Symposium on Language and Perception How does language affect what are normally considered to be lower-level perceptual and motor processes? Is language.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Constructing the World Week 4 David Chalmers. The Case for Scrutability (1) PQTI and the Cosmoscope (2) The Cosmoscope Argument (3) Empirical Scrutability.
Advertisements

Communication Theory Lecture 1: Introduction to Communication Theory and Novel Technology Dr. Danaë Stanton Fraser.
The Dictionary as Mirror of the Mind Stevan Harnad with collaborators: Alexandre Blondin-Massé Guillaume Chicoisne Yassine Gargouri Odile Marcotte Olivier.
Lecture 20 Theories of Consciousness, Consciousness and the Mind-Body Problem.
CSCTR Session 11 Dana Retová.  Start bottom-up  Create cognition based on sensori-motor interaction ◦ Cohen et al. (1996) – Building a baby ◦ Cohen.
1 Intuitive Irrationality: Reasons for Unreason. 2 Epistemology Branch of philosophy focused on how people acquire knowledge about the world Descriptive.
Introduction to Cognitive Sciences Harmanjit Singh Dipendra Misra Divyaratn Poply Kritika Singh Rishabh Raj.
Ontology From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In philosophy, ontology (from the Greek oν, genitive oντος: of being (part. of εiναι: to be) and –λογία:
Hume on Taste Hume's account of judgments of taste parallels his discussion of judgments or moral right and wrong.  Both accounts use the internal/external.
CPSC 411, Fall 2008: Set 12 1 CPSC 411 Design and Analysis of Algorithms Set 12: Undecidability Prof. Jennifer Welch Fall 2008.
Organizational Notes no study guide no review session not sufficient to just read book and glance at lecture material midterm/final is considered hard.
Concepts and Categories. Functions of Concepts By dividing the world into classes of things to decrease the amount of information we need to learn, perceive,
Sebastian Bitzer Seminar Neurophysiological Foundations of Consciousness University of Osnabrueck A sensorimotor.
Green’s Tri-Level Hypothesis Behavioral: a person’s performance on specific experimental tasks Cognitive: the postulated cognitive or affective systems.
What is Cognitive Science? … is the interdisciplinary study of mind and intelligence, embracing philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence, neuroscience,
Physical Symbol System Hypothesis
What is Cognitive Science? … is the interdisciplinary study of mind and intelligence, embracing philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence, neuroscience,
Conceptual modelling. Overview - what is the aim of the article? ”We build conceptual models in our heads to solve problems in our everyday life”… ”By.
Lecture 1 Introduction: Linguistic Theory and Theories
Roles of Knowledge in Cognition 1 Knowledge is often thought of as constituting particular bodies of facts, techniques, and procedures that cultures develop,
Theories of Development. Cognitive Development Early psychologists believed that children were not capable of meaningful thought and that there actions.
Chapter 2: Modeling mental imagery. Cognitive Science  José Luis Bermúdez / Cambridge University Press 2010 The ingredients Encountered some of the basic.
RESEARCH IN EDUCATION Chapter I. Explanations about the Universe Power of the gods Religious authority Challenge to religious dogma Metacognition: Thinking.
Philosophy of Mind Week 3: Objections to Dualism Logical Behaviorism
Language, Mind, and Brain by Ewa Dabrowska Chapter 7: Words.
The Newell Test for a Theory of Mind Anderson, John R., & Lebiere, Christian (forthcoming), “The Newell Test for a Theory of Mind”, Behavioral & Brain.
Cognitive Development. Jean Piaget Cognitive development theory Children "construct" their understanding of the world through their active involvement.
 Young children view the world very differently from adults.  E.g. no unusual for a child to think the sun follows them.  Field of cognitive psychology.
Jean Piaget EDRD 613 Suzanne Peters Lexi Allman Amanda Fecik.
Emotion and the Brain Emotion Amygdala- Ability to learn emotional associations, recognize emotional expressions, and perceive emotionally charged words.
1 Thinking in Objects and Classes © Datasim Education BV, 2010 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a database or retrieval.
Artificial Intelligence Introductory Lecture Jennifer J. Burg Department of Mathematics and Computer Science.
Theory of Cognitive Development
JEAN PIAGET HALIMA SHARIAT & TENI KURIAN.
Chapter 6 Cognitive and Learning Characteristics © Taylor & Francis 2015.
Chapter 2 Developmental Psychology A description of the general approach to behavior by developmental psychologists.
Chapter 7: Theories of Cognitive Development Module 7.1 Setting the Stage: Piaget’s Theory Module 7.2 Modern Theories of Cognitive Development Module 7.3.
Sense Perception Chapter 4.
SPEECH AND WRITING. Spoken language and speech communication In a normal speech communication a speaker tries to influence on a listener by making him:
© 2008 The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. Chapter 8: Cognition and Language.
Philosophy 4610 Philosophy of Mind Week 4: Objections to Behaviorism The Identity Theory.
University of Windsor School of Computer Science Topics in Artificial Intelligence Fall 2008 Sept 11, 2008.
Types of Minds J. Scott Jordan Department of Psychology Illinois State University.
© Michael Lacewing Kant on conceptual schemes Michael Lacewing osophy.co.uk.
INFO 414 Information Behavior Theoretical foundations, frameworks and paradigms.
Experimental Research Methods in Language Learning Chapter 5 Validity in Experimental Research.
SIMULATIONS, REALIZATIONS, AND THEORIES OF LIFE H. H. PATTEE (1989) By Hyojung Seo Dept. of Psychology.
Intelligence. Intelligence Tests and Testing Intelligence tests measure innate intelligence. Intelligence tests measure capacity or potential. IQ’s are.
Situated Cognition: A New Direction in AI Bram van Heuveln.
 How would you rate your memory? Does this number vary from day to day? Morning to evening?
1 26 September, 2000HKU Categorization Assigning things (percepts, concepts, objects, etc.) to distinct groups in a principled (rule-based) manner.
From Knowing-How To Knowing-That: Acquiring Categories By Word of Mouth Stevan Harnad (UQAM & U. Southampton)
PSY 432: Personality Chapter 1: What is Personality?
Grounded cognition. Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Annual Review of Psychology, 59, Grounded theories versus amodal representations. – Recapitulation.
Fundamentals of Informatics Lecture 12 The Halting Problem Bas Luttik.
IMAGINATION And knowledge. Bellwork ◦What role does imagination play in the various IB subjects that you study?
Computational Learning Theory Part 1: Preliminaries 1.
There is no concrete For autonomous sensorimotor systems like us, all objects, whether primroses or prime numbers, are abstractions.
Chapter 11 Language. Some Questions to Consider How do we understand individual words, and how are words combined to create sentences? How can we understand.
3.1 Cognitive processes. Cognitive psychology Includes: perception, thinking, problem solving, memory, language, and attention. Cognition refers to such.
According to Piaget, the stages Involve discontinuous (qualitative) change Form an invariant sequence –Stages are never skipped.
Perceptual Effects of New Category Learning: An Online Study
Moderate embodiment for educational design
Theory of Knowledge Review
Rationalism versus Empiricism
Intercultural Communication & Effectiveness
Do we directly perceive objects? (25 marks)
Chapter 9- Early Childhood: Cognitive Development
Piaget: Theory of cognitive development
Presented by Tim Hamilton
Presentation transcript:

Symposium on Language and Perception How does language affect what are normally considered to be lower-level perceptual and motor processes? Is language best conceptualized as a symbolic system in which terms derive all of their meaning from their relations to one another? How does the language we acquire augment our ability to represent, reason about, and computationally process our world? How do our perceptual abilities shape language processes normally considered to be arbitrary or ungrounded? How much of our language is perceptually grounded? How else can elements of our language get their meaning? How are the various components of language (word meanings, sounds, and grammatical constructions) influenced by perceptual and action processes? How do these same components influence perceptual and conceptual processes? Indiana University Monday, April 4, 2005, 12:00-2:00 PM Dogwood Room, Indiana Memorial Union Panelists Lera Boroditsky, Assistant Professor of Psychology, Stanford University Stevan Harnad, Canada Research Chair and Professor, Université du Québec à Montréal Linda Smith, Chancellor’s Professor of Psychology, Indiana University

Language --> Perception or Perception --> Language Does what we see determine what we say? Or does what we say determine what we see? (Let’s C…) Stevan Harnad U. du Québec à Montreal

1. Commensurability the fundamental question of whether it can be said that the objective shape of things in the world "resembles" the shape of their subjective appearance in our minds at all, rather than just being behaviorally correlated with it: e.g., how/why does bigger sound-wave amplitude resemble sounding louder, rather than softer, or for that matter, greener? how/why does looking curved resemble being curved?

2. Constructivism/Coherence/Consistency the notion that what things look like -- the shape of their subjective appearance -- is something we "construct", by social convention, culturally, or arbitrarily, with perhaps the only constraint being that the construction should be consistent or coherent with itself

3. Congruity/Conformity the notion that what things look like -- the shape of their appearance -- is congruent with the shape of what they really are like: that the subjective "shape" of appearances, not being constructed by culture, simply conforms to the objective shape of things in reality

4. Correlation the empirical fact -- objectively measurable through psychophysics and adaptive behavior -- that there is a correlation (which is not the same as a congruity) between the real shape of things and the shape of our behavior in response to them: we reliably call more "more," and act accordingly

5. Conformity/Constraint the notion that the shape of appearances is merely constrained by the shape of reality [and logic], at least inasmuch as I/O correlation and adaptive behavior are concerned: i.e., apart from whatever "more" may look/feel like, subjectively, we should feel as if more feels like more, rather than like less, and (more important) we should reliably act in conformity with that constraint (e.g., running more from a bigger threat, etc.)

6. Communication language, when we describe the shape of things to one another, can sometimes convey their objective shape faithfully, to an approximation [e.g., "a circle is a set of points equidistant from its center" or "she is the one with the hat"], and it can also sometimes bias its subjective shape, to a degree [e.g., "there is cynicism behind that smile", ”all El Greco subjects are distorted”]

7. Computation the fact that [just about] all objective shapes are informally describable in language and are even formally computable does not mean that cognition -- i.e., whatever goes on in our heads in between input and output -- is just computation: computation is symbol manipulation; symbol shapes are arbitrary (in relation to the shapes of the things the symbols are about), so the meanings of the symbols have to be grounded in something more than just further symbols and symbol-manipulations (this is the “symbol-grounding problem”)symbol-grounding problem

8. Corporality the fact that the subjective shape of things is determined in part by the objective shape of our bodies (e.g., one property of chairs is that they afford sittability-upon) means that some cognition is sensorimotor [and other] dynamics

9. Categorization to a great extent, cognition amounts to whatever is going on in our heads that gives us the capacity to know or learn how to do the kinds of things we do with the kinds of things we do it with: everything from sitting on them to manipulating, naming and describing them: to cognize is to categorize

10. Correction/Consequences to have and know a category, there has to be a right or wrong of the matter, there have to be consequences of miscategorizing that can serve as a reliable corrective to guide future correct categorization; there are behavioral continua too, where more/less is right, rather than all/none; but categorization concerns all/none -- i.e., categorical -- behavior; and where there is no possibility of error, no objective consequences of miscategorization, there are no categories, only arbitrary and incontrovertible subjectivity (Wittgenstein’s “private language”), hermeneutics, or free- floating metaphor (because everything resembles everything else, to an infinite degree, if freed of objective constraints and consequences)

11. Concreteness all categorization is abstraction: selectively hewing to some properties of the kind of thing categorized, ignoring others; all categories are hence abstract; types are always more abstract than their tokens; concreteness hence really refers only to how much sensorimotor experience is directly involved in the categorization: "red" is more concrete than "color" and "color" is more concrete than "property", but all categories, even those based purely on verbal hearsay, must be recursively grounded, bottom-up, in sensorimotor categories

12. Context/Confusability both categories and their invariant properties are context-dependent (and often also provisional and approximate): the properties that distinguish members from non-members depend on what proves to be reliably invariant in the range of variation the categorizer has sampled and from which he must, based on the consequences of miscategorization, successfully generalize to categorize future instances: "What is an X?" "Compared to what?”: category invariants are whatever features are sufficient to reliably resolve the confusability between members and nonmembers (i.e., there isn’t and never was anything wrong with the “classical theory” of categorization! whether the invariants prove to be conjunctive, disjunctive, monadic, polyadic, conditional, constructive, computational, deformational or statistical -- they must exist and be detectable if categorization is to succeed, and hence they must be “classical”)context-dependent

13. Compression in selectively detecting/attending to some properties and ignoring others, categorization results in a compression ["warping", "Whorfing"] of appearances in similarity space, making the subjective shapes of members of the same category resemble one another more, and resemble the shapes of members of other categories less; this is sometimes detectable as a psychophysical compression/separation of similarities, as in color and phoneme categorical perception [mostly innate], and even (more subtly) as a result of sensorimotor training or even verbal suggestion, in learned categorical perceptioncategorical perception

14. Cohabitation/Complementarity inside our heads there co-habit effects in both directions: the sensorimotor interactions between the objective shapes of our bodies and the objective shapes of things and kinds in the world constrain the shape of the subjective appearance of things and kinds, and verbal communication about shapes and kinds also influences the shape of their subjective appearance and the kinds of things we do with and to them

15. Collaboration/Cumulativity/Collectivity/Correctivity it is clear that not all of this can transpire within one head alone: both categories and their subjective appearance are shaped by interactions not only with the things in the world, but with the sayings and doings of other categorizers

References Harnad, Stevan (1982) Metaphor and Mental Duality, in Simon, T. and Scholes, R., Eds. Language, mind and brain, pages pp Hillsdale NJ: Erlbaum. Harnad, Stevan (1987) Category Induction and Representation, Chapter 18 of: Harnad, Stevan (ed.) (1987) Categorical Perception: The Groundwork of Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press. Harnad, Stevan (2001) Explaining the Mind: Problems, Problems. The Sciences 41:pp Harnad, Stevan (2003) Symbol-Grounding Problem, in Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. MacMillan: Nature Publishing Group. Harnad, Stevan (2003) Categorical Perception, in Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science. MacMillan: Nature Publishing Group. Harnad, S. (2005) To Cognize is to Categorize: Cognition is Categorization. To appear in Lefebvre C., & H. Cohen (Eds.) (2005) Handbook on Categorization. Elsevier