Quantum Origins of Information and Ignorance Wojciech Hubert Zurek Theory Division, Los Alamos Deriving Probabilities from Symmetries of Entanglement “BEYOND.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
10.4 Complex Vector Spaces.
Advertisements

3D Geometry for Computer Graphics
Quantum Computing MAS 725 Hartmut Klauck NTU
What really happens upon quantum measurement?[n eeds revision] References are more fully listed in my Phys Rev A paperPhys Rev A paper Art Hobson Prof.
Introduction to Quantum Information Processing CS 467 / CS 667 Phys 467 / Phys 767 C&O 481 / C&O 681 Lecture 11 (2005) Richard Cleve DC 3524
Quantum Information Stephen M. Barnett University of Strathclyde The Wolfson Foundation.
Wojciech Hubert Zurek Theory Division, Los Alamos
Entropy in the Quantum World Panagiotis Aleiferis EECS 598, Fall 2001.
Emergence of Quantum Mechanics from Classical Statistics.
L2:Non-equilibrium theory: Keldish formalism
1. Introduction Consistency of learning processes To explain when a learning machine that minimizes empirical risk can achieve a small value of actual.
Wavefunction Quantum mechanics acknowledges the wave-particle duality of matter by supposing that, rather than traveling along a definite path, a particle.
Review of Basics and Elementary introduction to quantum postulates.
DENSITY MATRICES, traces, Operators and Measurements
Advanced Computer Architecture Lab University of Michigan Quantum Operations and Quantum Noise Dan Ernst Quantum Noise and Quantum Operations Dan Ernst.
Chien Hsing James Wu David Gottesman Andrew Landahl.
Introduction to Quantum Information Processing Lecture 4 Michele Mosca.
Quantum Mechanics from Classical Statistics. what is an atom ? quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum mechanics : isolated object quantum field theory.
Chapter 3 Formalism. Hilbert Space Two kinds of mathematical constructs - wavefunctions (representing the system) - operators (representing observables)
4. The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics 4A. Revisiting Representations
Dirac Notation and Spectral decomposition
Quantum Information Processing
PHYS 3313 – Section 001 Lecture #17
राघव वर्मा Inner Product Spaces Physical properties of vectors  aka length and angles in case of arrows Lets use the dot product Length of Cosine of the.
Presented by: Erik Cox, Shannon Hintzman, Mike Miller, Jacquie Otto, Adam Serdar, Lacie Zimmerman.
1 Introduction to Quantum Information Processing CS 667 / PH 767 / CO 681 / AM 871 Richard Cleve DC 2117 Lecture 14 (2009)
6. Second Quantization and Quantum Field Theory
Alice and Bob’s Excellent Adventure
1 Introduction to Quantum Information Processing QIC 710 / CS 667 / PH 767 / CO 681 / AM 871 Richard Cleve DC 2117 Lecture 16 (2011)
Quantum Physics Mathematics
Chap 3. Formalism Hilbert Space Observables
Quantum Physics Mathematics. Quantum Physics Tools in Real Life Reality.
Quantum One: Lecture Representation Independent Properties of Linear Operators 3.
Lecture 2. Postulates in Quantum Mechanics
Section 2.3 Properties of Solution Sets
The Quantum Theory of Atoms and Molecules The Schrödinger equation and how to use wavefunctions Dr Grant Ritchie.
Chap. 5 Inner Product Spaces 5.1 Length and Dot Product in R n 5.2 Inner Product Spaces 5.3 Orthonormal Bases: Gram-Schmidt Process 5.4 Mathematical Models.
Quantum Chemistry: Our Agenda Birth of quantum mechanics (Ch. 1) Postulates in quantum mechanics (Ch. 3) Schrödinger equation (Ch. 2) Simple examples of.
Quantum Two 1. 2 Angular Momentum and Rotations 3.
1 MODELING MATTER AT NANOSCALES 6. The theory of molecular orbitals for the description of nanosystems (part II) Perturbational methods for dealing.
Quantum Two 1. 2 Angular Momentum and Rotations 3.
DYNAMICS OF OPEN Q-SYSTES FROM A PERSPECTIVE OF QIT IMS, Imperial College, London, 18 January 2007 Vladimír Bužek Research Center for Quantum Information.
1 Introduction to Quantum Information Processing CS 467 / CS 667 Phys 467 / Phys 767 C&O 481 / C&O 681 Richard Cleve DC 3524 Course.
IPQI-2010-Anu Venugopalan 1 qubits, quantum registers and gates Anu Venugopalan Guru Gobind Singh Indraprastha Univeristy Delhi _______________________________________________.
Quantum Computers The basics. Introduction 2/47 Dušan Gajević.
Density matrix and its application. Density matrix An alternative of state-vector (ket) representation for a certain set of state-vectors appearing with.
Chapter 3 Postulates of Quantum Mechanics. Questions QM answers 1) How is the state of a system described mathematically? (In CM – via generalized coordinates.
Quantum Measurements: some technical background “Measurement postulate” “Projection postulate” The two aspects of measurement Density matrices, environments,
The Quantum Theory of Atoms and Molecules
Systems of Identical Particles
Jean Christian Boileau (University of Toronto)
Formalism Chapter 3.
Postulates of Quantum Mechanics
Introduction to Quantum Computing Lecture 1 of 2
Quantum mechanics from classical statistics
Quantum One.
Quantum Two.
4. The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics 4A. Revisiting Representations
Quantum Foundations Lecture 15
Quantum One.
Lecture on Linear Algebra
Quantum One.
Quantum Foundations Lecture 25
Quantum computation with classical bits
Linear Vector Space and Matrix Mechanics
Linear Vector Space and Matrix Mechanics
Computational approaches for quantum many-body systems
Presentation transcript:

Quantum Origins of Information and Ignorance Wojciech Hubert Zurek Theory Division, Los Alamos Deriving Probabilities from Symmetries of Entanglement “BEYOND DECOHERENCE” Robin Blume-Kohout, Fernando Cucchietti, Diego Dalvit, Harold Ollivier, Juan Pablo Paz, David Poulin, Hai-Tao Quan, Michael Zwolak,…

Textbook * Quantum Theory 1.Quantum states of a system are represented by vectors in its Hilbert space. (“Quantum Superposition Principle”) 2.Evolutions are unitary (e.g. generated by Schroedinger equation). (“Unitarity”) 3.Immediate repetition of a measurement yields the same outcome. (“Predictability”) 4.(a) Outcomes are restricted to orthonormal states {|s k >} (eigenstates of the measured observable). (b) Just one outcome is seen each time. (“Collapse Postulate”) 5.Probability of finding an outcome |s k > given a state |ƒ> is p k =| | 2. (“Born’s Rule”) 0. State of a composite system is a vector in the tensor product of the constituent Hilbert spaces. (“Complexity”) Bohr, Dirac, “Copenhagen” -- 4&5 require “classical apparatus”, etc. Everett: Relative states -- no need for explicit collapse! But need a preferred basis!!! * Dirac

Decoherence restricts stable states (states that can persist, and, therefore, “exist”) to the exceptional… Pointer states that exist or evolve predictably in spite of the immersion of the system in the environment. Predictability sieve can be used to ‘sift’ through the Hilbert space of any open quantum system in search of these pointer states. EINSELECTION (or Environment INduced superSELECTION) is the process of selection of these preferred pointer states. DECOHERENCE AND EINSELECTION Thesis: Quantum theory can explain emergence of the classical. Principle of superposition loses its validity in “open” systems, that is, systems interacting with their environments. For macroscopic systems, decoherence and einselection can be very effective, enforcing ban on Schroedinger cats. Einselection enforces an effective border that divides quantum from classical, making a point of view similar to Bohr’s Copenhagen Interpretation possible, although starting from a rather different standpoint (i. e., no ab initio classical domain of the universe). (Zeh, Joos, Paz, Hu, Caldeira, Leggett, Kiefer, Gell-Mann, Hartle, Omnes, Dalvit, Dziarmaga, Cucchietti … Haroche, Raimond, Brune, Zeilinger, Arndt, Hasselbach…)

S E REDUCED DENSITY MATRIX EINSELECTION *, POINTER BASIS, AND DECOHERENCE EINSELECTION* leads to POINTER STATES Stable states, appear on the diagonal of after decoherence time; pointer states are effectively classical! Pointer states left unperturbed by the “environmental monitoring”. *Environment INduced superSELECTION

Goal Why are the measurement outcomes limited to an orthogonal subset of all the possible states in the Hilbert states? (as in “Collapse”) Why does “Born’s rule” yield probabilities? How can “objective classical reality” -- states we can find out -- arise from the fragile quantum states that are perturbed by measurements? (“Quantum Darwinism”) Justify axioms 4&5 using the noncontroversial PLAN: Understand emergence of “objective classical reality” -- how real states that can be found out by us arise from quantum substrate. CANNOT USE DECOHERENCE UNTILL BORN’S RULE IS ESTABLISHED!!!

States that can survive “being found out” intact must be orthogonal. Consider two states that can be “found out” -- that change state of an apparatus: Consider an initial superposition of these two states: Norm must be preserved. Hence: Phases of the coefficients can be adjusted at will. So: So either (measurement was not successful) or QED!!!! PREDICTABILITY IMPLIES RESTRICTION TO ORTHOGONAL STATES!!! “collapse”

Consequences and extensions Derivation of the key to Collapse Postulate from Axioms 1-3: explains why in general one cannot “find out” preexisting states. Implies that observables are Hermitean (given an extra assumption that eigenvalues are real). Proof similar to “no cloning theorem” -- information about preexisting states cannot be found out -- passed on. (Cloning means making a “perfect copy”. Here the copy need not be perfect; “information - disturbance”). Proof can be extended to the case when apparatus (or environment) is initially in a mixed state. Axiom 3 -- predictability -- is the key to the proof! Information transfer need not be due to a deliberate measurement: any information transfer that does not perturb outcome states will have to abide by this rule: Pointer states, predictability sieve, and DECOHERENCE. ? Quantum Origin of Quantum Jumps…, Phys. Rev. A Nov ‘07; arXiv:quant-ph/

Summary: Observables are Hermitean Theorem: Outcomes of a measurement that satisfy postulates1-3 must be orthogonal. Proof (another version): measurement is an information transfer from a quantum system S to a quantum apparatus A. So, for any two possible repeatable (predictable) (Axiom 3) outcome states of the same measurement it must be true that: By unitarity (Axiom 2) scalar product of the total (S+A) state before and after must be the same. So: But. So either (measurement was not successful) or. QED!!!! NOTE: IN CONTRAST WITH DECOHERENCE, WE DO NOT INVOKE BORN’S RULE!!! “information gain implies disturbance” (Bennett, Brassard,& Mermin) DISTINGUISHABLE “EVENTS”

Plan Why the measurement outcomes are limited to an orthogonal subset of all the possible states in the Hilbert states? Why does “Born’s rule” yield probabilities? How can “objective classical reality” -- states we can find out -- arise from the fragile quantum states that are perturbed by measurements? (“Quantum Darwinism”) Derive controversial axioms 4&5 from the noncontroversial 0-3. Understand emergence of “objective classical reality” -- how real states that can be found out by us arise from quantum substrate.  WE HAVE “EVENTS”!

{ { Copy from a translation, p in “Quantum Theory and Measurement”, John Archibald Wheeler & WHZ, eds. (Princeton U. Press, 1983)

{ {

!{

S E EINSELECTION, POINTER BASIS, AND DECOHERENCE ……..Depends on Born’s Rule!!! EINSELECTION leads to POINTER STATES (same states appear on the diagonal of for times long compared to decoherence time) REDUCED DENSITY MATRIX WE HAVE “EVENTS”!

ENVARIANCE (Entanglement-Assisted Invariance) Consider a composite quantum object consisting of system S and environment E. When the combined state is transformed by: but can be “untransformed” by acting solely on E, that is, if there exists: then is ENVARIANT with respect to. Envariance is a property of and the joint state of two systems, S & E. DEFINITION:

ENTANGLED STATE AS AN EXAMPLE OF ENVARIANCE: Schmidt decomposition: Above Schmidt states are orthonormal and complex. Lemma 1: Unitary transformations with Schmidt eigenstates: leave envariant. Proof: LOCALLY, SCHMIDT PHASES DO NOT MATTER: DECOHERENCE!!!

PHASE ENVARIANCE THEOREM Fact 1: Unitary transformations must act on the system to alter its state (if they act only somewhere else, system is not effected). Fact 2: The state of the system is all that is necessary/available to predict measurement outcomes (including their probabilities). Fact 3: A state of the composite system is all that is needed/available to determine the state of the system. Moreover, “entanglement happens”: THEOREM 1: State (and probabilities) of S alone can depend only on the absolute values of Schmidt coefficients, and not on their phases. Proof: Phases of can be changed by acting on S alone. But the state of the whole can be restored by acting only on E. So change of phases of Schmidt coefficients could not have affected S ! QED. By phase envariance, { } must provide a complete local description of the system alone. Same info as reduced density matrix!!!

Envariance of entangled states: the case of equal coefficients In this case ANY orthonormal basis is Schmidt. In particular, in the Hilbert subspace spanned by any two { } one can define a Hadamard basis; This can be used to generate ‘new kind’of envariant transformations: A SWAP: Can be ‘undone’ by the COUNTERSWAP: LEMMA 3: Swaps of states are envariant when Schmidt coefficients have same absolute value.

“Probability from certainty” Probabilities of Schmidt partners are the same (detecting 0 in S implies 0 in E, etc.). |0>|0> + |1>|1> (initial state -- equal abs. values of coeff’s) SWAP on S |1>|0> + |0>|1> (prob’s in S must have swapped, because after the swap they are equal to the prob’s of state in E that were not affected) COUNTERSWAP on S |1>|1> + |0>|0> (prob’s in E must be the same as they were to begin with -- the global state is back to the “original”) Probabilities can “stay the same” and also “get swapped” only when they are equal!!! (p(0)=p(1)) (Barnum, Schlosshauer & Fine, WHZ)

Probability of envariantly swappable states By the Phase Envariance Theorem the set of pairs provides a complete description of S. But all are equal. With additional assumption about probabilities (e.g., perfect correlation as on the previous transparency), one can prove THEOREM 2: Probabilities of envariantly swappable states are equal. (a)“Pedantic assumption”; when states get swapped, so do probabilitites; (b)When the state of the system does not change under any unitary in a part of its Hilbert space, probabilities of any set of basis states are equal. (c) Because there is one-to-one correlation between Therefore, by normalization:

Special case with unequal coefficients Consider system S with two states The environment E has three states and An auxilliary environment E’ interacts with E so that: States have equal coefficients. Therefore, Each of them has probability of 1/3. Consequently: p(0) = p(0,0)+p(0,1) = 2/3, and p(2) = 1/3. ….. BORN’s RULE!!! no need to assume additivity! (p(0)=1-p(2))!

Probabilities from Envariance The case of commensurate probabilities: Attach the auxiliary “counter” environment C : THEOREM 3: The case with commensurate probabilities can be reduced to the case with equal probabilities. BORN’s RULE follows: General case -- by continuity. QED.

ENVARIANCE* -- SUMMARY 1.New symmetry - ENVARIANCE - of joint states of quantum systems. It is related to causality. 2.In quantum physics perfect knowledge of the whole may imply complete ignorance of a part. 3. BORN’s RULE follows as a consequence of envariance. 4.Relative frequency interpretation of probabilities naturally follows. 5.Envariance supplies a new foundation for environment - induced superselection, decoherence, quantum statistical physics, etc., by justifying the form and interpretation of reduced density matrices. *WHZ, PRL 90, ; RMP 75, 715 (2003); PRA 71, (2005).

Plan Why the measurement outcomes are limited to an orthogonal subset of all the possible states in the Hilbert states? Why does “Born’s rule” yield probabilities? How can “objective classical reality” -- states we can find out -- arise from the fragile quantum states that are perturbed by measurements? (“Quantum Darwinism”) Derive controversial axioms 4&5 from the noncontroversial 0-3. Understand emergence of “objective classical reality” -- how real states that can be found out by us arise from quantum substrate.  

Quantum Darwinism The imprint left by the system S in the environment E is the cause of decoherence The focus of decoherence is the information that is left in S in spite of E. (“reduced density matrix” of S) Quantum Darwinism is focused on the information about S that can be found out indirectly from E !!! (i)How many copies of the information about S can be extracted from E? (Redundancy) (ii)What is this information about? (i.e, what observable of S gets redundantly imprinted in E?) (iii)Why does this matter? Robin Blume-Kohout (PI, Waterloo) Harold Ollivier (INRIA, France) David Poulin (IQC, Waterloo)

Quantum Darwinism -- “The Big Picture” Certain “fittest” information about S proliferates -- it is recorded in E in many copies Complementary information is diluted -- effectively obliterated The fittest information is about the einselected pointer states that can “survive” decoherence Information that can be obtained indirectly and independently by many is in effect objective Its acquisition does not endanger preexisting state of the system (which can be “found out” as if it were classical) (Environment as a witness) How do we analyze this?

Mutual Information where ● Measures the increase in entropy from eliminating correlations between S and E. ● No reference to observables or measurements. ● Bounded by. Measuring what E knows about S 1. Partial Info: How much does a fragment supply? 2. Redundancy: How many disjoint fragments supply ?

PIP = How info is distributed in E (Partial Information Plot) Maximum Classical Information “all but a small fraction  ” of classical info NOTE: This shape of Partial Information Plot is NOT ”typical” !!!!

c c Partial Information Plots (a visual characterization of information storage) ● Plot size of a fragment (F) vs. amount of info it provides. ● 3 info profiles: - redundant (decoherence) - distributed - TYPICAL (encoded) ● We average over all fragments of a given size. ● = Redundancy of “all but δ ” of the available info (1- δ )H S } ✵ Blume-Kohout & Zurek, Foundations of Physics (~Nov. 2005), quant-ph/

What does E know about? Q: What observables can be inferred from E ? - Consider GHZ: - “Ising” model -> singly branching states A: Only the pointer observable recorded redundantly! c c a) ✵ Ollivier, Poulin, & Zurek, PRL 93, (2004). ✵ Ollivier, Poulin, & Zurek, PRA 72, (2005).. angle with pointer observable

Quantum Darwinism -- brief summary of results Environment knows about the system. Every fragment of the environment knows the same thing about the system. They all know about the pointer observable. Many observers can extract that information without disturbing the state of the system. Pointer states / observables become “objective”. The ability of a state to survive decoherence without getting perturbed (1 st part of the talk) is the key.