Human Rights and Agency: James Griffin, On Human Rights ER 11, Gov E-1040 Spring 2012.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Non-Consequentialism
Advertisements

The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
© Michael Lacewing Rights Michael Lacewing
Why Ethics? Should I bring my personal beliefs into my organisation? Should not an employer determine standards of behaviour for all employees? Should.
Why Ethics? Should I bring my personal beliefs into my organisation? Should not my employer determine standards of behaviour for all employees? Should.
Decisions at the end of life
What is deontology?.
What is Social Theory?. Theory Harrington 2005: 1-3 Greek word theōria, opp. of praxis contemplation / reflection Reflection on the value and meaning.
Seeing the Light: KANTIAN ETHICS (ch. 2.4)
Frameworks for Moral Arguments
Kant Are there absolute moral laws that we have to follow regardless of consequences? First we want to know what Kant has to say about what moral rule.
The moral importance of agency Frederike Kaldewaij Philosophy Department, Utrecht University Expert Meeting Fish welfare:
Kant’s Ethical Theory.
 Humans are metaphysically free  Our choices define us and as a result our intuitions about the human condition are satisfied.  Dualism  Kant  Existentialism.
SESSION-4: RESPECTING OTHERS AS HUMAN BEINGS. What is “respect”? Respect has great importance in everyday life Belief: all people are worthy of respect.
KANTIAN ETHICS IN FIVE EASY (?) STEPS. Sandel’s Classification of Normative Ethical Theories 1.Core concept: maximizing happiness – Utilitarianism (morality,
Master Theory and Practice of Human Rights Oslo C.Corradetti and V. Blaker Strand.
Final Class ER 11, Spring A long way Tale of Two Sparks.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Master Theory and Practice of Human Rights Oslo C.Corradetti.
Immanuel Kant The Good Will and Autonomy. Context for Kant Groundwork for Metaphysics of Morals after American Revolution and Before French- rights.
Phil 160 Kant.
360 Business Ethics Chapter 4. Moral facts derived from reason Reason has three properties that have bearing on moral facts understood as the outcomes.
Ethics and Morality Theory Part 2 11 September 2006.
Ethics and ethical systems 12 January
COMP 381. Agenda  TA: Caitlyn Losee  Books and movies nominations  Team presentation signup Beginning of class End of class  Rawls and Moors.
The Ethics of Duty and Rights The Ethics of Duty More than any other philosopher, Kant emphasized the way in which the moral life was centered on duty.
Kant’s deontological ethics
PHILOSOPHY 102 (STOLZE) Notes on Dale Jamieson, Ethics and the Environment, chapter 4.
Deontological tradition Contractualism of John Rawls Discourse ethics.
Topics in Moral and Political Philosophy Human Rights.
© Michael Lacewing Three theories of ethics Michael Lacewing
Kant’s Ethics of Duty 3 insights form the basis for his theory  An action has moral worth if it is done for the sake of duty. (DUTY)  An action is morally.
Deontological ethics. What is the point of departure? Each human beings should be treated as an end. Certain acts (lying, breaking promises, killing...)
Deontological & Consequential Ethics
Chapter One: Moral Reasons
Questioning Natural Rights: Utilitarianism ER 11, Spring 2012.
THEORIES OF ETHICS PART 2 OF CHAPTER 12 (ETHICS).
Business Ethics Lecture Rights and Duties 1.
Categorical and Practical Imperative
Normative Ethical Theory: Utilitarianism and Kantian Deontology
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 12 Kant By David Kelsey.
A Contemporary Approach to Moral Reasoning and to Human Rights: A Different Approach to Rights ER 11, Gov E 1040 Spring 2012.
Kant (5) Humanity as an end in itself. 3 formulations of the CI Universal law formulation: Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same.
EECS 690 January 29. Rights and Duties A right is a claim to a moral good. Every right that one person holds implies a duty or obligation upon another.
Traditional Ethical Theories. Reminder Optional Tutorial Monday, February 25, 1-1:50 Room M122.
Class 6 Kant. Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) From Königsberg, Germany.
© Michael Lacewing Kant’s Categorical Imperative Michael Lacewing
ETHICALETHICALETHICALETHICAL PRINCIPLESPRINCIPLESPRINCIPLESPRINCIPLES.
Morality in the Modern World
Jody Blanke, Professor Computer Information Systems and Law.
What is Bioethics? Ethics- examining and understanding choices. Ethics- examining and understanding choices. The discipline dealing with what is good and.
Ethics AIO 2015 LECTURE 2.
The Relationship between Religion and Moral Values
Immanuel Kant and the moral law. Kant (1) Kant’s ethics are those of the deist, rather than the theist. He was an important thinker in the deist project,
DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS (CH. 2.0) © Wanda Teays. All rights reserved.
Immanuel Kant (1724 – 1804) Influenced Secular Moral Thought. Raised in a Protestant Household. No formal Church Structure. Morality ground in reason,
Kantian Ethics Good actions have intrinsic value; actions are good if and only if they follow from a moral law that can be universalized.
KANTIANISM AND EUTHANASIA ATTITUDES TO KEY ISSUES.
EECS 690 January 27, Deontology Typically, when anyone talks about Deontology, they mean to talk about Immanuel Kant. Kant is THE deontologist.
WEEK 2 Justice as Fairness. A Theory of Justice (1971) Political Liberalism (1993)
Ethical Decision Making and Ethical Theory Mgmt 621 Contemporary Ethical Issues in Management Jeffery D. Smith.
Contemporary Moral Problems
Ethics and Values for Professionals Chapter 2: Ethical Relativism
Kant’s Categorical Imperative
B3- Olympic High School Science Camp
PHI 208 RANK Lessons in Excellence-- phi208rank.com.
ETHICS BOWL kantian ETHICS.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 15 Ethics #1: Utilitarianism
Michael Lacewing Rights Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Presentation transcript:

Human Rights and Agency: James Griffin, On Human Rights ER 11, Gov E-1040 Spring 2012

The goal – very roughly human rights as protections of “normative agency” agency involved in choosing worthwhile life central component of distinctively human life

Keep an eye on this question: Why does this generate rights?

Three lectures

Kantian themes: dignity “what we attach value to, what we regard as giving dignity to human life, is our capacity to choose and to pursue our conception of a worthwhile life” (p 44) it is “mere possession of this common capacity to identify the good that guarantees persons the protection of human rights.” (p 46) threshold notion: do children have it? Can old people lose it?

“dignitas”

Giovanni Pico della Mirandola ( ) Oration on the Dignity of Man (1486) God gave human beings choice to locate themselves somewhere on the (already existing) chain of being Having that freedom is “human dignity”

Chain of Being

Thoughts like this had to be applied against still existing Aristotelian idea of natural slavery Major theme in age of expansionism

How literal is the white-male-ness?

So it is this idea of dignity pertaining to all human beings that Griffin also makes central – but importantly different from Kant

Griffin vs. Kant and Gewirth “That is not a derivation of human rights from normative agency; it is a proposal based on a hunch that this way of remedying the indeterminacy of the term will best suit its role in ethics. (…) What I do is distant from what Kant and Mill did. It is also distant from what Alan Gewirth did recently, in seeking to establish human rights by appeal to certain logical necessities. That he too makes human agency central to his project does not make his project close to mine. (…) I claim no logical necessity for my proposal that we see human rights as protections of normative agency.” (p 4)

Put differently: Difference lies in argument used to derive rights Not self-consistency, but arguments that claim reasonable acceptability to every single person claim is: this is all one can ask for

Why respect human rights? What mistake is involved in not doing so? Natural lawyers: because it lies in natural order of things Utilitarian: because they are generally useful devices of social coordination Kant: because otherwise the mind contradicts itself Scanlon/Griffin: because we must find living arrangements that are reasonably acceptable to every single person

Two ways for supplying account of human rights “top-down” – start with an over-arching principle or decision- procedure, such as Categorical Imperative “bottom-up” – “one starts with human rights as used in our actual social life by politicians, lawyers, social campaigners, as well as theorists of various sorts, and then sees what higher principles one must resort to in order to explain their moral weight, when one thinks they have it, and to resolve conflicts between them. I prefer the bottom-up approach.” (p 29)

Determinacy in idea of human rights

Not about human good or flourishing, but (merely) about human status

Central idea: distinctively human existence “Human life is different from the life of other animals. We human beings have a conception of ourselves and of our past and future. We reflect and assess. We form pictures of what a good life would be – often, it is true, only on a small scale, but occasionally also on a large scale. And we try to realize these pictures. This is what we mean by a distinctively human existence (…) And we value our status as human beings especially highly, even more highly than even our happiness. This status centers on our being agents – deliberating, assessing, choosing, and acting to make what we see as a good life for ourselves.” (p 32)

Three sources of rights derived from personhood

Human rights: protecting human status/personhood/agency To be an agent one must (1)choose one’s own path through life – not be dominated or controlled by someone else (2)have real choice; at least minimum education and information; must be able to act; have at least minimum provision of resources and capabilities (3)others must not forcibly stop one from pursuing what one sees as a worthwhile life AUTONOMY MINIMAL PROVISIONS LIBERTY

Two reason to understand human rights this way – particular role for human rights in moral discourse (systematic) – finds that in historical development of idea (historic)

Protecting Personhood: Kant vs. Griffin (p 36) Kant: rational personhood to be protected no matter what Not for the sake of additional ends “absolute rights” Griffin: exercise of personhood normally enhances quality of life “rights resistant to trade- offs, but not too resistant”

Kant vs. Griffin Kant: dignity is inviolable – can never forfeit or waive it – inherently inalienable – torture: never justifiable Griffin: dignity is not categorically inviolable, though standards for violations are high – conceivable to justify torture in particular cases, though would support general prohibition

Universality rights one can derive to protect personhood at this abstract level apply universally Different rights might be derived from abstract protections – dependent on technological advancement of society for instance

Freedom of speech vs. freedom of the press

Human rights in Stone Age?

Universality, cont. does not claim “human rights” have independently arisen in different cultures spread of human rights is spread of Western- inspired discourse claim about origins, not justifiability

Note contrast to Amartya Sen “cultures are inherently diverse, and ideas of, or similar to, human rights have arisen in different cultures at different times”

Human rights: reaction against abuses, especially religious intolerance, government oppression, discrimination

Such abuses occur everywhere – values protected by human rights can be appreciated everywhere

Why limit human rights in this way? Are “human rights violations” always violations of normative agency?

“Is torture bad only because it undermines normative agency?”

No – but that makes it subject of human rights discourse Particular role in moral discourse

Why limit human rights in this way, cont. One partner in unsuccessful marriage might treat the other coldly and callously; suffering caused might add up into something worse than short period of physical torture first partner, simply by being cruel, does not violate human rights Human rights play distinctive role – to protect personhood gives them determinate place, and makes sense of the human-rights tradition -- bottom-up approach

Personhood and Practicalities Empirical information about human nature and societies, limits of human understanding and motivation needed to determine contents of human rights right to life: implies right to health support necessary for maintaining human status – but not that life be extended as long as possible (“fair span of life” (p 101)) no right to flourishing Matters massively for end-of-life care; physician-assisted suicide, etc.