Cooperating Intelligent Systems Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9, AIMA.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Inference in First-Order Logic
Advertisements

First-Order Logic.
Inference Rules Universal Instantiation Existential Generalization
Standard Logical Equivalences
First-Order Logic (FOL) aka. predicate calculus. First-Order Logic (FOL) Syntax User defines these primitives: – Constant symbols (i.e., the "individuals"
Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9. Outline Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward.
We have seen that we can use Generalized Modus Ponens (GMP) combined with search to see if a fact is entailed from a Knowledge Base. Unfortunately, there.
For Friday No reading Homework: –Chapter 9, exercise 4 (This is VERY short – do it while you’re running your tests) Make sure you keep variables and constants.
1 Resolution in First Order Logic CS 171/271 (Chapter 9, continued) Some text and images in these slides were drawn from Russel & Norvig’s published material.
Inference in FOL All rules of inference for propositional logic apply to first-order logic We just need to reduce FOL sentences to PL sentences by instantiating.
First-Order Logic Inference
1 FOL CS 331/531 Dr M M Awais Unification “It is an algorithm for determining the substitutions needed to make two predicate calculus expressions match”
1 FOL Resolution based Inferencing Resolution based rules studied earlier can lead to inferences, rules such as modus ponen, unit resolution etc… Other.
CSCE 580 Artificial Intelligence Ch.9: Inference in First-Order Logic
Inference in FOL Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc. Chapter 9 Spring 2004.
Inference in FOL Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc. Chapter 9.
Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9. Outline Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward.
Inference in First-Order Logic
1 CS 4700: Foundations of Artificial Intelligence Carla P. Gomes Module: FOL Inference (Reading R&N: Chapter 8)
Cooperating Intelligent Systems Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9, AIMA.
Inference in FOL Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc. Chapter 9 Fall 2004.
Inference in FOL Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc. Chapter 9 Spring 2005.
1 Inference in First-Order Logic. 2 Outline Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward chaining.
Cooperating Intelligent Systems Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9, AIMA.
Predicate Logic or FOL Chapter 8. Syntax See text for formal rules. All of propositional + quantifiers, predicates, functions, and constants. Variables.
CHAPTER 9 Oliver Schulte Inference in First-Order Logic.
INFERENCE IN FIRST-ORDER LOGIC IES 503 ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE İPEK SÜĞÜT.
Inference in First-Order Logic CS 271: Fall 2007 Instructor: Padhraic Smyth.
Logic review A summary of chapters 7, 8, 9 of Artificial Intelligence: A modern approach by Russel and Norving.
1 CS 2710, ISSP 2160 Chapter 9 Inference in First-Order Logic.
Inference in first-order logic I CIS 391 – Introduction to Artificial Intelligence AIMA Chapter (through p. 278) Chapter 9.5 (through p. 300)
Inference in First-Order logic Department of Computer Science & Engineering Indian Institute of Technology Kharagpur.
1 Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9. 2 Outline Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward.
Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9. Outline Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward.
CS 416 Artificial Intelligence Lecture 12 First-Order Logic Chapter 9 Lecture 12 First-Order Logic Chapter 9.
Inference in first- order logic. Outline Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward chaining.
Computing & Information Sciences Kansas State University Friday, 29 Sep 2006CIS 490 / 730: Artificial Intelligence Lecture 16 of 42 Friday, 29 September.
Inference in First-Order Logic 부산대학교 전자전기컴퓨터공학과 인공지능연구실 김민호
CS Introduction to AI Tutorial 8 Resolution Tutorial 8 Resolution.
Computing & Information Sciences Kansas State University Lecture 14 of 42 CIS 530 / 730 Artificial Intelligence Lecture 14 of 42 William H. Hsu Department.
1 Inference in First-Order Logic CS 271: Fall 2009.
1 Inference in First Order Logic CS 171/271 (Chapter 9) Some text and images in these slides were drawn from Russel & Norvig’s published material.
5/18/2005EE562 EE562 ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE FOR ENGINEERS Lecture 13, 5/18/2005 University of Washington, Department of Electrical Engineering Spring.
1 First Order Logic (Syntax, Semantics and Inference)
An Introduction to Artificial Intelligence – CE Chapter 9 - Inference in first-order logic Ramin Halavati In which we define.
1 First Order Logic CS 171/271 (Chapters 8 and 9) Some text and images in these slides were drawn from Russel & Norvig’s published material.
1/19 Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9- Part2 Modified by Vali Derhami.
For Wednesday Finish reading chapter 10 – can skip chapter 8 No written homework.
Inference in first-order logic
Inference in First Order Logic. Outline Reducing first order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward and backward.
Inference in First-Order Logic Chapter 9. Outline Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference Unification Generalized Modus Ponens Forward.
1 Chaining in First Order Logic CS 171/271 (Chapter 9, continued) Some text and images in these slides were drawn from Russel & Norvig’s published material.
Inference in first-order logic
School of Computer Science & Engineering
Inference in First-Order Logic
Knowledge Representation & Reasoning
Introduction to Artificial Intelligence
Inference in First-Order Logic
Inference in first-order logic part 1
Artificial intelli-gence 1:Inference in first-order logic
Artificial Intelligence
Introduction to Artificial Intelligence
Artificial intelligence: Inference in first-order logic
Artificial Intelligence Inference in First Order Logic
Inference in first-order logic
Inference in first-order logic part 1
Inference in First Order Logic (1)
First-Order Logic Inference
First-Order Logic Prof. Dr. Widodo Budiharto 2018
Presentation transcript:

Cooperating Intelligent Systems Inference in first-order logic Chapter 9, AIMA

Reduce to propositional logic Reduce the first order logic sentences to propositional (boolean) logic. Use the inference systems in propositional logic. We need a system for transfering sentences with quantifiers to sentences without quantifiers 

FOL inference rules All the propositional rules (Modus Ponens, And Elimination, And introduction, etc.) plus:the propositional rules Universal Instantiation (UI) Where the variable x is replaced by the ground term a everywhere in the sentence w. Example: ∀ x P(x,f(x),B) ⇒ P(A,f(A),B) Existential Instantiation (EI) Where the variable x is replaced by a ground term a (that makes the sentence true) in the sentence w. Example: ∃ x Q(x,g(x),B) ⇒ Q(A,g(A),B) A must be a new symbol. Ground term = a term without variables

Example: Kings... UI: (Universal Instantiation) ∀ x (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x)) ⇒ Evil(x) King(John) ∧ Greedy(John) ⇒ Evil(John) King(Richard) ∧ Greedy(Richard) ⇒ Evil(Richard) ∶ EI: (Existential Instantiation) ∃ x (Crown(x) ∧ OnHead(x,John)) Crown(C) ∧ OnHead(C,John) C is called a Skolem constant Making up names is called skolemization

Example: Kings... UI: (Universal Instantiation) ∀ x (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x)) ⇒ Evil(x) King(John) ∧ Greedy(John) ⇒ Evil(John) King(Richard) ∧ Greedy(Richard) ⇒ Evil(Richard) ∶ EI: (Existential Instantiation) ∃ x (Crown(x) ∧ OnHead(x,John)) Crown(C) ∧ OnHead(C,John) C is called a Skolem constant Making up names is called skolemization

Propositionalization Apply Universal Instantiation (UI) and Existential Instantiation (EI) so that every FOL KB is made into a propositional KB. ⇒ We can use the tools from propositional logic to prove theorems. Problem with function constants: Father(A), Father(Father(A)), Father(Father(Father(A))), etc. ad infinitum...infinite number of sentences...how can we prove this in finite time? Theorem: We can find every entailed sentence [Gödel, Herbrand], but the search is not guaranteed to stop for nonentailed sentences. (”Solution”: negation-as-failure, stop after a certain time and assume the sentence is false) Inefficient...generalized (lifted) inference rules better

Notation: Substitution Subst() = Apply the substitution  to the sentence . Example: = {x/John} (replace x with John)  = (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x)) ⇒ Evil(x) (King(John) ∧ Greedy(John)) ⇒ Evil(John) General form:  = {v/g} where v is a variable and g is a ground term.

Generalized (lifted) Modus Ponens For atomic sentences p i, q i, and r where there exists a substitution  such that Subst(,p i ) = Subst(,q i ) for all i ∀ x (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) ⇒ Evil(x)) r = Evil(x)  = {x/John} q 2 = Greedy(x)p 2 = Greedy(John) q 1 = King(x)p 1 = King(John) KB We have John who is King and is Greedy. If someone is King and Greedy then he/she/it is also Evil.

Generalized (lifted) Modus Ponens For atomic sentences p i, q i, and r where there exists a substitution  such that Subst(,p i ) = Subst(,q i ) for all i ∀ x (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) ⇒ Evil(x)) r = Evil(x)  = {x/John} q 2 = Greedy(x)p 2 = Greedy(John) q 1 = King(x)p 1 = King(John) KB Subst( ,p 1 ) = Subst( ,q 1 )

Generalized (lifted) Modus Ponens For atomic sentences p i, q i, and r where there exists a substitution  such that Subst(,p i ) = Subst(,q i ) for all i ∀ x (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) ⇒ Evil(x)) r = Evil(x)  = {x/John} q 2 = Greedy(x)p 2 = Greedy(John) q 1 = King(x)p 1 = King(John) KB Subst( ,p 2 ) = Subst( ,q 2 )

Generalized (lifted) Modus Ponens For atomic sentences p i, q i, and r where there exists a substitution  such that Subst(,p i ) = Subst(,q i ) for all i ⇒ Evil(John) King(John), Greedy(John) ∀ x (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) ⇒ Evil(x)) Subst(,r) = Evil(John) r = Evil(x)  = {x/John} q 2 = Greedy(x)p 2 = Greedy(John) q 1 = King(x)p 1 = King(John) KB

Generalized (lifted) Modus Ponens For atomic sentences p i, q i, and r where there exists a substitution  such that Subst(,p i ) = Subst(,q i ) for all i ⇒ Evil(John) King(John), Greedy(John) ∀ x (King(x) ∧ Greedy(x) ⇒ Evil(x)) Subst(,r) = Evil(John) r = Evil(x)  = {x/John} q 2 = Greedy(x)p 2 = Greedy(John) q 1 = King(x)p 1 = King(John) KB Lifted inference rules make only the necessary substitutions

Forward chaining example KB: 1.All cats like fish 2.Cats eat everything they like 3.Ziggy is a cat Example from Tuomas CMU

Forward chaining example KB: 1.All cats like fish 2.Cats eat everything they like 3.Ziggy is a cat Example from Tuomas CMU

Cat(Ziggy) Likes(Ziggy,Fish) Eats(Ziggy,Fish) Cat(x) ⇒ Likes(x,Fish)  = {x/Ziggy} Cat(x) ∧ Likes(x,y) ⇒ Eats(x,y)  = {x/Ziggy, y/Fish} Ziggy the cat eats the fish!

Example: Arms dealer (1) ∀ x (American(x) ∧ Weapon(y) ∧ Hostile(z) ∧ Sells(x,y,z) ⇒ Criminal(x)) (2) Owns(NoNo,M) (3) Missile(M) (4) ∀ x (Missile(x) ∧ Owns(NoNo,x) ⇒ Sells(West,x,NoNo)) (5) ∀ x (Missile(x) ⇒ Weapon(x)) (6) ∀ x (Enemy(x,America) ⇒ Hostile(x)) (7) American(West) (8) Enemy(NoNo,America) KB in Horn Form

Example: Arms dealer (1) ∀ x (American(x) ∧ Weapon(y) ∧ Hostile(z) ∧ Sells(x,y,z) ⇒ Criminal(x)) (2) Owns(NoNo,M) (3) Missile(M) (4) ∀ x (Missile(x) ∧ Owns(NoNo,x) ⇒ Sells(West,x,NoNo)) (5) ∀ x (Missile(x) ⇒ Weapon(x)) (6) ∀ x (Enemy(x,America) ⇒ Hostile(x)) (7) American(West) (8) Enemy(NoNo,America) KB in Horn Form Facts

Owns(NoNo,M)Missile(M)American(West)Enemy(NoNo,America) Forward chaining: Arms dealer Hostile(NoNo) Enemy(x,America) ⇒ Hostile(x)  = {x/NoNo} Sells(West,M,NoNo)Weapon(M) Missile(x) ⇒ Weapon(x)  = {x/M} Missile(x) ∧ Owns(NoNo,x) ⇒ Sells(West,x,NoNo)  = {x/M} Criminal(West) American(x) ∧ Weapon(y) ∧ Hostile(z) ∧ Sells(x,y,z) ⇒ Criminal(x)  = {x/West, y/M, z/NoNo} Forward chaining generates all inferences (also irrelevant ones) We have proved that West is a criminal

Example: Financial advisor KB in Horn Form 1)SavingsAccount(Inadequate) ⇒ Investments(Bank) 2)SavingsAccount(Adequate) ∧ Income(Adequate) ⇒ Investments(Stocks) 3)SavingsAccount(Adequate) ∧ Income(Inadequate) ⇒ Investments(Mixed) 4)∀ x (AmountSaved(x) ∧ ∃ y (Dependents(y) ∧ Greater(x,MinSavings(y))) ⇒ SavingsAccount(Adequate)) 5)∀ x (AmountSaved(x) ∧ ∃ y (Dependents(y) ∧ ¬ Greater(x,MinSavings(y))) ⇒ SavingsAccount(Inadequate)) 6)∀ x (Earnings(x,Steady) ∧ ∃ y (Dependents(y) ∧ Greater(x,MinIncome(y))) ⇒ Income(Adequate)) 7)∀ x (Earnings(x,Steady) ∧ ∃ y (Dependents(y) ∧ ¬ Greater(x,MinIncome(y))) ⇒ Income(Inadequate)) 8)∀ x (Earnings(x,UnSteady) ⇒ Income(Inadequate)) 9)AmountSaved($22000) 10)Earnings($25000,Steady) 11)Dependents(3) Example from G.F. Luger, ”Artificial Intelligence” 2002 MinSavings(x) ≡ $5000 x MinIncome(x) ≡ $ ($4000 x)

Dependents(3)Earnings($25000,Steady)AmountSaved($22000) MinIncome = $27000 MinSavings = $15000 ¬ Greater($25000,MinIncome) Income(Inadequate) SavingsAccount(Adequate) Greater($22000,MinSavings) Investments(Mixed) FC financial advisor

FOL CNF (Conjunctive Normal Form) Literal = (possibly negated) atomic sentence, e.g., ¬ Rich(Me) Clause = disjunction of literals, e.g. ¬ Rich(Me) ∨ Unhappy(Me) The KB is a conjunction of clauses Any FOL KB can be converted to CNF as follows: 1.Replace (P ⇒ Q) by ( ¬ P ∨ Q) (implication elimination) 2.Move ¬ inwards, e.g., ¬∀ x P(x) becomes ∃ x ¬ P(x) 3.Standardize variables apart, e.g., ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ x Q(x)) becomes ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ y Q(y)) 4.Move quantifiers left, e.g., ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ y Q(y)) becomes ∀ x ∃ y (P(x) ∨ Q(y)) 5.Eliminate ∃ by Skolemization 6.Drop universal quantifiers 7.Distribute ∧ over ∨, e.g., (P ∧ Q) ∨ R becomes (P ∨ R) ∧ (Q ∨ R) Slide from S. Russel

CNF example ∀ x [ ∀ y Animal(y) ⇒ Loves(x,y)] ⇒ ∃ y Loves(y,x) Implication elimination ∀ x ¬ [ ∀ y ¬ Animal(y) ∨ Loves(x,y)] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) Move ¬ inwards ( ¬∀ y P becomes ∃ y ¬ P) ∀ x [ ∃ y ¬ ( ¬ Animal(y) ∨ Loves(x,y))] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) ∀ x [ ∃ y (Animal(y) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,y))] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) ∀ x [ ∃ y Animal(y) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,y)] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) Standardize variables individually ∀ x [ ∃ y Animal(y) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,y)] ∨ ∃ z Loves(z,x) Skolemize (Replace ∃ with constants) ∀ x [Animal(F(x)) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,F(x))] ∨ Loves(G(x),x) Why not ∀ x [Animal(A) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,A)] ∨ Loves(B,x) ?? Drop ∀ [Animal(F(x)) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,F(x))] ∨ Loves(G(x),x) Distribute ∨ over ∧ [Animal(F(x)) ∨ Loves(G(x),x)] ∧ [ ¬ Loves(x,F(x)) ∨ Loves(G(x),x)] ”Everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone”

CNF example ∀ x [ ∀ y Animal(y) ⇒ Loves(x,y)] ⇒ ∃ y Loves(y,x) Implication elimination ∀ x ¬ [ ∀ y ¬ Animal(y) ∨ Loves(x,y)] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) Move ¬ inwards ( ¬∀ y P becomes ∃ y ¬ P) ∀ x [ ∃ y ¬ ( ¬ Animal(y) ∨ Loves(x,y))] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) ∀ x [ ∃ y (Animal(y) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,y))] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) ∀ x [ ∃ y Animal(y) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,y)] ∨ ∃ y Loves(y,x) Standardize variables individually ∀ x [ ∃ y Animal(y) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,y)] ∨ ∃ z Loves(z,x) Skolemize (Replace ∃ with constants) ∀ x [Animal(F(x)) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,F(x))] ∨ Loves(G(x),x) Why not ∀ x [Animal(A) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,A)] ∨ Loves(B,x) ?? Drop ∀ [Animal(F(x)) ∧ ¬ Loves(x,F(x))] ∨ Loves(G(x),x) Distribute ∨ over ∧ [Animal(F(x)) ∨ Loves(G(x),x)] ∧ [ ¬ Loves(x,F(x)) ∨ Loves(G(x),x)] ”Everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone” The lower (green) sentence says that everyone (x) either fails to love one particular animal (A) or is loved by one particular person (B). However, the original sentence (above) says that everyone could either fail to love an animal, different for different people, or be loved by someone, different for different people. Therefore we introduce Skolem functions F(x) and G(x) that depend on the individual (x).

Notation: Unification Unify(p,q) =  means that Subst(,p) = Subst(,q)

FOL resolution inference rule First-order literals are complementary if one unifies with the negation of the other Where Unify( l i, ¬ m j ) = . [Animal(F(x)) ∨ Loves(G(x),x)], [ ¬ Loves(u,v) ∨ ¬ Kills(u,v)] Subst({u/G(x),v/x}, [Animal(F(x)) ∨ ¬ Kills(u,v)]) Which produces resolvent [Animal(F(x)) ∨ ¬ Kills(G(x),x)] Note that l i and m j are removed

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ Start from the top

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ ∀ x (American(x) ∧ Weapon(y) ∧ Hostile(z) ∧ Sells(x,y,z) ⇒ Criminal(x)) Translate to CNF: ∀ x ( ¬ (American(x) ∧ Weapon(y) ∧ Hostile(z) ∧ Sells(x,y,z)) ∨ Criminal(x)) ∀ x (( ¬ American(x) ∨ ¬ Weapon(y) ∨ ¬ Hostile(z) ∨ ¬ Sells(x,y,z)) ∨ Criminal(x)) ∀ x ( ¬ American(x) ∨ ¬ Weapon(y) ∨ ¬ Hostile(z) ∨ ¬ Sells(x,y,z) ∨ Criminal(x)) ¬ American(x) ∨ ¬ Weapon(y) ∨ ¬ Hostile(z) ∨ ¬ Sells(x,y,z) ∨ Criminal(x) Any FOL KB can be converted to CNF as follows: 1. Replace (P ⇒ Q) by (¬P ∨ Q) (implication elimination) 2. Move ¬ inwards, e.g., ¬ ∀ x P(x) becomes ∃ x ¬P(x) 3. Standardize variables apart, e.g., ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ x Q(x)) becomes ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ y Q(y)) 4. Move quantifiers left, e.g., ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ y Q(y)) becomes ∀ x ∃ y (P(x) ∨ Q(y)) 5. Eliminate ∃ by Skolemization 6. Drop universal quantifiers 7. Distribute ∧ over ∨, e.g., (P ∧ Q) ∨ R becomes (P ∨ R) ∧ (Q ∨ R)

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ ∀ x (American(x) ∧ Weapon(y) ∧ Hostile(z) ∧ Sells(x,y,z) ⇒ Criminal(x)) Translate to CNF: ∀ x ( ¬ (American(x) ∧ Weapon(y) ∧ Hostile(z) ∧ Sells(x,y,z)) ∨ Criminal(x)) ∀ x (( ¬ American(x) ∨ ¬ Weapon(y) ∨ ¬ Hostile(z) ∨ ¬ Sells(x,y,z)) ∨ Criminal(x)) ∀ x ( ¬ American(x) ∨ ¬ Weapon(y) ∨ ¬ Hostile(z) ∨ ¬ Sells(x,y,z) ∨ Criminal(x)) ¬ American(x) ∨ ¬ Weapon(y) ∨ ¬ Hostile(z) ∨ ¬ Sells(x,y,z) ∨ Criminal(x) Any FOL KB can be converted to CNF as follows: 1. Replace (P ⇒ Q) by (¬P ∨ Q) (implication elimination) 2. Move ¬ inwards, e.g., ¬ ∀ x P(x) becomes ∃ x ¬P(x) 3. Standardize variables apart, e.g., ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ x Q(x)) becomes ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ y Q(y)) 4. Move quantifiers left, e.g., ( ∀ x P(x) ∨ ∃ y Q(y)) becomes ∀ x ∃ y (P(x) ∨ Q(y)) 5. Eliminate ∃ by Skolemization 6. Drop universal quantifiers 7. Distribute ∧ over ∨, e.g., (P ∧ Q) ∨ R becomes (P ∨ R) ∧ (Q ∨ R)

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ Where Unify( l i, ¬ m j ) = .

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ l 1 = ¬ American(x) l 2 = ¬ Weapon(y) l 3 = ¬ Sells(x,y,z) l 4 = ¬ Hostile(z) l 5 = Criminal(x) m 1 = Criminal(West) Where Unify( l i, ¬ m j ) = . Unify( l 5, ¬ m 1 ) =  = {x/West} Subst(   l 1 ∨ l 2 ∨ l 3 ∨ l 4 ) =...

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ l 1 = ¬ American(x) l 2 = ¬ Weapon(y) l 3 = ¬ Sells(x,y,z) l 4 = ¬ Hostile(z) l 5 = Criminal(x) m 2 = American(West) Unify( l 1, ¬ m 2 ) =  = {x/West} Subst(   l 2 ∨ l 3 ∨ l 4 ) =...

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ ?

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ l 2 = ¬ Weapon(y) l 3 = ¬ Sells(x,y,z) l 4 = ¬ Hostile(z) m 3 = Weapon(x) m 4 = Missile(x) Unify( l 2, ¬ m 3 ) =  = {y/x} Subst(   l 2 ∨ l 3 ∨ l 4 ∨ m 4 ) =...

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ ?

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬

Resolution proves KB ⊨  by proving (KB ∧ ¬  ) is unsatisfiable Arms dealer example ¬ ∅

Resolution example II Problem Statement: Tony, Shikuo and Ellen belong to the Hoofers Club. Every member of the Hoofers Club is either a skier or a mountain climber or both. No mountain climber likes rain, and all skiers like snow. Ellen dislikes whatever Tony likes and likes whatever Tony dislikes. Tony likes rain and snow. Query: Is there a member of the Hoofers Club who is a mountain climber but not a skier? Example from Charles Dyer (referenced by Tuomas CMU)

KB The rules only apply to members of the Hoofers club (our domain). Problem Statement: Tony, Shikuo and Ellen belong to the Hoofers Club. Every member of the Hoofers Club is either a skier or a mountain climber or both. No mountain climber likes rain, and all skiers like snow. Ellen dislikes whatever Tony likes and likes whatever Tony dislikes. Tony likes rain and snow.

Query Query: Is there a member of the Hoofers Club who is a mountain climber but not a skier?

KB + the negation of the Query

(KB ∧¬ Q) to Clause form...(I)

(KB ∧¬ Q) to Clause form...(II)

(KB ∧¬ Q) to Clause form...(III)

(KB ∧¬ Q) to Clause form...(IV)

(KB ∧¬ Q) in Clause form We drop the universal quantifiers... But introduce different notation to keep better track...

Unify( p 4, ¬ p 11 ) =  = {x/s} The resolvent becomes our clause # 12

Unify( p 6, ¬ p 12 ) =  = {x/z} The resolvent becomes our clause # 13

Unify( p 10, ¬ p 8 ) =  = {v/Snow} The resolvent becomes our clause # 14

Unify( p 13, ¬ p 14 ) =  = {x/Ellen} We have proved that there is a member of the Hoofers club who is a mountain climber but not a skier.