Decision making Under Uncertainty

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Choices Involving Risk
Advertisements

Economics of Information (ECON3016)
Utility Theory.
States of the World In this section we introduce the notion that in the future the outcome in the world is not certain. Plus we introduce some related.
Managerial Decision Modeling with Spreadsheets
1 Demand for Health Insurance. 2 Which Investment will you pick Expected Value $2600 Choice 2 $5000 -$ Choice 1 $5000 $
Decision analysis: part 2
Choices Involving Risk
Risk Attitude Dr. Yan Liu
Part 3 Probabilistic Decision Models
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2011 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved.
Decision Analysis Chapter 3
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2013 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty.
Decision Tree Analysis. Decision Analysis Managers often must make decisions in environments that are fraught with uncertainty. Some Examples –A manufacturer.
Introduction to Probability Experiments Counting Rules Combinations Permutations Assigning Probabilities.
Introduction to Probability
Introduction to Probability Uncertainty, Probability, Tree Diagrams, Combinations and Permutations Chapter 4 BA 201.
Chapter 14 Decision Making
1 Utility Theory. 2 Option 1: bet that pays $5,000,000 if a coin flipped comes up tails you get $0 if the coin comes up heads. Option 2: get $2,000,000.
Risk a situation in which there is a probability that an event will occur. People tend to prefer greater certainty and less risk.
Lecture 4 on Individual Optimization Risk Aversion
Part 3 Uncertainty and Strategy © 2006 Thomson Learning/South-Western.
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior
Uncertain Outcomes Here we study projects that have uncertain outcomes and we view various ways people may deal with the uncertain situations.
Expected Value.  In gambling on an uncertain future, knowing the odds is only part of the story!  Example: I flip a fair coin. If it lands HEADS, you.
Decision Analysis Chapter 3
Decision Analysis Chapter 3
Copyright © 2005 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin Managerial Economics Thomas Maurice eighth edition Chapter 15.
© 2016 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part, except for use as permitted in a license.
Chapter 16 Uncertainty We must believe in luck. For how else can we explain the success of those we don’t like? Jean Cocteau.
Decision Analysis (cont)
Econ 3790: Business and Economics Statistics Instructor: Yogesh Uppal
Chapter 15 Risk Analysis. Frequency definition of probability zGiven a situation in which a number of possible outcomes might occur, the probability of.
Chapter 3 Arbitrage and Financial Decision Making
Decision Making Under Uncertainty and Risk 1 By Isuru Manawadu B.Sc in Accounting Sp. (USJP), ACA, AFM
Chapter 5 Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior. ©2005 Pearson Education, Inc.Chapter 52 Q: Value of Stock Investment in offshore drilling exploration: Two.
Stephen G. CECCHETTI Kermit L. SCHOENHOLTZ Understanding Risk Copyright © 2011 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin.
1 1 Slide © 2016 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. Probability is a numerical measure of the likelihood Probability is a numerical measure of the.
Chapter 5 Choice Under Uncertainty. Chapter 5Slide 2 Topics to be Discussed Describing Risk Preferences Toward Risk Reducing Risk The Demand for Risky.
Introduction to Probability
1 Risk and Information Chapter Chapter Fifteen Overview 1.Introduction: Amazon.com 2.Describing Risky Outcome – Basic Tools Lotteries and Probabilities.
Choice under uncertainty Assistant professor Bojan Georgievski PhD 1.
1 Chapter 4 – Probability An Introduction. 2 Chapter Outline – Part 1  Experiments, Counting Rules, and Assigning Probabilities  Events and Their Probability.
Decision theory under uncertainty
© 2005 Pearson Education Canada Inc Chapter 17 Choice Making Under Uncertainty.
Decision Theory McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2012 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved.
Models for Strategic Marketing Decision Making. Market Entry Decisions To enter first or to wait Sources of First-Mover Advantages –Technological leadership.
Capital Budgeting and Financial Planning Course Instructor: M.Jibran Sheikh.
Amity School Of Business Operations Research OPERATIONS RESEARCH.
Examples and Categories of Business Risks 1. Macro ( + Political ) econ growth, interest rates inflation, exchange rates 2. Micro (Demand & Cost) e.g.
Chapter Seventeen Uncertainty. © 2009 Pearson Addison-Wesley. All rights reserved Topics  Degree of Risk.  Decision Making Under Uncertainty.
Fundamentals of Decision Theory Chapter 16 Mausam (Based on slides of someone from NPS, Maria Fasli)
BUAD306 Chapter 5S – Decision Theory. Why DM is Important The act of selecting a preferred course of action among alternatives A KEY responsibility of.
BIA 2610 – Statistical Methods
QUANTITATIVE TECHNIQUES
1 Chapter 8 Revising Judgments in the Light of New Information.
© 2015 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. Chapter 16 Decision Analysis.
Microeconomics Course E John Hey. Chapter 26 Because we are all enjoying risk so much, I have decided not to cover Chapter 26 (on the labour market)
1 Systems Analysis Methods Dr. Jerrell T. Stracener, SAE Fellow SMU EMIS 5300/7300 NTU SY-521-N NTU SY-521-N SMU EMIS 5300/7300 Utility Theory Applications.
Money and Banking Lecture 11. Review of the Previous Lecture Application of Present Value Concept Internal Rate of Return Bond Pricing Real Vs Nominal.
The Law of Averages. What does the law of average say? We know that, from the definition of probability, in the long run the frequency of some event will.
Chapter 5 Understanding Risk
Decisions under uncertainty and risk
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Supplement: Decision Making
Chapter Five Understanding Risk.
Choices Involving Risk
Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Presentation transcript:

Decision making Under Uncertainty Uncertainty, Probability, and Expected Value Decision Trees Sequential Decisions Risk Aversion Expected utility Expected Utility and Risk Aversion

Uncertainty In business we are forced to make decisions involving risk—that is, where the consequences of any action we take is uncertain due to unforeseeable events. Where do we begin?

Analyzing the Problem—Preliminary Steps Listing the available alternatives, not only for direct action but also for gathering information on which to base later action; Listing the outcomes that can possibly occur (these depend on chance events as well as on the decision maker’s own actions); Evaluating the chances that any uncertain outcome will occur; and Deciding how well the decision maker likes each outcome.

Experimental Outcomes These are processes that generate well-defined outcomes Experiments Experiment Experimental Outcomes Toss a coin Head, tail Select a part for inspection Defective, nondefective Conduct a sales call Purchase, no purchase Roll a die 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 Play a football game Win, lose, tie

Probability is a numerical measure of the likelihood of an event occurring 1.0 0.5 Probability: The occurrence of the event is just as likely as it is unlikely

When an experiment is repeatable, then a probability is a long-run frequency. This if we flip a coin 1,000 times, the frequency of “heads” will be very close to 0.5

Unfortunately, business experiments are rarely repeatable Unfortunately, business experiments are rarely repeatable. We cannot introduce a new product 1,000 times and measure the frequency with which it succeeds—can we?

Objective versus Subjective Probabilities Repeatable experiments (tossing a die, flipping a coin) generate objective probabilities. Non-repeatable experiments necessarily involve assigning hypothetical or subjective probabilities to particular outcomes.

I estimate my odds of becoming a country music star at two to one. According to the subjective view, the probability of an outcome represents the decision maker’s degree of belief that the outcome will occur. I estimate my odds of becoming a country music star at two to one.

(Subjective) Probability Distribution for a New Product Launch The following gives the subjective view of a manager concerning the probability distribution for the first year’s outcome of a new product launch. Outcome Sales Revenue Probability Complete success $10,000,000 0.1 Promising 7,000,000 0.3 Mixed response 3,000,000 0.2 Failure 1,000,000 0.4

Computing Expected Value or E(v) Suppose the decision maker faces a risky prospect than has n possible monetary outcomes, v1, v2, . . . , vn, predicted to occur with probabilities p1, p2, . . . , pn. Then the (monetary) expected value is found by: E(v) for the new product launch is given by:

The Wildcatters Drilling Problem Payoffs measured in 1,000s Wet $600 0.4 Drill 120 Dry 120 -$200 0.6 Do not drill $0

The Expected Value Criterion I will select the course of action with the highest expected value. Note that the expected value of “not drilling” is equal to zero. Expected value of the drilling option:

Good Decision, Bad Outcome OK, the well turned out to be dry. But that does not mean the decision to drill was a bad one. When confronted with uncertainty, we must distinguish between bad decisions and bad outcomes.

Bushier Decision Tree Our next decision tree will take into account three (3) risks affecting the profits derived from drilling: The cost of drilling—which depends on the depth at which oil is found (or not found); The amount of oil discovered; and The price of oil. In this case we should apply the expected value criterion in stages.

“Bushier” Drilling Decision (19 outcomes)

Finding Expected Value With Multiple Risks To find the wildcatter’s expected value from drilling, we start at the tips of the decision tree and “average backwards.”

Expected Profit Drilling at 3,000 Feet At node D (drilling at 3,000 feet, 5,000 barrels discovered), expected profit is equal to: (0.2)(700) + (0.5)(0.3)(150)=$360 thousand But we might have discovered 8,000 barrels or 16,000 barrels by drilling at 3,000 feet. Thus at node E expected profit is equal to $636 thousand and at node F $1,372 thousand. Thus the expected profit of drilling at 3,000 feet is calculated by: (0.15)(360) + (0.55)(636) + (0.3)(1,372) = $815.4 thousand

Expected Value from Drilling Now we just multiply the expected value of each outcome (find oil at 3,000 feet, find oil at 5,000 feet, and not find oil) by its probability and sum together. Thus we have: (0.13)(815.4) + (0.21)(353.8) + (0.66)(-400) = -$83.7 thousand Would you drill?

Sequential Decisions Most important business problems require a sequence of key decisions over time. Building a new petrochemical facility is obviously a huge decision. Whether that decision turns out to be “good” or “bad” will partly depend on future decisions concerning product lines, pricing, or other variables.

R & D Decision A pharmaceutical firm must choose between 2 R&D approaches—biochemical and biogenetic.

An R&D Decision (all figures expressed in present values) R&D Choice Investment Outcomes Profit (Minus R&D) Probability Biochemical $10 million Large success Small Success $90 million $50 million 0.7 0.3 Biogenetic $20 million Success Failure $200 million 0 million 0.2 0.8 Let G denote the biogenetic approach and C is the biochemical approach. The expected profit (π) of the 2 approaches is calculated as follows:

Don’t’ Stop Now! We would select the biochemical option based on the expected value criterion. However, our analysis should not stop here. We might hedge our bets by doing both R&D programs simultaneously. Depending on the results, we can decide which method to commercialize

Simultaneous R&D Investments Figure 8.3 Note: failure for biochemical means “small success.”

Notes on Figure 8.3 4 possible outcomes Probability of “Both programs succeed is equal to the probability that biochemical will succeed (0.7) times the probability that biogenetic will succeed (0.2). That is: PBS = (0.7)(0.2)= 0.14 Note that the probabilities of the 4 outcomes must sum to 1. Biogenetic should be selected for commercialization if it is successful (as it is on the upper two branches of the tree) since it has the higher payoff. Thus the payoff would be equal to $200 million minus the $30 million spent for R&D, or $170 million “Average backwards” to find the expected value of simultaneous development.

Computing Expected Value in the Simultaneous Case 1 The expected profit from simultaneous R&D development exceeds the expected payoff from pursuing biochemical alone ($72.4 million compared to $68 million) 1 Note the typographical errors in the equation on p. 321 of Samuelson and Marks, 5th edition.

Sequential Development There is another strategy. We can pursue the R&D methods sequentially. But which approach should we do first?

Sequential R&D: Biochemical First Figure 8.4

Notes on Figure 8.4 One would intuitively think that, if biochemical is successful you would go ahead and commercialize it. This turns out not to be the case. You get a higher expected payoff by continuing on to develop biogenetic. Where does the $82 come from? If biogenetic success in the 2nd step, you would commercialize it. If it fails, you commercialize biochemical, but now the payoff is $60 million instead of $80 since you spend an additional $20 million to develop biochemical. Thus if biochemical succeeds the expected value is: E(v) = (0.2)(170)+(0.8)(60) = $82 million. Note that if biochemical fails, the firm would best option is to pursue biogenetic. The firm’s expect profit at the outset is equal to: E(v) = (0.7)(82) + (0.3)(50) = $72.4 million

Sequential R&D: Biogenetic First Figure 8.5

Why does the “biogenetic first” strategy have a higher expected profit ($74.4 million compared to $72.4 million for “biochemical first”)? If biogenetic is successful in the first stage, we will go ahead and commercialize it—thereby saving $10 million in R&D for biochemical

Summary of Pharmaceutical Company’s R&D Options

Risk Aversion When it comes to risks that are large relative to financial resources, firms and individuals tend to adopt a conservative attitude. That is, they are not “risk-neutral”—which is what the expected value criterion assumes.

A Coin Gamble If you refuse the bet, you are not risk neutral! You have 2 choices: You can have $60, no questions asked. Or, you can accept the following gamble: A fair coins is tossed. Heads: you win $400. Tails: You lose $200 dollars. OK, what is your choice? Question: Which choice has the highest expected value? For the “gamble” choice: If you refuse the bet, you are not risk neutral!

The Certainty Equivalent (CE) The CE is the amount of money for certain that makes the individual exactly indifferent to the risky prospect. Example: Suppose that a guaranteed $25 would make you indifferent to the bet with an expected value of $100. Thus your CE = $25. If CE < E(v), then the individual is risk averse.

The CE and the Degree of Risk Aversion Principle: The higher the discount factor, the higher the degree of risk aversion. The discount factor for risk is the difference between the expected value of the gamble and the CE. My CE is $75. Thus my discount factor is equal to: $100 - $75 = $25. If your CE is $25, then your discount factor is $75.

The Demand For Insurance Insurance entails the transfer (for a price) of risk from t risk averse individuals or films to risk neutral insurance companies. Risk pooling allows insurance companies to be risk neutral. An insurance company does not know which homes will catch fire. It can predict how many homes out of 10,000 will catch fire, however.

Expected Utility This is a similar decision making process to expected utility—with one big difference. In contrast to the risk neutral manager, who averages monetary values at each step, the risk averse manager averages expected utilities associated with monetary values.

A Risk Averse Wildcatter Figure 8-7

Expected Utility: How It Works The decision maker first attaches a utility value to each possible monetary outcome. The worst monetary outcome is assigned a value of zero; the best monetary outcome must have a greater than zero—but that is the only requirement. Our wildcatter assigns a value of 0 to the worst outcome (-$200) and a value of 100 to the best outcome ($600). Thus the expected utility of drilling is given by:

Expected Utility: How It Works-Continued Now I must compare the expected utility of drilling with the expected utility of not drilling—that is U(0). How do I find that? Principle: To find U(0), compare $0 for certain with a gamble offering $600 thousand (with probability p) and -$200 thousand (with probability 1 – p). The wildcatter finds his preference for $0 by finding the probability p that leaves him indifferent to the options of $0 and the gamble (drilling).

Should the wildcatter drill? I find my preference for $0 by finding the probability p that leaves me indifferent to the options of $0 and the gamble (drilling). Say I have determined it is 0.5. Then the expected utility of the 50-50 gamble is equal to: Expected utility rule: The decision maker should choose the course of action that maximizes his or her expected utility. Should the wildcatter drill?

A More Complicated Drilling Prospect Figure 8.8 Now drilling has 4 possible outcome with probabilities listed. Let’s compare expected value and expected utility of drilling: Thus expected utility is maximized by drilling

Figure 8.9

Notes on Figure 8-9 The utility curve gives us the “certainty equivalent” of a bet with a given expected value. The CE of a bet with an expected value of $200 thousand is $0. That is, the certainty of obtaining $0 and a bet with an expected value of $200 thousand have the same expected utility (50). A concave utility curve means the decision maker is risk averse—that is, there is a discount due to risk equal to E(v) – CE ($200 thousand in the example above). A risk-neutral decision maker is guided by expected value—there id no discount for risk so that the utility curve is linear. A risk lover has a convex utility curve.

Positive discount for risk E(v) – CE > 0 Zero discount for risk E(v) – CE = 0 Negative discount for risk E(v) – CE < 0

Nonmonetary Examples: An R&D Race A firm must decide between two R&D methods—A or B (it cannot do both). Methods A and B entail the same cost and have the dame projected profitability—the only source of uncertainty concerns each method’s time until completion. Subjective utilities are attached to various completion times—e.g., the utility of a 12 month completion time is 100. Management is solely interested in meeting an 18 week deadline.

R&D Race Figure 8.11 Notice that Method B gives the highest expected utility even though the expected completion time for this method is higher. Method B has a greater chance of beating the 18 week deadline.

A Surgical Decision A 60-year old woman suffers from cardiovascular disease. A heart bypass operation can restore her to near-perfect health, but carries the risk of death—an estimated 4 percent (p = 0.04) for someone with her health history. Should she undergo the operation? We assume that cost is not a factor—the woman is covered by health insurance.

A Medical Decision Figure 8-12 Note that the patient names the probability of success (p) that will leave her indifferent to the two course of action. The patient is indifferent between her current health status and a 12 percent chance of death.

Since the probability of success for this operation (0 Since the probability of success for this operation (0.96) exceeds the patient’s required degree of safety (0.88), the operation is a go. Note also that the expected utility of the surgery exceeds the utility of her current health status. That is, the expected utility of surgery is given by: Whereas the utility of the patients current health status is 88.