Non-selfish preferences. The Standard Model 1.Nature Self-interest and self-regarding preferences 2.Anomalies  Tipping waiters  Giving to charity.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
BEHAVIORAL RESEARCH IN MANAGERIAL ACCOUNTING RANJANI KRISHNAN HARVARD BUSINESS SCHOOL & MICHIGAN STATE UNIVERSITY 2008.
Advertisements

Chapter 12: Oligopoly and Monopolistic Competition
Ultimatum Game Two players bargain (anonymously) to divide a fixed amount between them. P1 (proposer) offers a division of the “pie” P2 (responder) decides.
1 On the Methodology of Inequity Aversion Theory.
Brandts and Solà: Reference Points and Negative Reciprocity in Simple Sequential Games Economics 328 Spring 2005.
Cheap talk and cooperation in Stackelberg games Raimo P. Hämäläinen Ilkka Leppänen Systems Analysis Laboratory Aalto University.
Game Theory Eduardo Costa. Contents What is game theory? Representation of games Types of games Applications of game theory Interesting Examples.
Fehr and Falk Wage Rigidity in a Competitive Incomplete Contract Market Economics 328 Spring 2005.
Game Theory The study of rational behavior among interdependent agents Agents have a common interest to make the pie as large as possible, but Agents have.
Econ 2610: Principles of Microeconomics Yogesh Uppal
Non-selfish preferences
Basic Concepts in Economics: Theory of Demand and Supply
ELM Part 2- Economic models Manuela Samek
Chapter 12: Oligopoly and Monopolistic Competition.
Developing Principles in Bargaining. Motivation Consider a purely distributive bargaining situation where impasse is costly to both sides How should we.
APEC 8205: Applied Game Theory Fall 2007
Motivations and observed behaviour: Evidence from ultimatum bargaining experiment Elena Tougareva Laboratory of Social and Economic Psychology, Institute.
TOPIC 6 REPEATED GAMES The same players play the same game G period after period. Before playing in one period they perfectly observe the actions chosen.
Playing Unfair: Punishment in Bargaining and Negotiations Deborah Kay Elms IPES Conference November 14, 2008.
Basic Tools of Finance Finance is the field that studies how people make decisions regarding the allocation of resources over time and the handling of.
Two-Stage Games APEC 8205: Applied Game Theory Fall 2007.
The Theory of Aggregate Supply Classical Model. Learning Objectives Understand the determinants of output. Understand how output is distributed. Learn.
AN INTRODUCTION TO PORTFOLIO MANAGEMENT
Introduction: Thinking Like an Economist 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 12 The Logic of Individual Choice: The Foundation of Supply and Demand The theory of economics.
PRINCIPLES OF MACROECONOMICS
Advanced Corporate Finance FINA 7330 Capital Structure Issues and Financing Fall, 2006.
Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics 11 Game Theory, Strategic Decision Making, and Behavioral Economics All men can see the.
Proposal Selection Form Proposer Identification Code __________________ Circle a proposal: 19/1 18/2 17/3 16/4 15/5 14/6 13/7 12/8 11/9 10/10 9/11 8/12.
1 Frank & Bernanke 3 rd edition, 2007 Ch. 11: Ch. 11: Strategic Choice in Oligopoly, Monopolistic Competition, and Everyday Life.
Coalition Formation between Self-Interested Heterogeneous Actors Arlette van Wissen Bart Kamphorst Virginia DignumKobi Gal.
Redistribution, Efficiency, Fairness 1. Consider a Possibility Frontier Most government action we have thought about is getting you from inside the frontier.
Chapter 9 - Prosocial Behavior
1 Chapter 11 Oligopoly. 2 Define market structures Number of sellers Product differentiation Barrier to entry.
Course Behavioral Economics Alessandro InnocentiAlessandro Innocenti Academic year Lecture 14 Fairness LECTURE 14 FAIRNESS Aim: To analyze the.
May 27, 2003 Vítězslav Babický Attitudes to risk and fairness: how they are related and how they evolved - theoretical and experimental studies.
Reputational advantages and disadvantages of punishment toward norm-violators Yutaka Horita Toshio Yamagishi Hokkaido University 13th international conference.
ECONOMIC FOUNDATIONS OF FINANCE BASIC ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF CAPITAL.
Lecture 2 Economic Actors and Organizations: Motivation and Behavior.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2008 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. GAME THEORY, STRATEGIC DECISION MAKING, AND BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS.
Perfect competition, with an infinite number of firms, and monopoly, with a single firm, are polar opposites. Monopolistic competition and oligopoly.
Negotiation 101 Fairness and the importance of looking ahead.
Motivation This experiment was a public good experiment to see if groups contribute differently than individuals.  intermediate social structure This.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright  2006 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. THE LOGIC OF INDIVIDUAL CHOICE: THE FOUNDATION OF DEMAND AND.
Dr. Asad Zaman Presentation at PIDE, 21 st April 2014 Based on “Empirical Evidence Against Utility Theory: A Survey of the Literature”
1 University of Auckland Winter Week Lectures Second Lecture 3 July 2007 Associate Professor Ananish Chaudhuri Department of Economics University of Auckland.
Decision theory under uncertainty
The Economic Framework For our purposes two basic sets of agents: –Consumers –Firms Interact through markets Faced with some economic environment or market.
Explicit versus Implicit Contracts for Dividing the Benefits of Cooperation Marco Casari and Timothy Cason Purdue University.
Testing theories of fairness— Intentions matter Armin Falk, Ernst Fehr, Urs Fischbacher February 26, 2015.
Intermediate Microeconomics Game Theory and Oligopoly.
The Logic of Individual Choice: The Foundation of Supply and Demand 10 The Logic of Individual Choice: The Foundation of Supply and Demand The theory of.
CULTURAL STEREOTYPES AND NORM OF RECIPROCITY 11/03/
MICROECONOMICS Chapter 5 Efficiency and Equity
Motivation Through Equity, Expectancy, & Goal Setting
Chapter 6 Extensive Form Games With Perfect Information (Illustrations)
Chapter 9 Prosocial Behavior: Doing What’s Best for Others © 2014 Wadsworth Cengage Learning Oskar Schindler’s grave. The Hebrew inscription reads: “A.
Yu-Hsuan Lin Catholic University of Korea, Korea University of York, U.K. 5 th Congress of EAAERE, Taipei, 06 th – 07 th August 2015.
Chapter 18 Social Economics.
Management support systems II
Proposal Selection Form
Behavioral economics Chapter 30
Eco 3311 Lecture 12 One Period Closed Economy Model - Equilibrium
Signaling unobservable quality choice through price and advertising: The case with competing firms Speaker: Wu Fulan 3rd August,2009.
Chapter 12: Oligopoly and Monopolistic Competition
THE ECONOMY: THE CORE PROJECT
Unit 4 SOCIAL INTERACTIONS.
Gönül Doğan, Marcel van Assen, Jan Potters Tilburg University
Auctions and Bargaining
Behavioral economics Chapter 30
TRUST, FEAR, RECIPROCITY, AND ALTRUISM: Theory and Experiment
Presentation transcript:

Non-selfish preferences

The Standard Model 1.Nature Self-interest and self-regarding preferences 2.Anomalies  Tipping waiters  Giving to charity  Voting  Completing tax returns honestly  Voluntary unpaid work  etc.

Limited Self Interest In basic neo-classical model decision makers perfectly maximize their own payoff. How do we incorporate interpersonal values: prestige, fairness, justice? – people care about how they are perceived by others – people are willing to sacrifice some of their own money so others can have more

Limited Self Interest: Altruism Altruism – regard for others’ well being Person 1’s consumption Person 2’s consumption Utility max. point for selfish person U1U1 U2U2 Utility max. point for altruistic person

Limited Self Interest: Fairness... Low Accept Even Reject 9, 10, 05, 50, What is the predicted outcome for this game? Player 1 chooses Low and Player 2 Accepts. Standard Ultimatum Game

Limited Self Interest: Fairness... Low Accept Even Reject 1, -70, 05, 50, Symmetric Fairness Now Player 1 offers an even amount, which is accepted.

Limited Self Interest: Fairness... Low Accept Even Reject 9, -70, 05, 50, Envy Again Player 1 offers an even amount, which is accepted.

Limited Self Interest: Fairness How do you decide what motivates player 1 to offer an even amount? – Player 1 offers an even amount out of fairness. – Player 1 offers an even amount because he fears Player 2 will reject uneven offers due to envy. Dictator Game – Like the Ultimatum Game but no second stage. Player 1 simply gets to decide how to split the money.

Limited Self Interest: Fairness Low Even 9, 15, 5 1, -7 9, -7 The number of low offers is more than in the Ultimatum Game, but there are still a number of even offers.

Limited Self Interest: Fairness Are there other motives for even splits that you can think of? – Reciprocity – reward good behavior and punish bad. (Rabin) – People care that they are perceived as being fair. Market vs. Personal Dealings – Your interpersonal values will differ depending on who you deal with: friends or strangers. – They also may depend on whether a transaction is commercial or personal.

Nature of Social Preferences  Social preferences and fairness – 'as if they value the payoff of relevant reference agents positively or negatively.’ (Fehr & Fischbacher, 2005)  Beliefs and intentions of others  Fairness: distribution of costs and benefits  Dual entitlement: reference transactions; outcomes  Strong reciprocity

Fairness Games and the Standard Model  Ultimatum game - 60% to 80% of offers between 0.4 and 0.5, rarely below 0.2.  Dictator games – Cherry et al. (2002): Baseline situation 17% zero offers; 80% with 'earned' wealth  Trust games – 30-40% purely selfish; also more complex (trust ↔ reciprocity)  Prisoner’s dilemma games – 50% cooperate even in one-shot games  Public goods games – effect of punishment

Factors Affecting SPs  Setting - repetition and learning, stakes, anonymity, communication, entitlement, competition, available information, number of players, intentions,...  Descriptive – framing effects  Demographic - gender, age, academic major, culture, and social distance  Social norms: Fehr & Gächter (2000) 1)behavioral regularities 2)socially shared belief regarding how one ought to behave 3)enforcement by informal social sanctions (but: what triggers a particular norm?)

Ultimatum Game Player 1 has a fixed amount of money (say $10) and must offer some fraction to Player 2 (from $0 and $10). If Player 2 accepts, they split the money as proposed. If Player 2 rejects, no one gets any money. Empirically, responders will reject offers below $2, but such low offers would be rare. Offers will fall in the $3–$5 range and will typically be accepted.

Ultimatum Game, cont.

Strictly speaking, a game is defined in terms of utilities, not dollars. So let us suppose u(x)=x. If so, the only subgame-perfect equilibrium is the one in which Player 2 accepts all offers and Player 1 offers nothing.

Dictator Game Similar to the ultimatum game except Player 2 does not have the opportunity to reject. Empirically, dictators offer about % of their money. Assuming u(x)=x, once again, the only subgame-perfect equilibrium is where the “dictator” offers nothing.

Social Preferences Social preferences reflect other people’s attainment y as well as the agent’s own x. If P derives positive utility from Q’s attainment, P is said to have altruistic preferences. If P derives negative utility from Q’s attainment, P is said to have envious preferences.

Social Preferences, cont. A person with Rawlsian preferences (or preferences for fairness) tries to maximize the minimum utility associated with the allocation. A person who wishes to minimize the difference between the best and the worst off is said to have inequality averse preferences. (Fehr and Schnidt, Bolton, et. Al.) Individuals who want to maximize the total amount of utility have utilitarian preferences.

Example Find all Nash equilibria in pure strategies when played by: a)egoists with u(x,y)=√x; b)utilitarians with u(x,y)=√x+√y; c)enviers with u(x,y)=√x-√y; d)Rawlsians with u(x,y)=min(√x,√y). This is one of your homework problems.

Intentions and Reciprocity Whether a responder will accept depends not just on the proposed allocation (e.g., an split), but on the options available to the proposer. This suggests that responders base their decisions in part on perceived intentions of the proposer. – Respondents exhibit positive reciprocity when they reward others with good intentions. – Respondents exhibit negative reciprocity when they punish players with bad intentions. ©Erik Angner

Empirical Evidence Neuroscientific studies – useful for estimating emotions when people unaware/unwilling to admit (reverse inference from relevant brain areas) Show:  Pleasure of cooperation and punishment  Anger/outrage at unfair offers  Empathy/lack of empathy based on previous fair/unfair play

Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler Firms deserve fair profit should not take advantage of customers or workers Sluggish market adjustments indicate firms are constrained in behavior by more than legal issues or budgets. Surveys show fairness in pricing and wages is important. Fairness is thought of as an enforceable implicit contract Transactors avoid offending firms Games show willingness to punish

Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler (cont) Fairness: Is more important in established relationships that new relationships. Price increases in response to cost increases is ok; price increases in response to demand increases are not. Fairness is relative to reference price. OK to up price to protect profit Similar findings with respect to wages.

Implications for Markets When excess demand is unaccompanied by increases in costs the market will fail to clear. When a single supplier provides a family of goods for which there is differential demand and different costs, there will be shortages in the most valued items. - This implies for most goods there will be shortages at peak demand times (like for vacation hotels). Price changes are more responsive to cost changes than to demand changes, and mre responsive to cost increases than to cost decreases. Price decreases take the form of temporary discounts. Wages are sticky downward. -Firms will frame part of compensation as bonueses or profit sharing to minimize reductions in compensation during slack periods.

Contrary evidence of social preferences Forsyth, Horowitz, Savin and Sefton find most players give away nontrivial portions of the money available to them. They use an ultimatum game and dictator game – Rational agents, offerer keeps (almost all) – Fair agents have a more equal split However, the tests of the fairness hypothesis fail.

Found in all experiments most players give away non trivial portions of the pie, which violates neoclassical theory of selfish preferences. Fairness hypothesis states that the distribution of proposals in ultimatum game and dictator game should be the same. – Players are more generous in the ultimatum game. – So Reject fairness hypothesis at p=0.01 One explanation is that different types of players; some receivers are gamesman, some are spiteful, so offerers who are gamesman find it optimal to offer a nontrivial share

Modelling Social Preferences  Objectives  explanation and prediction  psychological basis  Issues in modelling Reference standard; intentions; purpose of punishment; reference agent  Psychological game theory Based on beliefs and intentions. Takes into account emotions.

Social Preferences Occur whenever U i =U i (x i.x j ) i≠j where x i and x j are allocations. Altruism is when U i depends directly on x j. Distributive Preferences (Fairness) is U i depends on the comparison of x i to x j.

Inequality-Aversion Fehr-Schmidt model (WJE, 1999) – 'guilt/envy' U i (x) = x i – α i /(n-1)Σ max(x j –x i,0) – β i /(n-1) Σ max(x i –x j,0) i≠j where α and β = ‘envy’ and ‘guilt’ coefficients from comparing own allocation to others. Expect α i > β i so disutility is greater if others are better off. 1.Based on pure self-interest 2.A minority of selfish individuals can dominate a market 3.Ignores reciprocity

45 o xjxj xixi U i (x j ||x i ) Red line is the utility line

Inequality-Aversion (2) Bolton-Ockenfels model (AER, 2000) 'ERC-model' (equity, reciprocity, competition) Players prefer a relative payoff that is equal to the average payoff. U i (x) = U(x i, x i / Σx j ) Differences between BO and FS model: 1.BO model: relative shares. 2.BO model does not compare each player’s payoffs with the maximum and minimum of the other payoffs, like the FS model does. 3.BO model: symmetrical attitude towards inequality, guilt and envy equal in force (α i = β i ); FS model: envy stronger than guilt. FS model generally performing better

Inequality-Aversion (3) Charness and Rabin (QJE, 2002) Rawlsian distributive justice (quasi maximin) Social Welfare Function W(x i, x k )=  *min{x i, x k } +(1-  )(x i + x k )  (0,1) Utility U i (x i, x k )= (1-  )x i, +  W(x i,x k )  (0,1) Cares less about person j if person j is better off

Inequity-Aversion Konow (AER, 2003) “Entitlement” or “right” allocation  j is the right allocation for person j Utility U i (x i, x j,  j )= U(x i ) – f i (x j -  j ) f i is inequity aversion function

jj -f j Example, f i (x j -  j ) = (x j -  j ) 2  depends on 1.Accountability 2.Efficiency 3.Need

For example, If person i is twice as productive as person j, the allocation depends on the cause of the higher productivity. If the greater productivity is due to endogenous issues like greater effort, the allocation should be double. If the allocation is due to exogenous issues, the allocation should be more equal. Application, Rosenman, “The public finance of healthy behavior”, Public Choice, 2011

Reciprocity Models Rabin (1993) – tit-for-tat 1. Be kind in response to actual or perceived or expected kindness 2. Be unkind in response to actual or perceived or expected unkindness U i = x i + g j (1+f i ) Where g i is the believe of how he will be treated and f i is how he will treat j. Utility increases if treatment given is the same as treatment received/expected. Hence reciprocity model.

Reciprocity Model (more complicated)  Rabin (1993) – tit-for-tat, 2 players with 2 factors: 1.Player 1’s kindness to player 2 2.Player 1’s perception of player 2’s kindness Player 1 has 3- component utility function: (can be further parameterized to pure altruism)

Characteristics of Rabin Model 1.People will sacrifice their own material well-being to help those being kind. 2.People will sacrifice their own material well-being to punish those being unkind 3.Both these effects are bigger as the cost of the material sacrifice is smaller

General Specification for Empirical Testing Efficiency requires U i = x i +  (x i + x k ) where  is the MU of aggregate x. So specify U i = x i +  (x i + x k ) - α i max(x k – x i,0) -  i max(x i – x k,0) So α measures envy and  measures guilt