QR 38 4/3/07, Uncertainty I. Risk II. Agency problems III. Asymmetric information and perceptions.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
1.
Advertisements

Remuneration & Monitoring n 1. Introduction n 2. Principal-Agent Theory n 3. Do incentives work? n 4. Empirical evidence.
Contracts and Moral Hazards
Hal Varian Intermediate Microeconomics Chapter Thirty-Six
BASICS OF GAME THEORY. Recap Decision Theory vs. Game Theory Rationality Completeness Transitivity What’s in a game? Players Actions Outcomes Preferences.
Michael R. Baye, Managerial Economics and Business Strategy, 3e. ©The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc., 1999 Managerial Economics & Business Strategy Chapter.
Choices Involving Risk
QR 38 3/22/07, Strategic moves and structure-induced equilibria I. Strategic moves II. Credibility III. Strategic moves as institutional choice.
Slide 1  2002 South-Western Publishing An assumption of pure competition was complete knowledge of all market information. But knowledge can be unevenly.
Adverse Selection Asymmetric information is feature of many markets
The Economics of Information. Risk a situation in which there is a probability that an event will occur. People tend to prefer greater certainty and less.
A camper awakens to the growl of a hungry bear and sees his friend putting on a pair of running shoes, “You can’t outrun a bear,” scoffs the camper. His.
Interactions of Tax and Nontax Costs n Uncertainty u Symmetric uncertainty u Strategic uncertainty (information asymmetry) F Hidden action (moral hazard)
Chapter 11 Game Theory and Asymmetric Information
QR 38, 2/8/07 Elements of games I.The Columbus game II.Basic questions III.Terms.
Asymmetric Information ECON 370: Microeconomic Theory Summer 2004 – Rice University Stanley Gilbert.
QR 38 4/10 and 4/12/07 Bayes’ Theorem I. Bayes’ Rule II. Updating beliefs in deterrence III. Hegemonic policy.
Chapter 9 THE ECONOMICS OF INFORMATION Copyright ©2002 by South-Western, a division of Thomson Learning. All rights reserved. MICROECONOMIC THEORY BASIC.
QR 38, 2/20/07 Credibility I.Deterrence II.Threats, promises, and credibility.
QR 38, 2/6/07 Overview of game theory I. Strategic interaction II. Game theory and international relations III. Deterrence.
QR 38 Signaling I, 4/17/07 I. Signaling and screening II. Pooling and separating equilibria III. Semi-separating equilibria.
Game Theory Here we study a method for thinking about oligopoly situations. As we consider some terminology, we will see the simultaneous move, one shot.
QR 38 3/20/07, More on repeated games in IR I.Folk theorem II.Other solutions to the PD III.Repeated PDs in practice.
Robust Mechanisms for Information Elicitation Aviv Zohar & Jeffrey S. Rosenschein The Hebrew University.
Asymmetric Information
QR 38, 2/22/07 Strategic form: dominant strategies I.Strategic form II.Finding Nash equilibria III.Strategic form games in IR.
By Edgar K. Browning & Mark A. Zupan John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
QR 38, 2/15/07 Extensive form games I.Writing down a game II.Finding the equilibrium III.Adding complexity.
1 Chapter 9 Knowledge and Information In this chapter we want to see what happens in a market when the amount of information participants have is different.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Bargaining and Negotiation Review.
This Week’s Topics  Review Class Concepts -Sequential Games -Simultaneous Games -Bertrand Trap -Auctions  Review Homework  Practice Problems.
UNIT II: The Basic Theory Zero-sum Games Nonzero-sum Games Nash Equilibrium: Properties and Problems Bargaining Games Bargaining and Negotiation Review.
This Week’s Topics  Review Class Concepts -Auctions, continued -Repeated Games -Bertrand Trap & Anti-Trust -Auctions.
Game Theory “A little knowledge is a dangerous thing. So is a lot.” - Albert Einstein Topic 7 Information.
Principal - Agent Games. Sometimes asymmetric information develops after a contract has been signed In this case, signaling and screening do not help,
Semester 2, Seminar 7 – Contracting & Accounting Information Financial Accounting.
Chapter 37 Asymmetric Information. Information in Competitive Markets In purely competitive markets all agents are fully informed about traded commodities.
Asymmetric Information
Recognizing Employee Contributions with Pay
Copyright © 2009 by Pearson Education Canada Chapter 9 An Analysis of Conflict.
Chapter 12 Choices Involving Strategy Copyright © 2014 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written.
Lecture 2 in Contracts Employment Contracts This lecture studies how those who create and administer organizations design the incentives and institutional.
Information and the Coase Theorem From Joseph Farrell JEP 1987.
The Moral Hazard Problem Stefan P. Schleicher University of Graz
Decision Making Under Uncertainty and Risk 1 By Isuru Manawadu B.Sc in Accounting Sp. (USJP), ACA, AFM
Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Contract Design MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Adverse selection Almost essential Adverse.
© 2010 W. W. Norton & Company, Inc. 37 Asymmetric Information.
Asymmetric Information
© John Chachere– CEE 115/215 Goals and Methods of Sustainable Building Design Analysis of Decisions and Risks Decision Elements Decision and Risk Analysis.
Chapter 5 Choice Under Uncertainty. Chapter 5Slide 2 Topics to be Discussed Describing Risk Preferences Toward Risk Reducing Risk The Demand for Risky.
Lecture 7 Course Summary The tools of strategy provide guiding principles that that should help determine the extent and nature of your professional interactions.
QR 24 Economics Review Session 12/3/2009. Agenda Demand curves Supply curves Equilibrium Market failures – Moral hazard – Adverse selection Net Present.
Chapter 4 The Adverse Selection Problem Stefan P. Schleicher University of Graz Economics of Information Incentives and Contracts.
Contracting The incentives of the employer (principal) and employee (agent) are different. A contract is designed to implement an outcome both parties.
Chapter ElevenCopyright 2009 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Prentice Hall. 1 Chapter 11 Game Theory and Asymmetric Information.
Lecture 5 Financial Incentives This lecture is paired with our previous one that discussed employee benefits. Here we focus on the reasons why monetary.
Lecture 6 Uncertainty. Cost of Risk Agents are said to be risk averse if they prefer the expected payoff from a gamble to the gamble itself.
© 2010 Institute of Information Management National Chiao Tung University Chapter 7 Incentive Mechanism Principle-Agent Problem Production with Teams Competition.
1 THE FUTURE: RISK AND RETURN. 2 RISK AND RETURN If the future is known with certainty, all investors will hold assets offering the highest rate of return.
Frank Cowell: Microeconomics Moral Hazard MICROECONOMICS Principles and Analysis Frank Cowell Almost essential Risk Almost essential Risk Prerequisites.
Oligopoly and Game Theory Topic Students should be able to: Use simple game theory to illustrate the interdependence that exists in oligopolistic.
By: Donté Howell Game Theory in Sports. What is Game Theory? It is a tool used to analyze strategic behavior and trying to maximize his/her payoff of.
Chapter Thirty-Six Asymmetric Information. Information in Competitive Markets u In purely competitive markets all agents are fully informed about traded.
Asymmetric Information
Asymmetric Information
Lecture 8 Asymmetric Information: Adverse Selection
Uncertainty and Information
Markets with Asymmetric Information
THE FIRM: OWNERS, MANAGERS, AND EMPLOYEES
Game Theory Fall Mike Shor Topic 7.
Presentation transcript:

QR 38 4/3/07, Uncertainty I. Risk II. Agency problems III. Asymmetric information and perceptions

I. Risk Uncertainty means lack of certainty about the outcomes of a game. Many possible sources: Outcomes inherently risky (effect of weather on a battle) Actions difficult to observe Preferences of other player unknown All are important in IR

Incomplete and imperfect information Imprecise information about outcomes is incomplete information. Imprecise information about past moves is imperfect information. In practice, the way that we deal with incomplete information is to transform it into a game of imperfect information.

Risk Risk: some probability distribution over outcomes Payoffs are probabilistic. Risk is inherent in the situation, not due to the strategic actions of others.

Commodity supplier example Consider OPEC (or coffee or bauxite suppliers): Price of commodity fluctuates depending on consumer demand, weather, etc. This creates risk for both the supplier and consumer. Assume that a coffee grower makes $150,000 in a good year, $50,000 in a bad year

Commodity example Assume a distribution over these two possible outcomes The expected profit is then $100,000 Consider the consumer (U.S. distributor): a good year for the grower is a bad year for the consumer. So a “good” year leads to profits of $50,000 for the consumer; a “bad” year to profits of $150,000

Commodity example The consumer’s expected profit is $100,000. Can the consumer and grower collaborate to reduce the risk to which they are exposed? Yes, by pooling their risks. In general, pooling works as long as risks are not perfectly positively correlated.

Commodity example Here, since the risks are negatively correlated, pooling should help both. Their combined income is always $200,000. They could enter into a contract in which the grower gives the consumer $50,000 in good years, and the consumer gives the grower $50,000 in bad years.

Commodity example Then each is guaranteed a payoff of $100,000 Risk has been eliminated There is no advantage to this arrangement if the players are risk-neutral, but it increases their utility if they are risk- averse. Because of the perfect negative correlation, the risk disappears completely.

Risk pooling in IR Problems with risk-pooling schemes: Enforceability –Commodity arrangements often short-lived; a PD (ICA and OPEC exceptions) Moral hazard –If insured against risk, may not take precautions you otherwise would (fertilizer) Adverse selection –Those most likely to need insurance will purchase it (incompetent growers)

II. Agency problems Moral hazard problem is linked to a general class of informational problems known as agency issues. Examples: employer hiring an employee – the employee is the employer’s agent. Choosing leader for an IO. Using an agent has many advantages, but also problems, such as whether the agent’s actions are observable.

Observability of actions Consider allowing the IMF to negotiate a bail-out arrangement with Argentina (U.S. the principal, IMF the agent). Negotiations won’t be entirely public Even if a good agreement is reached, it may not help Argentina’s economy (risk) If the economy doesn’t improve, is this the result of the agent not doing a good job or bad luck? U.S. can’t tell.

Observability of actions How to address this problem? If agent’s actions observable, just pay IMF more for negotiating well. Otherwise have to make the payoff contingent on the observed outcomes and use incentive schemes. Solutions have to meet the incentive- compatibility constraint and the participation constraint.

Incentive schemes Incentive-compatibility constraint: How big the payment would have to be to induce good effort. –Have to make the expected payoff big enough to induce good effort. –Because outcomes are risky, this can mean the actual payment must be very large. –Even if the agent does a good job, by bad luck he might get paid nothing.

Incentive schemes Participation constraint: Have to offer enough that the agent will choose to work with you at all How big this payment must be depends on the agent’s exit options. The principal’s lack of information means that he must pay more than under complete information. This inefficiency falls on the least-informed player, the principal.

III. Asymmetric information and perceptions Agency problems are an example of information asymmetry (above, the IMF knew if it negotiated in good faith, but the U.S. didn’t). Asymmetric information is a general problem in IR. –Players may know their own preferences, but not others’ –Players know their own past behavior, but not others’

Asymmetric information When asymmetric information exists, perceptions or beliefs become central to the play and resolution of the game. Now the equilibrium has to be described in terms of both strategies and beliefs, because they depend intimately on one another.

Beliefs Beliefs are not random: a rational player will update beliefs in response to events. –A player that stubbornly stuck to beliefs that were at odds with observed behavior wouldn’t be acting rationally. Definition of belief: a probability attached to some quantity, such as others’ payoffs.

U.S.-North Korea example Consider the U.S. trying to convince NK to give up its nuclear program by offering aid in exchange. NK could put either a high or a low value on aid This is NK’s type: a type that values aid highly, or that puts a low value on it NK’s type is private information; NK knows, U.S. only has an estimate.

U.S.-North Korea example E.g., U.S. might believe there is a 70% probability that NK puts a high value on aid, and a 30% probability that it puts a low value on aid. This probability distribution is the U.S. belief about NK’s type. We usually assume that beliefs are common knowledge: NK knows what probabilities U.S. assigns, U.S. knows NK knows this, etc.

Showing asymmetric information in an extensive-form game How to capture asymmetric information in an extensive-form game? Trade sanctions example. –U.S. is considering the use of trade sanctions to convince Japan to open its market. –U.S. is not sure whether Japan is cooperative or not. –A cooperative Japan prefers open markets to a trade war; an uncooperative Japan does not. –U.S. believes Japan is cooperative with probability p.

U.S.-Japan games US J Sanctions No Cooperate No Open markets 3, 2 Trade war 0, 1 Status quo 2, 3 Japan cooperative (p) US No SQ 2, 3 Sanctions J Coop No OM 3, 1 TW 0, 2 Japan uncooperative (1-p)

Game with uncertainty To show the U.S. decision problem, we include an initial move by Nature. Japan can be of two types Each type has different payoffs Nature is not strategic, just rolls the dice An information set ties together nodes where the player making the decision at that node is uncertain about which node has been chosen.

Game with uncertainty Nature Cooperative, prob p Uncooperative, prob 1-p US Sanction No Coop No J Open market, 3, 2 Trade war, 0, 1 SQ 2, 3 Sanction No Coop Open market, 3, 1 Trade war, 0, 2 SQ 2, 3

Game with uncertainty The dashed line indicates the U.S. information set: it doesn’t know precisely which of these nodes it is at when it makes its decision –Could also indicate this by circling the nodes How does the U.S. decide what to do? –It calculates its expected payoff for each strategy (sanction, don’t sanction) –Then chooses the strategy with the highest expected payoff

Critical value of p The U.S. looks for the critical value of p: the value at which it switches to the sanctioning strategy. US payoff from choosing sanctions: p3+(1-p)0 = 3p US payoff from no sanctions: 2 So sanction if 3p>2; p>2/3 2/3 is the critical value of p.

Adding domestic politics BdM then extends the game by considering an interest group that punishes the president if he doesn’t adopt their preferred strategy. This just changes the president’s payoffs, so that the critical value for sanctioning becomes higher Work through this calculation for yourself

Analyzing uncertainty This is a game of one-sided uncertainty: Japan knows U.S. payoffs with certainty. Two-sided uncertainty would get a little messier, but solving the game would involve the same logic.

Signaling What if the players have the opportunity to try to influence the other’s beliefs? This is known as signaling. This opportunity may create incentives to bluff.

Signaling E.g., assume J has the chance to pass a law that makes it easier to impose retaliatory tariffs before US moves. US, on observing passage of this law, may change its probability estimate about J’s type. Knowing this, even a cooperative J may have an incentive to bluff. But US knows this, and so will discount J’s actions.

Appeasement example Appeasement as an example: should a declining power appease a rising power by making repeated concessions to demands? The challenger gets to decide in each period whether to make demands Then the declining power concedes or says no.

Appeasement example There is one-sided uncertainty about the demands of the challenger: declining doesn’t know whether demands are limited or not (how determined the challenger is). If demands are unlimited, war is inevitable, and the declining power would rather fight sooner than later. –Then no concessions made

Appeasement example But because of uncertainty, sometimes the declining power will end up making concessions but still fighting. This is an inefficient outcome. Incomplete information has a cost, and it falls on the less-informed player (as in the agency example).