1. Points and lines 2. Convexity 3. Causality. ORDINARY LINES EXTRAORDINARY LINES?

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Axiomatic systems and Incidence Geometry
Advertisements

Week 21 Basic Set Theory A set is a collection of elements. Use capital letters, A, B, C to denotes sets and small letters a 1, a 2, … to denote the elements.
Canada Research Chairs In 2000, the Government of Canada created a permanent program to establish 2000 research professorships—Canada Research Chairs—in.
Bondy is 70!! November 17th, ORDINARY LINES EXTRAORDINARY LINES?
§18.1 Taxicab Geometry The student will learn about:
Notes Lesson 5.2 Congruent Triangles Target 4.1.
Junction Tree Algorithm Brookes Vision Reading Group.
Computational Geometry The art of finding algorithms for solving geometrical problems Literature: –M. De Berg et al: Computational Geometry, Springer,
Computational Geometry The art of finding algorithms for solving geometrical problems Literature: –M. De Berg et al: Computational Geometry, Springer,
1 Chapter 3 Set Theory Yen-Liang Chen Dept of Information Management National Central University.
Introductory Geometry CHAPTER 9. Chapter Introductory Geometry 9-1 Basic Notions 9-2 Polygons 9-3 More About Angles 9-4 Geometry in Three Dimensions 9.
One Olympiad Problem SDMC Gauss class Instructor: David Balmin
Menu Select the class required then click mouse key to view class.
Relations Chapter 9.
Unit 7: Probability Lesson 2 Tree Diagrams, fundamental counting principle, sample space lists and tables, permutation, combination, factorials.
§2.1 Introductory Material The student will learn about: and the beginning postulates to be used in this course. definitions of basic terms, 1.
Inequalities and Proof
Unit 2: Deductive Reasoning
Page 53, Chapter Summary: Concepts and Procedures After studying this CHAPTER, you should be able to Recognize points, lines, segments, rays, angles,
Ch. 1. Midpoint of a segment The point that divides the segment into two congruent segments. A B P 3 3.
Lesson 1.9 Probability Objective: Solve probability problems.
Krakow, Summer 2011 Comparability Graphs William T. Trotter
MAT 360 Lecture 5 Hilbert’s axioms - Betweenness.
Chapter 9. Chapter Summary Relations and Their Properties n-ary Relations and Their Applications (not currently included in overheads) Representing Relations.
Canada Research Chairs In 2000, the Government of Canada created a permanent program to establish 2000 research professorships—Canada Research Chairs—in.
Monday Sept Math 3621 Parallelism. Monday Sept Math 3622 Definition Two lines l and m are said to be parallel if there is no point P such.
Chapter 9. Section 9.1 Binary Relations Definition: A binary relation R from a set A to a set B is a subset R ⊆ A × B. Example: Let A = { 0, 1,2 } and.
1 ENM 503 Block 1 Algebraic Systems Lesson 2 – The Algebra of Sets The Essence of Sets What are they?
Congruence of Line Segments, Angles, and Triangles Eleanor Roosevelt High School Geometry Mr. Chin-Sung Lin.
PLANES, LINES AND POINTS A B A A B C A B C m A.
Counting CSC-2259 Discrete Structures Konstantin Busch - LSU1.
ENM 503 Block 1 Algebraic Systems Lesson 3 – Modeling with Sets Sets - Why do we care? The Application of Sets – a look ahead 1 Narrator: Charles Ebeling.
Probability: Terminology  Sample Space  Set of all possible outcomes of a random experiment.  Random Experiment  Any activity resulting in uncertain.
Honors Geometry Section 5.2 Use Perpendicular Bisectors.
ORDINARY LINES EXTRAORDINARY LINES? James Joseph Sylvester Prove that it is not possible to arrange any finite number of real points so that a right.
(CSC 102) Lecture 13 Discrete Structures. Previous Lectures Summary  Direct Proof  Indirect Proof  Proof by Contradiction  Proof by Contra positive.
Friday 8 Sept 2006Math 3621 Axiomatic Systems Also called Axiom Systems.
Problem Statement How do we represent relationship between two related elements ?
Chapter 9. Chapter Summary Relations and Their Properties n-ary Relations and Their Applications (not currently included in overheads) Representing Relations.
CONSENSUS THEOREM Choopan Rattanapoka.
Representing Relations Using Matrices A relation between finite sets can be represented using a zero-one matrix Suppose R is a relation from A = {a 1,
5.1 midsegments of triangles Geometry Mrs. Spitz Fall 2004.
5.4 Warm Up Warm Up Lesson Quiz Lesson Quiz Lesson Presentation Lesson Presentation Use Medians and Altitudes.
Chapter 9 Parallel Lines
Copyright (C) 2002 Houghton Mifflin Company. All rights reserved. 1 Understandable Statistics Seventh Edition By Brase and Brase Prepared by: Lynn Smith.
Counting Techniques Tree Diagram Multiplication Rule Permutations Combinations.
UNIT 3. OUTLINE: Sets and Subsets Set Operations the Laws of Set Theory Counting and Venn Diagrams. A First Word on Probability. The Axioms of Probability.
4-4 Triangle Congruence: SSS and SAS Warm Up Lesson Presentation
Congruence Based on Triangles Eleanor Roosevelt High School Geometry Mr. Chin-Sung Lin.
Warm – up 11/07 MAKE SURE YOU ARE SITTING IN YOUR NEW SEAT!! Start a new sheet for Ch. 5 warm-ups Answer the following –Come up with your own definition.
Points, Lines, and Planes. Even though there is no formal definition for these terms, there is general agreement of their meaning: A point is a dimensionless.
Set. Outline Universal Set Venn Diagram Operations on Sets.
ORDINARY LINES EXTRAORDINARY LINES?. ORDINARY LINES EXTRAORDINARY LINES?
1. For A(–4, 8) and B(5, 8), find the midpoint of AB.
Elementary Probability Theory
What is Probability? Quantification of uncertainty.
Y. Davis Geometry Notes Chapter 2.
Congruence of Line Segments, Angles, and Triangles
4.5 Using Congruent Triangles
Use the centroid of a triangle
6.3 Tests for Parallelograms
4.5 Using Congruent Triangles
6.3 Proving Quadrilaterals are Parallelograms
Vašek Chvátal Department of Computer Science and Software Engineering
9.2 Proving Quadrilaterals are Parallelograms
Sets A set is simply any collection of objects
1. For A(–4, 8) and B(5, 8), find the midpoint of AB.
Lesson 1.6 Incidence Theorems pp
G1 Point, Line, Plane Point, Line, Plane.
Presentation transcript:

1. Points and lines 2. Convexity 3. Causality

ORDINARY LINES EXTRAORDINARY LINES?

James Joseph Sylvester Prove that it is not possible to arrange any finite number of real points so that a right line through every two of them shall pass through a third, unless they all lie in the same right line. Educational Times, March 1893 Educational Times, May 1893 H.J. Woodall, A.R.C.S. A four-line solution … containing two distinct flaws

First proof: T.Gallai (1933) L.M. Kelly’s proof: starting line starting point new line new point near far

Be wise: Generalize! or What iceberg is the Sylvester-Gallai theorem a tip of?

A B C E D dist(A,B) = 1, dist(A,C) = 2, etc.

A B C E D B lies between A and C, C lies between B and D, etc.

a b x y z a b x y z

a b x y z A B C E D line AB consists of E,A,B,C line AC consists of A,B,C

a b x y z A B C E D line AB consists of E,A,B,C line AC consists of A,B,C One line can hide another!

a b x y z A B C E D line AB consists of E,A,B,C line AC consists of A,B,C no line consists of all points no line consists of two points

Definition: A pin is a set of three points such that one of these three points lies between the other two. Definition: A set is called affine if, and only if, with any two points of a pin, it also contains the third. Observation: Intersection of affine sets is affine. Definition: The affine hull of a set is the intersection of all its affine supersets. Definition: The closure line AB is the affine hull of the set consisting of the two points A and B. Remedy: An alternative definition of a line

A B C E D Every closure line here consists of all five points A,B,C,D,E Pins: {A,B,C}, {B,C,D}, {C,D,E}, {D,E,A}, {E,A,B}.

Conjecture (V.C. 1998) Theorem (Xiaomin Chen 2003) In every finite metric space, some closure line consists of two points or else some closure line consists of all the points.

Ordered geometry

Every set of n points in the plane determines at least n distinct lines unless all these n points lie on a single line. Corollary of Sylvester-Gallai (generalized by de Bruijn and Erdős in 1948)

Conjecture (Chen and C. 2006): In every metric space on n points, there are at least n distinct lines or else some line consists of all these n points. “Closure lines” in place of “lines” do not work here: For arbitrarily large n, there are metric spaces on n points, where there are precisely seven distinct closure lines and none of them consist of all the n points.

z x y Manhattan distance b a a b x y z becomes

With Manhattan betweenness, precisely seven closure lines

Conjecture (Chen and C. 2006): In every metric space on n points, there are at least n distinct lines or else some line consists of all these n points. Partial results include: (Xiaomin Chen, V.C.) (Ehsan Chiniforooshan, V.C.)

Abstract convexity A finite convexity space is a pair (X, C ) such that --- X is a finite set --- C is a family of subsets of X, which are called convex --- the empty set and the “ground set” X are convex --- intersection of any two convex sets is convex.

Interval convexity in partially ordered sets A set is called convex if, with every two points A and C, it includes all the points B for which A < B < C or C < B < A Hasse diagram Here, all the convex sets are: the empty set; the five singletons {1},{2}, {3},{4},{5}; {1,2}, {2,4}, {4,20}, {1,5}, {5,20}; {1,2,4}, {2,4,20}, {1,2,5}, {2,4,5}, {4,5,20}; {1,2,4,5}, {2,4,5,20}; the whole ground set {1,2,3,4,5}.

The convex hull of a set is the intersection of all its convex supersets. An extreme point of a convex set C is any point x of C such that C - {x} is convex.

Every compact convex set is the convex hull of its extreme points. Theorem (Minkowski 1911, Krein & Milman 1940): Definition: A convex geometry is a convexity space with the Minkowski-Krein-Milman property: Every convex set is the convex hull of its extreme points. Interval convexity in partially ordered sets is a convex geometry.

Monophonic convexity in graphs A set of vertices is called convex if, with every two vertices A and C, it includes all vertices of every chordless path from A to C. Set {A,B,C} is not convex: it does not include vertices D,E of the chordless path A-E-D-C E D C B A

Monophonic convexity in graphs Observation: A point in a convex set C is not extreme if and only if it has two nonadjacent neighbours in C

A graph is called triangulated if, and only if, It contains no chordless cycle of length at least four. Monophonic convexity in triangulated graphs is a convex geometry. Theorem (Farber & Jamison 1986):

interval convexity In partially ordered sets convex geometries monophonic convexity In triangulated graphs ???

Convexity defined by betweenness A set is called convex if, with every two points A and C, it includes all the points B that lie between A and C. Interval convexity in partially ordered sets A set is called convex if, with every two points A and C, it includes all the points B for which A < B < C or C < B < A. Monophonic convexity in graphs A set of vertices is called convex if, with every two vertices A and C, it includes all vertices B of every chordless path from A to C.

Convexity defined by betweenness A set is called convex if, with every two points A and C, it includes all the points B that lie between A and C. What do we mean by betweenness? Any ternary relation B such that

interval convexity In partially ordered sets convex geometries monophonic convexity In triangulated graphs ??? convex geometries defined by betweenness

convexity spaces defined by betweenness convex geometries The problem of recognizing betweennesses that define convex geometries is co NP -complete. Theorem (Laurent Beaudou, Ehsan Chiniforooshan, V.C. 2008): {(A,B,C),(C,B,A), (B,C,D),(D,C,B)} ?

interval convexity In partially ordered sets convex geometries monophonic convexity In triangulated graphs convex geometries defined by betweenness ???

A convex geometry is said to have Caratheodory number k if, and only if, every point of every convex set C belongs to the convex hull of some set of at most k extreme points of C Monophonic convexity in triangulated graphs is a convex geometry of Caratheodory number 2 Theorem (Farber & Jamison 1986): Interval convexity in partially ordered sets is a convex geometry of Caratheodory number 2

interval convexity In partially ordered sets convex geometries monophonic convexity In triangulated graphs convex geometries defined by betweenness ??? Caratheodory number 2

Theorem (C. 2008): A betweenness B defines a convex geometry of Caratheodory number 2 whenever it has the following property: If both (B,C,D) and (A,D,E) belong to B, then at least one of (B,C,A), (B,C,E), (A,C,E) belongs to B. A D E C B Points A,B,C,D,E may not be all distinct! C=A D E B etc.

interval convexity In partially ordered sets convex geometries monophonic convexity In triangulated graphs convex geometries defined by betweenness Caratheodory number 2 {(B,C,D),(D,C,B), (B,D,E),(E,D,B)} {B,C,D),(D,C,B),( A,D,E),(E,D,A), (A,C,E),(E,C,A)}

Hans Reichenbach doctoral thesis on philosophical aspects of probability theory one of the five people to attend Einstein’s first course on relativity founded the Berlin Circle (David Hilbert, Richard von Mises, …) with Rudolf Carnap, founded the journal Erkenntnis dissertation supervisor of Hillary Putnam and Wesley Salmon The Rise of Scientific Philosophy theory of tense (12 pages in Elements of Symbolic Logic)

found 922 works citing it University of California Press, 1956

TIME PROBABILITY CAUSALITY CAUSES COME BEFORE THEIR EFFECTS WATCH THIS SPACE

Finite probability spaces Six outcomes 2 events 6

Prob(A)=1/3Prob(B)=1/2 Prob(C)=1/3 Conditional probability of event E given event F: Prob(E|F) = Prob(E&F) / Prob(F) A and C are positively correlated A and B are independent Prob(A|B)= 1/3, Prob(B|A)= 1/2 Prob(A|C)= 1/2, Prob(B|C)= 0, Prob(C|B)= 0 B and C are negatively correlated Prob(C|A)= 1/2

TIME PROBABILITY CAUSALITY CAUSES COME BEFORE THEIR EFFECTS CAUSES ARE POSITIVELY CORRELATED WITH THEIR EFFECTS

Definition (Reichenbach, p. 190): Event B is causally between events A and C if, and only if 1 > P(C|B) > P(C|A) > P(C) > 0, 1 > P(A|B) > P(A|C) > P(A) > 0, P(C | A&B) = P(C|B). Equation P(C | A&B) = P(C|B) can be written as P(A&C | B) = P(A|B) P(C|B). B screens off A from C Inequality P(C|A) > P(C) means that A and C are positively correlated

and a certain directed graph G( B ) contains no directed cycles. Question: When is a ternary relation B isomorphic to a causal betweenness? Answer (Baoyindureng Wu and V.C. 2009): If and only if it is a betweenness

Definition of G( B ) Example: B consists of (C,A,B), (B,A,C), (D,B,C), (C,B,D), (A,C,D), (D,C,A), (B,D,A), (A,D,B). Its vertices are all sets of two events. Each pair (X,Y,Z), (Z,Y,X) of triples in B gives rise to a pair of directed edges: one from {X,Y} to {X,Z} and the other from {Y,Z} to {X,Z}. {A,B} {A,D} {B,D} {A,C} {B,C} {C,D} Abstract causal betweennesses can be recognized in polynomial time

Definition (Reichenbach, p. 159): Events A,B,C constitute a conjunctive fork if, and only if B and A are positively correlated, B and C are positively correlated, B screens off A from C, the complement of B screens off A from C Question: When is a ternary relation B isomorphic to the conjunctive fork betweenness? Here, B can be a common cause of A and C or a common effect of A and C

The End

TIME CAUSALITY --- WARNING --- If an event B is causally between events A and C, then it does not necessarily occur between A and C: it can occur before both A and C and it can occur after both A and C. B is causally between A and C B occurs between A and C

Definition A ternary relation B on a set X is called totally orderable if, and only if, there is a mapping t from X into a totally ordered set such that, for each (A,B,C) in B, either t (A)< t (B)< t(C) or t(C)< t(B)< t(A). How about betweennesses B such that (A,B,C) is in B if and only if B is between A and C both causally and in time?

Justification: If B is totally orderable, then G( B ) contains no directed cycle. Fact: Every totally orderable betweenness is causal. | t (A)– t (B) | < | t(A)–t(C) | {A,B} {A,C} Opatrny (1979): The problem of recognizing totally orderable ternary relations is NP -complete. The problem of recognizing totally orderable abstract causal betwennesses is NP -complete.

convex geometries defined by betweenness convexity spaces with Caratheodory number 2 Work in progress: Laurent Beaudou, Ehsan Chiniforooshan, V.C. How difficult is the problem of recognizing betweennesses that define convex geometries of Caratheodory number 2?