IN DEFENSE OF IMPERATIVE INFERENCE Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison Warsaw, 18 May 2012.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Syntactic Complexity and Cohesion
Advertisements

Anselm On the Existence of God. “Nor do I seek to understand so that I can believe, but rather I believe so that I can understand. For I believe this.
Hypotheticals: The If/Then Form Hypothetical arguments are usually more obvious than categorical ones. A hypothetical argument has an “if/then” pattern.
Reported Speech and Reporting verbs
S3 Useful Expressions.
DO CRY OVER SPILT MILK: POSSIBLY YOU CAN CHANGE THE PAST Peter B. M. Vranas Iowa State University Central APA, 28 April 2005.
1 Philosophy and Arguments. 2Outline 1 – Arguments: valid vs sound 2. Conditionals 3. Common Forms of Bad Arguments.
Today’s Outline Hume’s Problem of Induction Two Kinds of Skepticism
Descartes’ cosmological argument
Ambiguous contents? Arvid Båve, Higher seminar in Theoretical Philosophy, FLoV, Gothenburg University, 8 May 2013.
Chapter 1 Critical Thinking.
“Be kind, because everyone you meet is fighting a hard battle.” – Plato.
How to choose the right one.... Gerund or Infinitive ?
INFINITIVE VS. GERUND VERB PATTERNS 1.
Refutation, Part 1: Counterexamples & Reductio Kareem Khalifa Philosophy Department Middlebury College.
Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison
The Problem of Induction Reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’ by W. Salmon.
Albert Gatt LIN1180 – Semantics Lecture 10. Part 1 (from last week) Theories of presupposition: the semantics- pragmatics interface.
CAS LX 502 Semantics 1b. The Truth Ch. 1.
Pragmatics.
Pragmatics. Terminology Pragmatics: the study of intended meaning –often this meaning is “invisible” and consists of “shared assumptions” between speaker.
Today’s Topics n Review Logical Implication & Truth Table Tests for Validity n Truth Value Analysis n Short Form Validity Tests n Consistency and validity.
Pragmatics. Terminology Pragmatics: the study of intended meaning –often this meaning is “invisible” and consists of “shared assumptions” between speaker.
The Problem of Induction Reading: ‘The Problem of Induction’ by W. Salmon.
1 Arguments in Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy.
VERBS FOLLOWED BY GERUNDS OR INFINITIVES. Gerunds? Infinitives?  GERUND: A verb form that ends in –ing and used as a noun. (eating, running, flying)
Unit One: Parts of Speech
Topic: If you believe this is true, then copy this statement as your main idea. If you do not believe this is true, then rewrite it in a way that makes.
Reported Speech Dragana Filipović.
thinking hats Six of Prepared by Eman A. Al Abdullah ©
REPORTED SPEECH Unit 11 – English 12 Instructor: Nguyễn Ngọc Vũ
This is Diana. She had a meeting yesterday. We’ll use your plans, Diana.
Parts with Explanations
Princeton Review SAT Book PowerPoint #3 (Grade 9): Part III: Writing Section 3: Grammar Introduction (pages )
0 Validity & Invalidity (Exercises) December 23, 2005.
Gerund or Infinitive?. We select the –ing from.... To create a NOUN from a verb to express a general idea(Subject of the sentence in most cases): “Paying.
March 3, 2015Applied Discrete Mathematics Week 5: Mathematical Reasoning 1Arguments Just like a rule of inference, an argument consists of one or more.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Informal transactional letter
Inductive vs. Deductive Reasoning. Deductive Reasoning Starts with a general rule (a premise) which we know to be true. Then, from that rule, we make.
Equivalent Number Sentences, Equals Sign Means Equality __ + __ = __ - __ = Addition and Subtraction 22 Patterns and Algebra 19.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
0 Validity & Invalidity (Exercises) All dogs have two heads. 2. All tigers are dogs. ___________________________________ 3. All tigers have two.
Why Does Anything at all Exist? Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz - the principle of sufficient reason.
1 CS161 Introduction to Computer Science Topic #9.
Critical Thinking. Critical thinkers use reasons to back up their claims. What is a claim? ◦ A claim is a statement that is either true or false. It must.
Lesson 2: Common Misconceptions. Misconception 1 “Christianity must be proven scientifically; I’ll accept Christianity when you prove it with the scientific.
Prepared by: A. T. M. Monawer Success in EPT Listening & Speaking Reading Writing Listening &Speaking Reading Writing.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 5 The Ontological Argument By David Kelsey.
Presentation about pragmatic concepts Implicatures Presuppositions
Start-Up – Group Discussion With your group, discuss the following: Have you ever seen someone being made fun of or picked on for being different? Did.
What is gossip? When people spread rumors about another person it is called gossip. Gossip is talking about something that is not your problem.
Philosophy and Logic The Process of Correct Reasoning.
Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 1-b What is Philosophy? (Part 2) By David Kelsey.
Certainty and ErrorCertainty and Error One thing Russell seems right about is that we don’t need certainty in order to know something. In fact, even Descartes.
STEPS FOR PASSING THE AP RHETORICAL ESSAY 4 Components 4 Components 1) What is the author’s purpose? What does the author hope to achieve? 1) What is the.
DIRECT AND INDIRECT SPEECH. BY MISS WAREE ARDKAMON B.BD. 3.4 ID.NO
Relativism, Divine Command Theory, and Particularism A closer look at some prominent views of ethical theory.
NEW FOUNDATIONS FOR IMPERATIVE LOGIC III: A General Definition of Argument Validity Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison.
Speech Acts: What is a Speech Act?
Verbs followed by -ing or infinitive.
Wish Wish is used when the speaker wants reality to be different, to be exactly the opposite. Verb forms similar to those in conditional sentences are.
Pragmatics.
Overview of Group Presentations & Counterarguments
Modal Auxiliaries.
Philosophical Methods
INFORMATIVE ABOUTNESS
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
If there is any case in which true premises lead to a false conclusion, the argument is invalid. Therefore this argument is INVALID.
Presentation transcript:

IN DEFENSE OF IMPERATIVE INFERENCE Peter B. M. Vranas University of Wisconsin-Madison Warsaw, 18 May 2012

INTRODUCTION l Driving instructor tells you first “If there is a stop sign, stop” and then “There is a stop sign, so stop”. This is apparently an example of an imperative inference: Imperative premise: If there is a stop sign, stop Declarative premise: There is a stop sign Imperative conclusion: Stop l But several philosophers are skeptical about imperative inferences: Williams 1963, Wedeking 1970, Harrison 1991, Hansen 2008.

ARGUMENTS VS INFERENCES l An imperative argument is a pair consisting of (1) a nonempty set of imperative or declarative sentences (the premises) and (2) an imperative sentence (the conclusion). l An imperative inference is a process of reason- ing which starts by endorsing certain sentences and ends by endorsing an imperative sentence. l To endorse a sentence is to believe that it is [if declarative] true or [if imperative] binding (i.e., supported by a reason).

OVERVIEW Part 1 WILLIAMS’S ARGUMENT Part 2 ARE IMPERATIVE INFERENCES USELESS?

WILLIAMS’S ARGUMENT [W]e see an objection to construing the schema [ “ do x or do y; do not do x; so do y ” ] as anything that could be called a pattern of inference. For the first premiss presupposes permission to do x, and permission to do y; but the second premiss, ‘ do not do x ’, obviously has the force of denying permission to do x. Thus the speaker implicitly gives or admits something with his first utterance, which he withdraws with his second; and this can be construed only as the speaker changing his mind, or going back on what he first said. This destroys any resemblance of this sequence of commands to an inference; it is essential to the idea of an inference of q from a set of premises P that in reaching q, the speaker should not go back on or change his mind about any of the members of P  the form of an inference is ‘ given P, q ’ (Williams 1963: 32)

RECONSTRUCTING WILLIAMS’S ARGUMENT (W1) Utterances of imperative sentences have conflicting permissive presuppositions. So: (L1) No one can utter (nonequivalent) imper- ative sentences without changing her mind. So: (L2) No one can utter the premises and the conclusion of a (nontrivial) imperative argument without changing her mind. (W2) An inference can exist only if someone can utter its premises and its conclusion without changing her mind. So: (C) No imperative inference can exist.

OBJECTION 1 TO WILLIAMS: L1 IS FALSE l The objection: An examiner who says “Answer exactly two out of the three questions. But don’t answer both questions 1 and 3” need not change her mind. l Williams might respond: The examiner in effect utters a single sentence. l I reply: This response renders invalid the move from L1 to L2: anyone who expresses an argu- ment can be understood as uttering a single sentence (“do x or y, but don’t do x, so do y”).

OBJECTION 2 TO WILLIAMS: W2 IS FALSE l An examiner says: “Answer exactly two out of the three questions  any two questions, at your choice.” l A minute later, the examiner says: “I changed my mind. Don’t answer both questions 1 and 3. So answer either questions 1 and 2 or questions 2 and 3, at your choice.” l Although the examiner must have changed her mind, she can have inferred the last imperative sentence from the first two, so W2 is false.

OBJECTION 3 TO WILLIAMS: W1 IS FALSE l The imperative sentences “If the volcano erupts, flee” and “If you don’t flee, let it not be the case that the volcano erupts” are not equivalent but have the same permissive presuppositions: they forbid everything which entails that the volcano erupts and you don’t flee, and they permit everything else. l Similarly for “Don’t drink immoderately” and “If you drink, don’t drink immoderately”.

PART 2 Part 1 WILLIAMS’S ARGUMENT Part 2 ARE IMPERATIVE INFERENCES USELESS?

ARE IMPERATIVE INFERENCES INFREQUENT? l Recipes, instruction manuals, etc. suggest that imperative inferences are common. l Williams: No, the inferences are deontic. l But even if first-person imperative inferences are rare, second-person ones need not be. E.g.:  “Invite them either today or tomorrow. … Wait! Don’t invite them today: I forgot that we have guests. So invite them tomorrow.”  “Meet me at noon.” “I can meet you at noon only if I skip lunch.” “Then skip lunch.”

ARE IMPERATIVE INFERENCES DISPENSABLE? l The objection: Imperative inferences can always be replaced with declarative ones. l I reply: It does not follow that imperative inferences are useless. Analogy: geometric inferences can be replaced with algebraic ones. l Inference (1) is easier than (2)&(3): (1) Run (2) It rains (3) It rains and If it and you run you don’t run rains, run You run You don’t run