Kant’s Transcendental Idealism according to Henry E. Allison Itzel Gonzalez Phil 4191 March 2, 2009.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Commentary on Katalin Balog, In defense of the phenomenal concept strategy Assistant Prof. István Aranyosi, Bilkent University, Ankara, Turkey.
Advertisements

© Michael Lacewing The concept of a person Michael Lacewing.
Joe Levines Purple Haze. Physical/Phenomenal Gaps P = the complete microphysical truth Q = a phenomenal truth Q1: Is there an epistemic gap between.
Immanuel Kant ( ) Theory of Aesthetics
The Subject-Matter of Ethics
Meditation IV God is not a Deceiver, Truth Criterion & Problem of Error.
The Cogito. The Story So Far! Descartes’ search for certainty has him using extreme sceptical arguments in order to finally arrive at knowledge. He has.
Descartes God.
Philosophy and the proof of God's existence
Descartes’ rationalism
Descartes’ rationalism
René Descartes ( ) Father of modern rationalism. Reason is the source of knowledge, not experience. All our ideas are innate. God fashioned us.
Idealism.
Kant, Transcendental Aesthetic
Malcolm’s ontological argument Michael Lacewing
Introduction to Ethics Lecture 6 Ayer and Emotivism By David Kelsey.
Hume on Taste Hume's account of judgments of taste parallels his discussion of judgments or moral right and wrong.  Both accounts use the internal/external.
The Rationalists: Descartes Certainty: Self and God
Critique of Pure Reason Philosophy 1 Spring, 2002 G. J. Mattey.
 Derives from Greek words meaning Love of Wisdom.
Parsing Categories of Belief Why Early Modern M&E divides belief into two types: Sensory & Mathematical.
More categories for our mental maps  How we understand knowledge has repercussions for how we understand our place in the world.  How we understand.
The Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787)
Why a third Critique? Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 1 18/9/2007 Text: Preface Claus Beisbart.
Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason. Historical Context Kant lived during the age of enlightenment The spirit of enlightenment (Aufklaerung): 1. Universalism:
Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason Preface B, Introductions A & B.
© Michael Lacewing Reason and experience Michael Lacewing
Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 3 20/9/2007 Text: Introduction (III-IX) Claus Beisbart The Power of Judgment.
Philosophy 1050: Introduction to Philosophy Week 10: Descartes and the Subject: The way of Ideas.
Chapter 3: Knowledge Kant’s Revolution Introducing Philosophy, 10th edition Robert C. Solomon, Kathleen Higgins, and Clancy Martin.
© Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing co.uk.
11/26/2015 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant III Charles Manekin.
An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding
© Michael Lacewing Kant on conceptual schemes Michael Lacewing osophy.co.uk.
Seminar “Kant: Critique of the Power of Judgment” University of Iceland Session 7 2/10/2007 Text: Critique of the Aesthtical Power of Judgment (9-17) Claus.
Philosophy 190: Seminar on Kant Spring, 2015 Prof. Peter Hadreas Course website: nt/index.html.
LECTURE 19 THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT CONTINUED. THE QUANTUM MECHANICAL OBJECTION DEPENDS UPON A PARTICULAR INTERPRETATION WE MIGHT REASONABLY SUSPEND.
Descates Meditations II A starting point for reconstructing the world.
1/9/2016 Modern Philosophy PHIL320 1 Kant II Charles Manekin.
L ECTURE 15: C ERTAINTY. T ODAY ’ S L ECTURE In Today’s Lecture we will: 1.Review Hume’s radical empiricism and its consequences 2.Outline and investigate.
Knowledge rationalism Michael Lacewing
Lecture 13: Empiricism.
Philosophy 190: Seminar on Kant Spring, 2015 Prof. Peter Hadreas Course website: nt/index.html.
The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel’s Idealism.
Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning.
An analysis of Kant’s argument against the Cartesian skeptic in his ‘Refutation of Idealism” Note: Audio links to youtube are found on my blog at matthewnevius.wordpress.com.
Thomas Aquinas “On Being and Essence”. Saint Thomas Aquinas born ca. 1225; died 7 March 1274 Dominican.
KANT ON THE POSSIBILITY OF METAPHYSICS Text source: Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, introduction.
WEEK 4: EPISTEMOLOGY Introduction to Rationalism.
JUDGMENTS. Transcendental Aesthetic of Time “Time is not an empirical concept deduced from any experience, for neither co-existence nor succession would.
From Pyrrhonian Skepticism to Justification for Belief.
OA: Faith and Reason What difference does the argument make
Intuition and deduction thesis (rationalism)
The ontological argument
c) Strengths and weaknesses of Cosmological Arguments:
Kant’s criticisms of the Ontological Argument
Philosophy and History of Mathematics
O.A. so far.. Anselm – from faith, the fool, 2 part argument
Philosophy of Mathematics 1: Geometry
The zombie argument: responses
B-Deduction §15-§26.
Michael Lacewing Hume and Kant Michael Lacewing © Michael Lacewing.
Rationalism.
THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT.
Explore key ideas in the ontological argument. (8 marks)
EXAM WEEK DATES THE FINAL EXAM IS 12 NOON, THURS 9th
The Big Picture Deductive arguments - origins of the ontological argument Deductive proofs; the concept of ‘a priori’. St Anselm - God as the greatest.
Clarify and explain the key ideas. A’priori Deductive
Clarify and explain the key ideas. A’priori Deductive
A Failure of Recognition Pt. 2
Presentation transcript:

Kant’s Transcendental Idealism according to Henry E. Allison Itzel Gonzalez Phil 4191 March 2, 2009

Overview Henry E. Allison (biographical facts) Ch.7: The Transcendental Deduction from Kant’s Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense Introduction Sec. 1: Apperception, Synthesis, and Objectivity Sec. 2: The Problem of Subjective Unity Sec. 3: Imagination, Perception, and Experience Conclusions

Henry E. Allison Currently, he is an Emeritus Professor at the University of Boston He published the 1 st edition of Kant’s Transcendental Idealism in 1983 (the 2 nd (ours) in 2004)

Introduction He focuses on the B-edition of Kant’s Transcendental Deduction (B-Deduction) And claims Kant’s central problem in it to be “the demonstration of a connection between the intellectual and sensible conditions of human cognition.” (159) That is, he maintains Kant’s worry to be the existence of a correspondence between the deliverances of sensibility and the a priori rules of thought. Further, Henry, in agreement with Dieter Henrich, claims that Kant, as a solution, attempts to establish the necessity of the categories.

Introduction (cont.) Also, like Henrich, he claims that Kant divides the argument in the B-Deduction for the necessity of the categories into 2 parts: The 1 st being meant to assert the necessity of the categories with respect to objects of sensible intuition in general (that is, “any sensible content must be subject to the categories if it is to be brought to the unity of consciousness”) The 2 nd being meant to argue “for the necessity of the categories with respect to human sensibility and its objects” (160)

Introduction (cont.) According to Allison, Henrich, asserts that “the 1 st part of the B-Deduction affirms the validity of the categories under a restricting condition that is then removed in the second part.” (161) However, Allison finds questionable Henrich’s claim that the 1 st part of the Deduction effectively demonstrates that “the categories…apply to a certain range of intuitions,” particularly, because Kant intends the 1 st part of the Deduction to contain the broader claim and Henrich’s assertion appears to place the broader claim, instead, in the 2 nd part. (Note 7, p.476) Hence, Allison assumes a different interpretation from that of Henrich.

Introduction (cont.) Allison, contrary to Henrich, interprets the 1 st part of the B-Deduction to show that “the thought of objects” stands under the categories, while the 2 nd the further claim that “the perception of objects” is also linked to the categories. (162) A Foreshadowing…

I.Apperception, Synthesis, and Objectivity ‘(t)he I think must be able to accompany all my representations; for otherwise something would be represented in me that could not be thought at all, which is as much as to say that the representation would either be impossible or else at least would be nothing to me. That representation that can be given prior to all thought is called intuition. Thus all manifold of intuition has a necessary relation to the I think in the same subject in which this manifold is to be encountered.’ (Critique of Pure Reason, B131 – 132)

I. (cont.) Allison’s 3 claims: 1.For any representation to be anything “to me, that is, to represent anything for me, it must be possible to think it as mine. Since a representation for which this is not possible could not represent anything for me, it would…be ‘nothing to me.’” (163) 2.One just means that “the I think must be able to (but need not actually) accompany all my representations.” (164) 3.The Principle of the Necessary Synthetic Unity of Apperception (“the fundamental premise of the 1 st part of the argument in the B-Deduction”) (164)

I. (cont.) The Principle of the Necessary Synthetic Unity of Apperception (PNSUA): “the components of a complex thought must be connected in such a way as to allow for the possibility of their ascription to a single thinking subject, which entails that they constitute a synthetic unity.” (164) (Argument for PNSUA derives from the idea that “a single complex thought logically requires a single thinker”) (164)

I. (cont.) The Principle of the Necessary Unity of Apperception (PNUA): “all representations in any given intuition must stand under the condition under which alone I can ascribe them to the identical self as my representations, and thus can grasp them together, as synthetically combined in an apperception, through the general expression I think.” (Critique of Pure Reason, B 138) This principle, which Kant claims to be an analytic proposition, is “a claim about how the thinking subject must be thought (or conceive of itself) qua engaged in such activity.” (167)

I. (cont.) Note: PNUA is an analytic proposition because it is derived by abstracting “from the nature of sensibility,” which leads thought to be related to “the concept of ‘sensible intuition in general.’” (167)

I. (cont.) The analytic unity of apperception presupposes a synthetic unity, as 1.The consciousness of the identity of the I think “contains a synthesis, and 2.The consciousness of the identity of the I think is possible only through a consciousness of this synthesis This follows because “a subject cannot think its own identity with respect to distinct representations without in the same act bringing them into a synthetic unity.” ( )

I. (cont.) Argument for the connection between the doctrine of apperception and the necessity of a consciousness of synthesis:  A single complex thought (formed by a A and B) requires both a single thinker, as well as a unified act of thinking (in which A and B are thought together).  The I think lacks content apart from the consciousness of the identity of this unifying action through which the thinking subject becomes aware of his or her own identity. (171)

I. (cont.) This connection results in Kant viewing: “all general concepts as analytic unities,” “the I think…(as) itself the thought of what is common to all conceptualization,” and “the act of becoming aware of this identical I think…(as) the…means (by)…which the mind grasps the identity in difference in the formation of general concepts.” (172)

I. (cont.) According to Allison, from the connection of apperception to the understanding, Kant derives the claim that “in so far as the manifold of a given intuition is grasped as a manifold or brought to the synthetic unity of apperception, it is by this very act, also unified in a judgment (which is “the way to bring given cognitions to the objective unity of apperception” B ).” And, further, that as “the logical functions of judgment are the forms of such unification…that the manifold is also determined with regard to them.” That is, “for a discursive understanding to think the manifold of a given intuition just is to unify it in a judgment by means of the logical functions.” (177)

I. (cont.) This claim ties apperception to the categories, establishing their necessity, as “the categories just are…(the mentioned) logical functions.” Allison maintains that Kant shows how “the manifold, insofar as it is thought together in a single consciousness, is necessarily subject to the categories.” (177)

II. The Problem of Subjective Unity Here Allison presents a problem of Kant’s: According to Allison, by Kant claiming that “the empirical unity of apperception is derived from the transcendental or objective unity ‘under given conditions in concreto,’” he must mean that “though the content of such consciousness is determined by contingent empirical factors…its form as a mode of consciousness is subject to the transcendental conditions of unity.” (184) But how is a non-objective form of consciousness possible?

III.Imagination, Perception, and Experience According to Allison, Kant introduces the idea of the imagination in Sec. 24 under the name figurative synthesis (synthesis speciosa) and makes two claims about it. Kant claims: 1.That this synthesis, under the name of the transcendental synthesis of the imagination, has both an a priori dimension and a transcendental function in the determining of time as the form of inner sense 2.That since this function must accord with conditions of the synthetic unity of apperception, it is subject to the categories (189)

III.(cont.) Allison notes that Kant furthers his project of establishing the necessity of the categories by demonstrating that the transcendental synthesis of the imagination connects the categories with the forms of sensibility. However, Allison also notes that such move is not sufficient for Kant to meet his goal, as to meet his goal he must also “demonstrat(e)…that the categories stand in a necessary connection with empirical intuition.” (193)

III. (cont.) According to Allison, Kant attempts to solve this problem by linking the categories to the synthesis of apprehension, which he defines as “the composition of the manifold in an empirical intuition, through which perception…becomes possible.” (193)

III. (cont.) In other words, according to Allison, Kant attempts to resolve his problem by claiming that even perception must stand under the categories. But a further problem arises: Namely, that “linking the categories to perception cannot account for the epistemic function of all the categories.” (200) And an argument must incorporate this point, because “the different category types have significantly different experiential functions.” (201)

Conclusions Allison maintains that Kant’s project in the B- Deduction to link the deliverances of sensibility to the a priori rules of thought (that is, “to…connect…the intellectual and sensible conditions of human cognition”) though begun is not completed. (201) It is begun as Kant in the B-Deduction does effectively link the categories to thought and then, subsequently, to perception. However, it is not completed as Kant “cannot account for the epistemic function of all the categories.” (200) So while there is no complete vindication of Kant’s account, it must also be noted, as Allison does, that Kant’s account lacks intrinsic incoherencies in it. (201)