton, and Pareto Matthew Adler Duke University Harvard UC Conference, April 2013.
Regulating a Monopolist Monopolist choose output q m,whereas the efficient output is q w. Regulation will be needed to avoid the former result. However,
Christopher Dougherty EC220 - Introduction to econometrics (review chapter) Slideshow: asymptotic properties of estimators: plims and consistency Original.
ERE3: Ethics Foundations –Why is ethics so important? –Alternative views, including the standard economic position Time dimensions –Discounting –Sustainability.
Statistical Techniques I EXST7005 Lets go Power and Types of Errors.
McGraw-Hill Ryerson Copyright © 2011 McGraw-Hill Ryerson Limited. Adapted by Peter Au, George Brown College.
ASYMPTOTIC PROPERTIES OF ESTIMATORS: PLIMS AND CONSISTENCY
Chapter 7, Consumers, Producers, and the Efficiency of Markets
A Game Of Strategy … Or Luck? Serene Li Hui Heng Xiaojun Jiang Cheewei Ng Li Xue Alison Then Team 5, MS&E220 Autumn 2008.
Regulating a Monopolist Monopolist choose output q m,whereas the efficient output is q w. Regulation will be needed to avoid the former result. However,
The Goals of Public Health and the Ethics of Public Health Policy Christian Munthe Department of Philosophy, Göteborg University EuroPHEN, financed by.
Introduction to Hypothesis Testing
1 Civil Systems Planning Benefit/Cost Analysis Scott Matthews / and Lecture 2 - 9/1/2004.
Chapter 17 Unemployment, Inflation, and Growth. 2 Introduction In Chapter 4, 5, 6, we have studied a classical model of the complete economy, but said.
Chapter 4 Multiple Regression.
AN INTRODUCTION TO PORTFOLIO MANAGEMENT
The Goals of Public Health An Integrated Multi-dimensional Model Christian Munthe Department of Philosophy, Göteborg University EuroPHEN, funded by the.
Consumers, Producers, and the Efficiency of Markets Outline:  Positive economics: Allocation of scarce resources using forces of demand and supply  Normative.
CS Bayesian Learning1 Bayesian Learning. CS Bayesian Learning2 States, causes, hypotheses. Observations, effect, data. We need to reconcile.
Getting Started with Hypothesis Testing The Single Sample.
Summer Semester  Objective of a firm in a competitive market is to maximize profit.  Profit is equal to total revenue minus total cost of production.
Copyright © 2005 Brooks/Cole, a division of Thomson Learning, Inc Chapter 11 Introduction to Hypothesis Testing.
Business Statistics: Communicating with Numbers
ECON 6012 Cost Benefit Analysis Memorial University of Newfoundland
University of Papua New Guinea International Economics Lecture 10: Firms in the Global Economy [Internal Economies of Scale]
Determining Sample Size
Psy B07 Chapter 8Slide 1 POWER. Psy B07 Chapter 8Slide 2 Chapter 4 flashback  Type I error is the probability of rejecting the null hypothesis when it.
PRINCIPLES OF MICROECONOMICS Professor Karen Leppel Widener University Q P S D.
Theory testing Part of what differentiates science from non-science is the process of theory testing. When a theory has been articulated carefully, it.
The paired sample experiment The paired t test. Frequently one is interested in comparing the effects of two treatments (drugs, etc…) on a response variable.
Section 9.2 ~ Hypothesis Tests for Population Means Introduction to Probability and Statistics Ms. Young.
How Much Pollution Is Too Much?. Ethics and Economics.
Hypothesis Testing: One Sample Cases. Outline: – The logic of hypothesis testing – The Five-Step Model – Hypothesis testing for single sample means (z.
ECO 5550 More Health Capital Supply -- (Cost of Capital) Since health is a capital good, it is necessary to understand the cost of capital as well as.
Chapter 6 Lecture 3 Sections: 6.4 – 6.5.
CHAPTER 12 Income Redistribution: Conceptual Issues Copyright © 2010 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin.
Decision Making Under Uncertainty and Risk 1 By Isuru Manawadu B.Sc in Accounting Sp. (USJP), ACA, AFM
Chapter 10 Introduction to Estimation Sir Naseer Shahzada.
Inequality Larry Temkin. Studied at UW Madison, Oxford, and Princeton Currently chair of Philosophy at Rutgers.
CAPITAL BUDGETING_LECT 091 The Concept of Opportunity Cost The concept of opportunity cost is used in CBA to place a dollar value on the inputs required.
Lecture 16 Section 8.1 Objectives: Testing Statistical Hypotheses − Stating hypotheses statements − Type I and II errors − Conducting a hypothesis test.
Economics 173 Business Statistics Lecture 4 Fall, 2001 Professor J. Petry
Lecture 18 Dustin Lueker.  A way of statistically testing a hypothesis by comparing the data to values predicted by the hypothesis ◦ Data that fall far.
1 Demand for Repeated Insurance Contracts with Unknown Loss Probability Emilio Venezian Venezian Associates Chwen-Chi Liu Feng Chia University Chu-Shiu.
Computational Intelligence: Methods and Applications Lecture 16 Model evaluation and ROC Włodzisław Duch Dept. of Informatics, UMK Google: W Duch.
1 Comparing multiple tests for separating populations Juliet Popper Shaffer Paper presented at the Fifth International Conference on Multiple Comparisons,
International Economics. Comparative versus Absolute Advantage 0 Some people are better at producing things than others. This is an undisputable fact.
CHILD POVERTY and factors that affect it. What is child poverty? Child poverty: is a significant lack of the basic needs required for healthy physical,
Testing the Differences between Means Statistics for Political Science Levin and Fox Chapter Seven 1.
Fernando & Yvonn Quijano Prepared by: Consumer Behavior 3 C H A P T E R Copyright © 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Prentice Hall Microeconomics.
Math 3680 Lecture #13 Hypothesis Testing: The z Test.
Key West Productions Performance Analysis By, Kelly Quish.
Statistical Techniques
Chapter 15: Distribution May 20, Pareto optimality Economics defines efficiency as the Pareto optimal allocation of resources by the market  Assumption?
Critique of Hotelling Hotelling’s “Principle of Minimum Differentiation” was flawed No pure strategy exists if firms are close together. With quadratic.
Evaluation Institute Qatar Comprehensive Educational Assessment (QCEA) 2008 Summary of Results.
Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization Presented by: Kuan Chen.
Appendix 2 Comparison of screening from age 20 and age 25 Table of harms and benefits.
Decision Support Systems INF421 & IS Introduction To distinguish between normative theories, descriptive studies and prescriptive analysis; To.
 This will explain how consumers allocate their income over many goods.  This looks at individual’s decision making when faced with limited income and.
INCOME REDISTRIBUTION
end+disparities Learning Exchange Part IV: Calculator Assumptions
LIMITED DEPENDENT VARIABLE REGRESSION MODELS
Significance Tests: The Basics
Elements of a statistical test Statistical null hypotheses
Chapter 34 Welfare Key Concept: Arrow’s impossibility theorem, social welfare functions Limited support of how market preserves fairness.
Presentation transcript:

Health Prioritarianism Peter Vallentyne University of Missouri

Background Universal Coverage Question: What determines whether one form of universal coverage is morally better than another? More General Question: What determines whether a health policy/system, for a given country at a given time, is morally better than another? General Assumption: If one system is Pareto superior to the other (i.e., gives some people more wellbeing, and none less), then it is morally better. Simplifying Assumptions: –A useful proxy for individual’s lifetime wellbeing is individual health-adjusted years of life (e.g., number of Dalys) –Fixed population (so that total = average; and to avoid non-identity problem) –Certainty in outcomes (to avoid the need to appeal to probabilities) Health-year = df one year of “perfect” health (e.g., one Daly)

Health Utilitarianism Health Utilitarianism (no priority to less healthy): –(1) Greater total health-years is better. –(2) For same total health-years, the policies are equally good. Problem (no sensitivity to equity): No sensitivity to how individual health-years are distributed among people. Equity (relevant distribution-sensitivity): –Might appeal to desert –Might appeal to equality –Might appeal to priority for worse off. I shall focus on priority for worse off. Arguably, the appeal to wellbeing, or health-years, should be to brute luck wellbeing or health-years (i.e., not attributable to her agency). For simplicity, I ignore this.

Health Prioritarianism Health Prioritarianism: It is morally more important to increase the health-years of a given person by n units than to increase the health- years of a person with more health-years by n units. Questions: –(1) Is Health Prioritarianism correct? –(2) What are some of the main forms that it can take? Two reasons to endorse Health Prioritarianism: –Decreasing Marginal Impact of Health on Wellbeing –Wellbeing Prioritarianism Let’s explore each.

Decreasing Marginal Impact of Health on Wellbeing Decreasing Marginal Impact of Health on Wellbeing: For a given individual, all else being equal, increasing a person’s health-years by a given number of units has a smaller impact on her wellbeing, the higher her level of health-years is. Example: Suppose that increasing someone’s health-years from 1 unit to 2 increases her wellbeing by 1 unit. –Then, all else being equal, increasing her health-years from 2 units to 3 increases her wellbeing by less than 1 unit. Health Prioritarianism does not follow from Decreasing Marginal Impact on Wellbeing (in conjunction with Wellbeing Utilitarianism). The former is an interpersonal condition, whereas the latter is purely intrapersonal.

Decreasing Marginal Impact of Health on Wellbeing Example: HealthYour WellbeingMy Wellbeing We each have decreasing marginal impact of health on wellbeing, but increasing your health from 2 to 3 (increase of 5 units of wellbeing) may be more morally more important than increasing my health from 1 to 2 (increase of 1 unit of wellbeing). Health Prioritarianism does follow, if we assume (1) Wellbeing utilitarianism (maximize total), and (2) everyone’s cardinal wellbeing is cardinally affected by health in the same way (all else being equal). (2) is false, but it may be a good working assumption for aggregate measures of wellbeing for large populations. Let’s assume so.

Wellbeing Prioritarianism A second reason to endorse Health Prioritarianism: Wellbeing Prioritarianism: It is morally more important to increase the wellbeing of a given person by a given number of units than to increase the wellbeing of a person with greater wellbeing by the same number of units. This does not entail Health Prioritarianism: A person with lower health can have higher wellbeing (since health is not the only factor for wellbeing). Still, for large populations, at the aggregate level, wellbeing and health will be closely correlated. So, if Wellbeing Prioritarianism is correct, then there is a second reason to endorse Health Prioritarianism in practice when dealing with aggregates for large populations. Let us now consider some forms that Health Prioritarianism can take.

Weakly Prioritarian Health Utilitarianism Weakly Prioritarian Health Utilitarianism: –(1) Greater total health-years is better. –(2) For same total health-years, the policy with the greater lowest individual number of health-years is better (and, for ties, compare the second lowest number of health-years, etc.). This invokes priority only as a tie-breaker. –This is arguably too little priority.

Additive Prioritarianism Assume a set of finitely decreasing priority-weights for health-year increments. For example: Health-year IncrWeight Total Priority-Weighted HY 0 to to to Additive Prioritarianism: –(1) Greater total priority-weighted health-years is better. –(2) For same total priority-weighted health-years, the policies are equally good. This treats priority as more than a tie-breaker for the same total health-years.

Additive Prioritarianism One problematic feature is that this entails that it can judge it better to give a trivial increase in health to sufficiently many very healthy people rather than to give a major increase in health to one very unhealthy person. The severity of this problem will depend on how quickly the priority weights decrease. –They might decrease so slowly that in practice they are equivalent to constant marginal weights (as with utilitarianism). –Or they might decrease so quickly that in practice they are equivalent to leximin (absolutely priority of the worse off; see below).

Threshold prioritarianism Set a threshold for adequate health-years. A person’s truncated health-years is the lesser of her actual level of health-years and the threshold. –For example, if the threshold is 10, and A has 8 health-years and B has 12, then their respective truncated health-years are 8 and 10. Threshold prioritarianism: –(1) Greater total truncated prioritarian-weighted health-years (which ignores health above the threshold) is better. –(2) For the same total truncated prioritarian-weighted health-years, greater total prioritarian-weighted health-years (with no truncation) is better. Below the threshold, this gives finite priority to those who are worse off, and likewise above the threshold. –Moreover, it gives absolute priority to the health of those below the threshold over those above the threshold. Thus, it avoids the above problem “numbers problem”. This involves, however, a questionable discontinuity at the threshold.

Leximin Leximin: –(1) Greater health-years for a person with the least health-years is better. –(2) If there is a tie, greater health-years for a person with the second least health-years is better. Etc. This gives absolute priority to a less healthy person. It faces the problem that it deems it better to give the least healthy person a trivial increase in health rather than to give a massive number of people who are only slightly more healthy a massive increase in health.

Conclusion If one adopts Health Prioritarianism, there is the question of how strong the priority should be for the less healthy. There is an on-going investigation of these issues by moral philosophers and normative economists.