Coordination and institutions: A review of game-theoretic contributions Stéphane Straub University of Edinburgh.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
The Basics of Game Theory
Advertisements

6.896: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture 20 Yang Cai.
Arbitration. Introduction In this section we will consider the impact of outside arbitration on coordination games Specifically, we will consider two.
Seminar in Auctions and Mechanism Design Based on J. Hartline’s book: Approximation in Economic Design Presented by: Miki Dimenshtein & Noga Levy.
Bank Competition and Financial Stability: A General Equilibrium Expositi on Gianni De Nicolò International Monetary Fund and CESifo Marcella Lucchetta.
1 Strategic choice of financing systems in regulated and interconnected industries Anna BassaniniJerome Pouyet Rome & IDEICREST-LEI & CERAS-ENPC
SOCIAL CAPITAL THE AIMS OF THESE NOTES – Social capital: a controversial concept THREE KEY WORDS – Networks – Trust – Institutions.
Genesis of social institution Erika Seki Department of Economics University of Aberdeen How existing institutions have emerged How to design mechanisms.
Evolution and Repeated Games D. Fudenberg (Harvard) E. Maskin (IAS, Princeton)
Contract Enforceability and Economic Institutions in Early Trade: The Maghribi Trader’s Coalition By Avner Grief.
Games With No Pure Strategy Nash Equilibrium Player 2 Player
Infinitely Repeated Games. In an infinitely repeated game, the application of subgame perfection is different - after any possible history, the continuation.
Chapter 14 Infinite Horizon 1.Markov Games 2.Markov Solutions 3.Infinite Horizon Repeated Games 4.Trigger Strategy Solutions 5.Investing in Strategic Capital.
The basics of Game Theory Understanding strategic behaviour.
M9302 Mathematical Models in Economics Instructor: Georgi Burlakov 2.5.Repeated Games Lecture
EC941 - Game Theory Lecture 7 Prof. Francesco Squintani
Negotiation A Lesson in Multiagent System Based on Jose Vidal’s book Fundamentals of Multiagent Systems Henry Hexmoor SIUC.
Game Theory: Inside Oligopoly
Game Theory Lecture 9.
The Core A Methodological Toolkit to Reform Payment Systems Game Theory World Bank, Washington DC, November 5th, 2003.
EC941 - Game Theory Prof. Francesco Squintani Lecture 8 1.
Bundling Equilibrium in Combinatorial Auctions Written by: Presented by: Ron Holzman Rica Gonen Noa Kfir-Dahav Dov Monderer Moshe Tennenholtz.
Adverse Selection Asymmetric information is feature of many markets
Small business banking and financing: a global perspective, Cagliari The impact of an IFRS-adoption on relationship lending for German SMEs – An economic.
Chapter 11 Game Theory and Asymmetric Information
Yale Lectures 21 and Repeated Games: Cooperation vs the End Game.
Agent Technology for e-Commerce Chapter 10: Mechanism Design Maria Fasli
ESNIE, May 2006The Emergence of Formal Institutions1 Santiago Sánchez-Pagés & Stephane Straub (University of Edinburgh)
CS522: Algorithmic and Economic Aspects of the Internet Instructors: Nicole Immorlica Mohammad Mahdian
Job Market Signaling (Spence model)
APEC 8205: Applied Game Theory Fall 2007
Incomplete Contracts Renegotiation, Communications and Theory December 10, 2007.
TOPIC 6 REPEATED GAMES The same players play the same game G period after period. Before playing in one period they perfectly observe the actions chosen.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Bargaining and Negotiation Review.
Chapter 19 Fiscal Federalism Intermediate Public Economics.
Anonymizing Web Services Through a Club Mechanism With Economic Incentives Mamata Jenamani Leszek Lilien Bharat Bhargava Department of Computer Sciences.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Bargaining and Negotiation Review.
Communication Networks A Second Course Jean Walrand Department of EECS University of California at Berkeley.
© 2009 Institute of Information Management National Chiao Tung University Lecture Notes II-2 Dynamic Games of Complete Information Extensive Form Representation.
Overview Aggregating preferences The Social Welfare function The Pareto Criterion The Compensation Principle.
Principal - Agent Games. Sometimes asymmetric information develops after a contract has been signed In this case, signaling and screening do not help,
Chapter 5.  Are “initial conditions” important in determining final outcomes for countries?  Does it matter where a country starts its development process.
Chapter 37 Asymmetric Information. Information in Competitive Markets In purely competitive markets all agents are fully informed about traded commodities.
1 Game Theory Sequential bargaining and Repeated Games Univ. Prof.dr. M.C.W. Janssen University of Vienna Winter semester Week 46 (November 14-15)
Principles of Policy Analysis. Markets are a good way to organize economic activities However, the government often plays a role in today’s modern economies.
Consumer Behavior & Public Policy Lecture #3 Microeconomics.
Information and the Coase Theorem From Joseph Farrell JEP 1987.
1 Efficiency and Nash Equilibria in a Scrip System for P2P Networks Eric J. Friedman Joseph Y. Halpern Ian Kash.
Nash equilibrium Nash equilibrium is defined in terms of strategies, not payoffs Every player is best responding simultaneously (everyone optimizes) This.
Experimental Economics and Neuroeconomics. An Illustration: Rules.
Dynamic Games & The Extensive Form
PowerPoint Slides prepared by: Andreea CHIRITESCU Eastern Illinois University Ten Principles of Economics 1 © 2011 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved.
Lecture 7 Course Summary The tools of strategy provide guiding principles that that should help determine the extent and nature of your professional interactions.
Managerial Effort Incentives and Market Collusion Cécile Aubert University of Bordeaux (GREThA) and Toulouse School of Economics (LERNA) ACLE 2009.
제 10 장 게임이론 Game Theory: Inside Oligopoly
Mechanism Design II CS 886:Electronic Market Design Sept 27, 2004.
Ten Principles of Economics. 1. Trade off -between efficiency and equity Efficiency - the property of society getting the most it can from its scarce.
6.853: Topics in Algorithmic Game Theory Fall 2011 Constantinos Daskalakis Lecture 22.
Repeated Game Modeling of Multicast Overlays Mike Afergan (MIT CSAIL/Akamai) Rahul Sami (University of Michigan) April 25, 2006.
Edinburgh, 17th May 2008The Emergence of Institutions1 1 Santiago Sánchez-Pagés (University of Edinburgh) Stéphane Straub (University of Edinburgh)
1 CH2_Part II. 2 Externalities as a Source of Market Failure Exclusivity is one of the chief characteristics of an efficient property rights structure.
“Group consumption, free-riding, & informal reciprocity agreements”. Why do people use informal reciprocity agreements? Most analysis answers this question.
ECO290E: Game Theory Lecture 3 Why and How is Nash Equilibrium Reached?
By: Donté Howell Game Theory in Sports. What is Game Theory? It is a tool used to analyze strategic behavior and trying to maximize his/her payoff of.
Unit 4 SOCIAL INTERACTIONS.
Learning 6.2 Game Theory.
Chapter 14 & 15 Repeated Games.
Chapter 14 & 15 Repeated Games.
Lecture 10 Coordination and Reputation
Informal Creditors and Sovereign Debt Restructuring
Presentation transcript:

Coordination and institutions: A review of game-theoretic contributions Stéphane Straub University of Edinburgh

Introduction Institutions are key in enhancing the efficiency of economic interactions. Huge variation. Both temporal and spatial. While the role of institutions as protectors of property rights has been extensively studied, a more neglected aspect is that of institutions as coordination devices (Bardhan, 2005).

Institutions and coordination failures Institutions can help to correct the coordination failure that plague basic economic interactions. - Developing economies: Witnesses in commercial exchange (Attali, 2003), contract enforcement (Fafchamps, 2004), dispute prevention (McMillan & Woodruff, 99, 2000). - Economies in transition to industrial/market stage: Japan after WWII, East Asian countries (Aoki et al., 1997), transition countries (Johnson et al., 2002). - Specific markets: US Cotton Market (Bernstein, 2001), Diamond (Bernstein, 1992, Richman, 2005).

Player C jDjD C x,x -l, g Player i Dg, -ly,y Institutional coordination needed because when individuals act opportunistically, pareto inferior outcomes may arise. Example: prisoner’s dilemna. (D,D) is the only Nash equilibrium, and it is dominated by (C,C). Assumptions: g > x > y > -l (g - l > 2x)

Application 1: Social Capital (Durlauf & Fafchamps, 2005) ‘‘You should always go to other people’s funerals; otherwise, they won’t come to yours.’’ Yogi Bera. Social Capital (SK) is “something” that generates positive externalities for members of a group, through shared norms, trust and values and their effects on expectations and behavior. These arise from informal forms of organizations based on social networks and associations. So SK looks very much like “informal institutions”.

Social Capital To matter, SK must compensate for some inefficiency, i.e. we must be in a 2 nd best world, e.g. because of externalities, free- riding, imperfect information and enforcement, imperfect competition, etc. Social capital can act by:  Facilitating information sharing;  Modify preferences, alter identification to groups;  Facilitate coordination, provide leadership;

Player C jDjD C x,x -l, g Player i Dg, -l0,0 Example: modified preferences induce shift from (D,D) to (C,C)

Example: altruistic preferences (within group, kinship, etc.) Each player’s payoff is a weighted sum of hers and her opponent’s payoff: U i = (1-α) π i + α π j Then we get (see next slide) that (C,C) is a Nash equilibrium whenever: α > (g - x) / g + l which can arise for α << ½.

Player C jDjD C x,x αg -(1-α)l, (1-α)g-αl Player i D (1-α)g-αl, αg -(1-α)l0,0 Players’ payoffs with altruistic preferences:

Example: social structure that facilitates cooperation (Routledge & Amsberg, JME 03) Community with N players, randomly matched to play a repeated PD. Games are private (no info on other players’ trade). Agents play C if it is an equilibrium. Proba of trade between 2 agents depends on N. Player C jDjD C 2,2 0,3 Player i D3,01,1

N max trades per period. If N max > N-1, at most N-1 trades. Proba of trade between 2 agents (i and j): π ij = min (1, N max /(N-1)) Discount rate β. A strategy profile s c that supports (C,C) is to use trigger strategies: play C if history of play with agent j contains only (C,C), otherwise play D. SK exists if all players following s c is an equilibrium.

For trade between 2 agents (i and j), strategies s ij c and s ji c are a SPE iff : π ij > π c = (1-β)/β Proof: no deviation if 3 + β [(π ij.1)/(1-β)] < 2 + β [(π ij.2)/(1-β)]  π ij > (1-β)/ β Intuition: no deviation as long as agents value future cooperative trade more than one-time deviation gain + unfriendly trade forever thereafter.

N max = 3, β = 0.55, π c = In closed communities, probability of trade π(3) = 1 > π c. Each agent trades twice, for a utility of 4: 2 trades times 2, since cooperation is sustained.

When communities are linked by the bridge, probability of trade π(6) = 0.6 < π c. Each agent trades 3 times, for a utility of 3: 3 trades times 1, since cooperation is not sustained. More opportunities for trade but reduction in welfare because SK destroyed (migration parabola).

Repeated PD and cooperation. In 2 agents repeated PD, Folk Theorem known to hold: cooperative outcome can be sustained as an equilibrium. Can Folk Theorem-type results be obtained in social games with (possibly random) matching? when players have limited information about others (past) behavior? Answer is yes, under certain assumptions. Informational assumptions appear to be crucial. Refs: Greif, 93; Milgrom, North and Weingast, 90; Kandori, 92, Ellison, 94, etc.

Greif (1994) – Informal institution 11 th century Maghribi traders used to employ overseas agents, despite the obvious commitment problem. Complete information about past behavior of agents in the community. Cooperative relationships sustained by a multilateral punishment strategy: a merchant offers an agent a wage W, rehires the same agent if he has been honest (unless forced separation has occurred), fires the agent if he has cheated, never hires an agent who has ever cheated any merchant, and (randomly) chooses an agent from among the unemployed agents who never have cheated if forced separation has occurred.

Kandori (1992) – Informal institution With no information, a “contagious” punishment strategy may sustain cooperation: when one player cheats in period t, his opponent cheats from t+1 onwards, infecting other players, etc. For any N, there are payoffs which allow cooperation, but as N grows large, extreme values of the payoff are required (to avoid agents not punishing to slow down contagion and enjoy high payoffs in the future, the risk associated (getting -l) must be high). Ellison (1994) provides several refinements.

Milgrom, North and Weingast (1990) Formal institution The law merchant enforcement system and Champagne fairs in the 12 th and 13 th centuries. There is a specialized agent (judge) serving both as repository of information and adjudicator of disputes (both at a cost to trading agents). Under certain conditions, cooperation is sustained at a (transaction) cost for trading agents.

Osborne & Rubinstein (1994): “…in our opinion the main contribution of the theory is the discovery of interesting stable social norms (strategies) that support mutually desirable payoff profiles, and not simply the demonstration that equilibria exist that generate such profiles.” Problem: How do agents come up with these norms in the first place? In particular, how do they structure their interaction and allocate roles when some form of formal enforcement is required?

Sanchez-Pages & Straub 2007 We model the process through which institutions such as these may arise. We characterize:  The factors that make possible or hinder the formation of institutions.  The level of efficiency at which they arise. Their emergence is the equilibrium of a game that agents play in the state of nature. It has to be self- enforcing. Otherwise, the economy remains in the status-quo.

Player C jDjD C x,x -l, g Player i Dg, -l0,0 Who induces shift from (D,D) to (C,C)?

The Model In the state of nature, N+1 agents, endowed with ω, are randomly matched to play the PD without interference. Expected unit payoff is then αx. The parameter α denotes the status-quo level of coordination or trust (without institution, they play (C,C) with proba α). The institution is able to ensure that the (C,C) profile is played with proba 1. But someone has to run it (Pepe…).

The Model One of the agents becomes the “centre”. She must relinquish the ability to trade. But is compensated in exchange. Agents must pay a fee a ≤ ω to interact under the centre’s umbrella (trade certification, dispute prevention / resolution, reputation management…).

The procedure of institution formation Our procedure of institution formation starts with a lottery over the set of agents who freely participate in it, to determine who will become the central agent. Justification:  All equally likely to be center.  centre is randomly drawn each period. the institution must emerge in the most decentralized way possible. No commitment is assumed.

The procedure of institution formation First, the fee is freely chosen by the central agent: The institution is a revenue-maximizer. Having observed a, agents must decide whether to become formal or not. 2 problems (IR constraints):  Ex ante, agents may not want to participate.  Ex post center may renege.

Two sources of inefficiency (1) Efficient institution may not arise  This is more likely for economies of intermediate size and high levels of trust α.  If N small: W F lower than informality payoff.  If N large: incentive to become the central agent increases (more revenue).  High trust undermines the position of the institution (reminiscent of identification problem in social capital literature. See Durlauf and Fafchamps, 2005).

Two sources of inefficiency (2) Institution may be sub-efficient (too extractive).  When status-quo trust is high, revenue and welfare maximisation are aligned.  Otherwise, with low status-quo trust, the institution arises at a sub-optimal level of efficiency (that is when it is most needed).  The rent associated with being the centre are the key motivation for agents to participate. With a high extractive fee, all other agents are just indifferent.

Appendix: The formal model One of the agents becomes the “centre”. She must relinquish the ability to trade. But is compensated in exchange. Agents must pay a fee a ≤ ω to interact under the centre’s umbrella (trade certification, dispute prevention / resolution, reputation management…).

Participation decisions Having observed a, agents must decide whether to become formal or not. If they become formal, interacting with another formal agents yields per unit return where x a > 0, x aa 1/α. The efficiency of interactions depends on the fee paid to the institution.

Participation decisions Interacting with an informal agent yields regardless of your status. Expected payoffs when K formal agents:

Participation decisions Define K formal agents can be supported in equilibrium if and only if But a (K) is increasing in K, so only corner solutions prevail (full formality or full informality)

Participation decisions Proposition 1: For a given level of the fee a (i) Informality can be supported in equilibrium only if a ≥ a(1)=0 (ii) Full formality can be supported in equilibrium only if a ≤ a(N) 0 a(N) Only informalityMultiple equilibria: full formality or informality Formality sustainable Informality sustainable

First-best level of the fee a Planner objective function: max W F = N[(ω-a)x(a)+(a-c)]+ ω s.t. a < a(N) This defines a*. The first best fee is then: a F = min{a*,a(N)} and there is a threshold α* s.t a*>a(N) if α > α*, so in this case the revenue maximizing fee coincides with the first best level. Finally, informality may dominate for N and ω small and α high.

The procedure of institution formation Our procedure of institution formation starts with a lottery over the set of agents who freely participate in it, to determine who will become the central agent. One justification: All equally likely to be center. game repeated infinitely and centre is randomly drawn each period. See Morgan (2000) for an application of lotteries to reduce free-riding on public goods financing.

Timing

The fully decentralized procedure In this procedure, the institution must emerge in the most decentralized way possible. No commitment is assumed. First, the fee is freely chosen by the central agent: The institution is a revenue-maximizer. So it will set the maximum fee compatible with formality, a(N).

The fully decentralized procedure Second, the agent that runs the institution can renege ex-post. For the institution to arise, an ex-post participation constraint must be satisfied: That’s for the centre. It is trivially satisfied for other agents.

The fully decentralized procedure Ex-ante participation constraint given the fee a because either all agents or none participate in the lottery. With a(N), the institution arises iff the (stronger) ex- ante constraint is met. It rewrites:

The fully decentralized procedure Proposition 2: If the ex-ante constraint holds, there exists a SPE of the fully decentralized procedure that implements formality under a(N).

Two sources of inefficiency Corollary 1: There exists a range of parameters for which a potentially welfare enhancing institution does not arise. This is the case when parameters are such that the level of individual welfare obtained under formality dominates the level of welfare under full informality but is not high enough to induce ex ante participation in the lottery:

Two sources of inefficiency This is more likely for economies of intermediate size and high levels of trust α. If N small: W F lower than informality payoff. If N large: incentive to become the central agent increases (more revenue). High trust undermines the position of the institution (reminiscent of identification problem in social capital literature. See Durlauf and Fafchamps, 2005).

Two sources of inefficiency Corollary 2: The utilitarian first best fee can be implemented in a SPE of the fully decentralized procedure only for high enough of status-quo trust α. When status-quo trust is high, revenue and welfare maximisation are aligned (see first best fee a*). Otherwise, the institution arises at a sub-optimal level of efficiency. The rent associated with being the centre are the key motivation for agents to participate. With a = a(N), all other agents are just indifferent.

Two types of commitment Now imagine that commitment can be imposed along two lines: 1. Individual: Agents cannot renege ex-post whatever their role. 2. Collective: The fee is chosen collectively before the lottery takes place. Different procedures arise from different combinations of assumptions.

Other procedures One can consider alternative procedures by combining these 2 types of commitment. Imposing individual commitment alone has no effect. Collective commitment alleviates the second type of inefficiency. Only when commitment is imposed in both dimensions, does the institution arise whenever it is welfare enhancing.

These two types of commitment rely on some exogenous enforcement mechanism. We consider two ways to endogenize commitment: 1. Trigger-like strategies. 2. Threat of secession. Endogenous commitment

Secession When there is no commitment, secession is an issue. No group in society should be able to improve its situation by withdrawing and forming its own mini-society. We study when the institution will be secession-proof and the impact of this threat on welfare.

Secession Definition: Denote by a N the fee set by the institution. A coalition of S interacting agents is said to be blocking if and only if Note that when a group secedes, it sets a self-enforcing fee. A fee is secession-proof (it is in the core of the procedure of institution formation) if it does not spawn any blocking coalition.

Secession Proposition 4 : The set of secession-proof fees is non-empty if and only if N is low enough. The reason for blocking is the prospect of becoming the central agent in the new mini society. When the level of status-quo trust is low enough, the threat of secession can tame the central agent.

Secession N

Secession and efficiency A natural question is whether secession is bad or good for efficiency. Let us look at the eventual outcome of the secession process. We say that a coalition structure is secession-proof if all coalitions in it can set a (possibly different) fee that does not spawn any blocking coalition.

Secession and efficiency Proposition 5 : For high enough levels of status-quo trust, the total sum of payoffs under a secession-proof structure is never greater than under a single institution. In our model, only the center gets positive rents. This creates strong incentives for secession. Proliferation of institutions is however socially inefficient because of duplication of costs. A trade-off may arise if transaction costs of institution are lower in small groups.

Conclusions We have presented a model where an institution emerges as the equilibrium of a game played in the state of nature. The institution may not emerge despite being welfare enhancing This happens for intermediate population sizes and high levels of status quo coordination. But even if it emerges it can do it at a suboptimal level. This is because the rent associated with being the centre are the key motivation for agents to participate.