1 CHAPTER 3 Certainty Equivalents from Utility Theory.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
Copyright © 2008 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin Managerial Economics, 9e Managerial Economics Thomas Maurice.
Advertisements

Economics of Information (ECON3016)
From risk to opportunity Lecture 11 John Hey and Carmen Pasca.
Decision Analysis (Decision Tables, Utility)
Treatments of Risks and Uncertainty in Projects The availability of partial or imperfect information about a problem leads to two new category of decision-making.
Module C1 Decision Models Uncertainty. What is a Decision Analysis Model? Decision Analysis Models is about making optimal decisions when the future is.
Utility Theory.
Chapter 8: Decision Analysis
1 1 Slide © 2009 South-Western, a part of Cengage Learning Slides by John Loucks St. Edward’s University.
1 Decision Making and Utility Introduction –The expected value criterion may not be appropriate if the decision is a one-time opportunity with substantial.
Introduction to Decision Analysis
Chapter 18 Statistical Decision Theory Copyright © 2010 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Prentice Hall Statistics for Business and Economics 7 th.
Chapter 21 Statistical Decision Theory
1 Demand for Health Insurance. 2 Which Investment will you pick Expected Value $2600 Choice 2 $5000 -$ Choice 1 $5000 $
DSC 3120 Generalized Modeling Techniques with Applications
Choices Involving Risk
Risk Attitude Dr. Yan Liu
Part 3 Probabilistic Decision Models
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2011 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved.
Lecture 4 Environmental Cost - Benefit - Analysis under risk and uncertainty.
McGraw-Hill/Irwin Copyright © 2013 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty.
Notes: Use this cover page for internal presentations The Behavioural Components Of Risk Aversion Greg B Davies University College.
Chapter 13 Risk Attitudes ..
Utility Axioms Axiom: something obvious, cannot be proven Utility axioms (rules for clear thinking)
CHAPTER 14 Utility Axioms Paradoxes & Implications.
1 Utility Theory. 2 Option 1: bet that pays $5,000,000 if a coin flipped comes up tails you get $0 if the coin comes up heads. Option 2: get $2,000,000.
Judgment and Decision Making in Information Systems Utility Functions, Utility Elicitation, and Risk Attitudes Yuval Shahar, M.D., Ph.D.
Certainty Equivalent and Stochastic Preferences June 2006 FUR 2006, Rome Pavlo Blavatskyy Wolfgang Köhler IEW, University of Zürich.
Converting Risk Preferences into Money Equivalents with Quadratic Programming AEC 851 – Agribusiness Operations Management Spring, 2006.
Decision making and economics. Economic theories Economic theories provide normative standards Expected value Expected utility Specialized branches like.

Multi-Attribute Utility Models with Interactions
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior
PREFERENCES AND UTILITY
Making Decisions Under Uncertainty
Extensions to Consumer theory Inter-temporal choice Uncertainty Revealed preferences.
Decision Trees and Utility Theory
Risk Aversion and Capital Allocation to Risky Assets
8-1 CHAPTER 8 Decision Analysis. 8-2 LEARNING OBJECTIVES 1.List the steps of the decision-making process and describe the different types of decision-making.
Copyright © 2005 by the McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. McGraw-Hill/Irwin Managerial Economics Thomas Maurice eighth edition Chapter 15.
Decision making Making decisions Optimal decisions Violations of rationality.
Agata Michalaszek Warsaw School of Social Psychology Information search patterns in risk judgment and in risky choices.
TOPIC THREE Chapter 4: Understanding Risk and Return By Diana Beal and Michelle Goyen.
Chapter 15 Risk Analysis. Frequency definition of probability zGiven a situation in which a number of possible outcomes might occur, the probability of.
Decision Making Under Uncertainty and Risk 1 By Isuru Manawadu B.Sc in Accounting Sp. (USJP), ACA, AFM
Microeconomics 2 John Hey. Chapters 23, 24 and 25 CHOICE UNDER RISK Chapter 23: The Budget Constraint. Chapter 24: The Expected Utility Model. Chapter.
1 Chapter 7 Applying Simulation to Decision Problems.
Chapter 5 Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior. ©2005 Pearson Education, Inc.Chapter 52 Q: Value of Stock Investment in offshore drilling exploration: Two.
Chapter 5 Choice Under Uncertainty. Chapter 5Slide 2 Topics to be Discussed Describing Risk Preferences Toward Risk Reducing Risk The Demand for Risky.
Choice under uncertainty Assistant professor Bojan Georgievski PhD 1.
Decision theory under uncertainty
Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior Chapter 5. Uncertainty and Consumer Behavior 1.In order to compare the riskiness of alternative choices, we need to.
© 2005 Pearson Education Canada Inc Chapter 17 Choice Making Under Uncertainty.
Making Simple Decisions Utility Theory MultiAttribute Utility Functions Decision Networks The Value of Information Summary.
Fundamentals of Decision Theory Chapter 16 Mausam (Based on slides of someone from NPS, Maria Fasli)
1 Systems Analysis Methods Dr. Jerrell T. Stracener, SAE Fellow SMU EMIS 5300/7300 NTU SY-521-N NTU SY-521-N SMU EMIS 5300/7300 Utility Theory Applications.
Money and Banking Lecture 11. Review of the Previous Lecture Application of Present Value Concept Internal Rate of Return Bond Pricing Real Vs Nominal.
Decision making under uncertainty
DADSS Lecture 11: Decision Analysis with Utility Elicitation and Use.
Cost-Volume-Profit Analysis
Decisions under uncertainty and risk
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
CHAPTER 1 FOUNDATIONS OF FINANCE I: EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY
Supplement: Decision Making
Choices Involving Risk
Making Decisions Under Uncertainty
Chapter 15 Decisions under Risk and Uncertainty
Behavioral Finance Economics 437.
Chapter 15: Decisions Under Risk and Uncertainty
Presentation transcript:

1 CHAPTER 3 Certainty Equivalents from Utility Theory

Certainty Equivalents w Suppose you had 2 choices: w a 1. Flip a fair coin Heads: you get $500, Tails: you get nothing w a 2. $200 for certain: price for selling a 1 w  p(  )a 1 a 2 Heads Tails w Your sale price of a 1 is its certainty equivalence

3 Certainty Equivalents Definition w A certain payoff which has the same value to the decision maker as an uncertain payoff w a 1. Uncertain payoff: Heads: +$500, Tails: 0 w a 2. Certain payoff: $X w If X = 0, you will prefer a 1 w If X = 500, you will prefer a 2 w Certainty Equivalent: Value of X (0  X  500) that makes a 1 = a 2

4 Determining & Using CE In general, given 2 choices: w a 1. $X with probability p, or $Y with prob. (1 – p) w a 2. $Z for certain (X  Z  Y) w The value of Z that makes the 2 options equal to decision maker is the: Certainty equivalent of a 1 : CE(a 1 ) w Stochastic problems can be transformed to deterministic equivalent w Criterion: select option a j with maximum CE(a j )

5 Making Decisions based on CE w Given 4 choices depending on flipping a fair coin w  p(  )a 1 a 2 a 3 a 4 Heads Tails0.50 – CE w a 1 is chosen under minimax regret w a 2 is chosen under max EV (but highest risk) w a 3 is chosen under max certainty equivalent (combines expected value with risk) w a 4 is chosen under maximin

6 Certainty Equivalents & Coherence w The concept of CE provides a coherent approach for evaluating (ranking) decisions w A valid criterion must recommend ranking consistent with the CE options w A coherent criterion must provide the same score for an uncertain option and its certainty equivalent

7 CE & Coherence Counter-Example w Given: Option a j has CE(a j ) = y*, but Under criterion C, score C(a j )  C(y*) w We can find y’ such that: C(a j ) = C(y’),y’ > y* w Decision maker (DM) will pay to replace y* by y’ w Next, since C(a j ) = C(y’), DM will not mind switching from y’ to a j. w Next, since y* = CE(a j ), DM will not mind switching from a j to y*

8 CE & Coherence Counter-Example w Example shows that an incoherent criterion makes DM a perpetual money-making machine w For coherence:y’ = y* w Any evaluation criterion must be subjected to this coherence test w Can we use only CE criterion for all decision problems? No, only for simple 2-outcome problems

9 CE for complex problems w Given:  p(  )a 1 Excellent0.110,000 Good0.35,000 Average0.31,000 Poor0.2 – 400 Terrible0.1 – 3,000 w Evaluating CE(a 1 ) is extremely difficult w Utility theory is used for complex problems

Utility Functions w Utility: Relative value (worth) of each payoff to the decision maker w Utility Theory: Transform payoffs into utility scale (0  1) w Utility & Coherence: Expected utility criterion EU(a j ) ranking of options is consistent with DM certainty equivalents EU(a j )

11 Evaluating utility functions w Given:  p(  )a 1 a 2 Good0.3$1000$800 Average0.4$500$600 Poor0.3$300$400 w Min payoff = $300, Max payoff = $1000 w Range of payoffs (300  1000) U(300)= 0 U(1000)= 1

12 Evaluating utility functions w What is CE for: (p = 0.5 of $300, and p = 0.5 of $1000)? w Assume CE = $500 U(500) = 0.5*U(300) + 0.5*U(1000) = 0.5 w For (p = 0.5 of $300, and p = 0.5 of $500) Assume CE = $375 U(375) = 0.5*U(300) + 0.5*U(500) = 0.25 w If equal prob of 500 & 1000 has CE = 700, we get: U(700) = 0.75

13 Evaluating utility functions w y w U(y) y

14 Converting payoffs to utilities w Utility matrix, using interpolation:  p(  )a 1 a 2 Good Average Poor EU w Since U(375) = 0.25 & U(500) = 0.5 U(400) = [( )/( )]*( ) = 0.3  w Based on EU, choose a 2

15 Steps in using utility functions 1. Derive the utility function using simple CE questions 2. Transform payoffs into utilities 3. Choose decision with max expected utility

16 Utility Ex 1: Oil exploration w Decisions: Alternative investment strategies in oil exploration w To evaluate utility, 2 options: a 1. Invest $X to explore for oil prob p: you get $Y, prob (1 – p): you get 0 a 2. Do not invest w What probability p would make you indifferent?

17 Utility Ex 2: Education planning w Decisions: Alternative reading improvement programs w Payoff: Average reading performance w Utility function changes slope around national average (50%) Risk = doing worse than national average Shape of utility function indicates risk attitude

Risk Attitudes w Given 2 choices: w  p(  )a 1 a 2 Heads Tails w If 2 options are equivalent to you, i.e., CE(a 1 ) = 200, then CE(a 1 ) = 200 < EV(a 1 ) = 250 w You considered are risk averse (avoider)

19 Risk Premium w Risk Premium Money DM is willing to pay to avoid uncertainty (risk) RP(y)= EV(y) – CE(y) = 250 – 200 = 50 w 3 risk attitudes: Risk-Averse:RP(y) > 0 Risk-Neutral:RP(y) = 0 Risk-Seeking:RP(y) < 0

20 Risk-Neutral Utility Function Straight line: EV(y) = CE(y) RP(y) = constant U’(y) = 1,U’’(y) = 0 U(y) 1 0 y y min y max

21 Risk-Averse Utility Function Concave line: EV(y) > CE(y) RP(y) > 0 U’(y) > 0,U’’(y)  0 U(y) 1 y y min y max

22 Risk-Seeking Utility Function Convex line: EV(y) < CE(y) RP(y) < 0 U’(y) > 0,U’’(y)  0 U(y) 1 y y min y max

23 Risk Attitude Example w Given 2 options: w a 1. Uncertain payoff: Heads: +$500, Tails: 0 w a 2. Certain payoff: $X What value of X would make 2 options equivalent? w Risk averse:X = 200RP = 50 w Risk neutral:X = 250RP = 0 w Risk seeking:X = 300RP = – 50

24 Applications of Risk Attitude w Risk Aversion Most common approach in significant decisions w Risk neutrality Corresponds to expected value criterion. Should be used in routine, non-significant decisions w Risk attitude may: - change over time - increase with increasing capital

25 Risk Attitude vs. payoff range y w A payoff consists of both: Certain amounty Uncertain amount   << y, mean = 0, variance =   2, w RP(  + y) = EV(  + y) – CE(  + y) = y – CE(  + y) w Risk attitude is: Decreasing if RP(  +y) decreases as y increases constant if RP(  +y) is constant as y increases Increasing if RP(  +y) increases as y increases

26 Risk Attitude vs. payoff range y w Constant risk attitude (premium) Constantly risk-averse U(y) = a – be – ry,r > 0,a & b constants Constantly risk-neutral U(y) = a + by,a & b constants Constantly risk-averse U(y) = a + be – ry,r < 0,a & b constants

27 Risk Attitude vs. payoff range y w Decreasing risk attitude Risk aversion (premium) decreases with increasing capital U(y) = – e – ay – be – cy,a > 0,bc > 0 w Decreasing risk attitude Risk aversion (premium) proportional to y RP(  + y) = a + by

28 Risk Aversion Function w r(y) = – U’’(y)/U’(y) w RP(  + y)  0.5   2 r(y) w Example Given: U(y) = a + by – cy 2, b, c > 0, 0 < y < b/2c U’(y) = b – 2cy U’’(y) = – 2c r(y) = 2c/(b – 2cy) RP(  + y) = c   2 /(b – 2cy) > 0 (increasing risk attitude)

Theoretical Assumptions of Utility w Preceding sections: How utility works w This section: Why utility works Theoretical basis Basic assumptions

30 Notation w Prospect A j n payoffs, Y i, each with probability p ji, i = 1…n payoffY 1 Y 2… Y n probabilityp j1 p j2… p jn A j = (p j1, Y 1 ; p j2, Y 2 ; … ; p jn, Y n )

31 Notation w Compound Prospect C k m prospects, A j, each with probability q kj, j = 1…m prospectA 1 A 2… A m probabilityq k1 q k2… q km C k = (q k1, A 1 ; q k2, A 2 ; … ; q km, A m )

32 Notation example w A 1 : fair coin Heads (p 11 = 0.5)  Y 1 = 20 Tails: (p 12 = 0.5)  Y 2 = – 10 w A 2 : bent coin Heads (p 21 = 0.3)  Y 1 = 20 Tails: (p 22 = 0.7)  Y 2 = – 10 w C 1 : fair die even: 2, 4, 6 (q 11 = 0.5)  A 1 Odd: 1, 3, 5 (q 12 = 0.5)  A 2

33 Assumption 1 (Structure) w It is sufficient to describe the choices open to the decision maker in terms of payoff values and their associated probabilities w Reducing the problem to prospects and compound prospects captures all that is essential to the decision maker w Temporal resolution of uncertainty: The decision maker may choose between 2 alternatives with exactly the same payoffs and probabilities based on different payoff times

34 Assumption 2 (Ordering) w The decision maker may express preference or indifference between any pair of payoffs w Notation Y 1 > Y 2  Y 1 is preferred to Y 2 Y 1  Y 2  Y 1 is preferred to or same as Y 2 Y 2 is not preferred to Y 1 Y* = best payoff,Y * = worst payoff w Transitivity: If A 1  A 2 andA 2  A 3 thenA 1  A 3

35 Assumption 3 (Reduction of Compound Prospects) w Any compound prospect should be indifferent to its equivalent simple prospect C k  (q k1, A 1 ; q k2, A 2 ; … ; q km, A m )  [q k1 (p 11, Y 1 ; p 12, Y 2 ; … ; p 1n, Y n ); q k2 (p 21, Y 1 ; p 22, Y 2 ; … ; p 2n, Y n );... q km (p m1, Y 1 ; p m2, Y 2 ; … ; p mn, Y n )]  (p' k1, Y 1 ; p' k2, Y 2 ; … ; p' km, Y m ) Where p' kj = q k1 p 1j + q k2 p 2j q km p mj

36 Assumption 3 example w C 1 : fair die q 1j A j p 1j Y 1 p 2j Y 2 q 11 = 0.5  A 1 : fair coin –10 q 12 = 0.5  A 2 : bent coin –10 w C 1  (0.5, A 1 ; 0.5, A 2 )  [0.5(0.5, 20; 0.5, –10); 0.5(0.3, 20; 0.7, –10)]  [( ), 20; ( ), –10]  [0.4, 20; 0.6, –10]

37 Assumption 3 & Coherence w Assumption 3 indicates ideal level of coherence w No preference for single or multiple steps w Assumption 3 does not apply if Preference for multiple steps, game atmosphere Special type of risk in a particular business

38 Assumption 4 (Continuity) w Every payoff Y i can be considered a certainty equivalent for a prospect: [u i, Y*; (1 – u i ), Y * ], 0  u i  1 Y* = best payoff, Y * = worst payoff w Since each uncertain prospect has an equivalent certain payoff (CE), w then each certain payoff has an equivalent uncertain prospect

39 Assumption 4 (Continuity) w Since Y i = CE of: A i  [u i, Y*; (1 – u i ), Y * ], 0  u i  1 Y* = best payoff, Y * = worst payoff w u i (Y i )= probability of Y* that makes A i  Y i w u i (Y*)= 1for max payoff w u i (Y * )= 0 for min payoff w u i (Y i )= utility of payoff Y i

40 Assumption 5 (Substitutability) w In any prospect, Y i can be substituted by its a uncertain equivalent: [u i, Y*; (1 – u i ), Y * ] w Y i and [u i, Y*; (1 – u i ), Y * ] are indifferent, not only when considered alone, but also when considered part of a more complicated prospect w Similar to coherence related to minimax regret: ranking of alternatives should not change if other alternatives are added

41 Assumption 6 (Transitivity of Prospects) w The decision maker can express preference or indifference between all pairs of prospects. w Extension of Assumption 2 (payoff preference) w Any prospect can be expressed in terms of Y* & Y * A 1  (p 11, Y 1 ; p 12, Y 2 ; … ; p 1n, Y n )  (p 11, [u 1, Y*; (1 – u 1 ), Y * ];... )  (p 1, Y*; p 2, Y * ) Where p 1 = p 11 u 1 + p 12 u p 1n u n

42 Assumption 7 ( Monotonicity) w A prospect A r  [p r, Y*; (1 – p r ), Y * ] is preferred or indifferent to (  ) prospect A s  [p s, Y*; (1 – p s ), Y * ] iff: p r  p s w Given 2 options with the same 2 alternative payoffs, we prefer the option with higher probability of the better payoff w For options with several payoffs: A r  A s iff: p r1 u 1 + p r2 u p r1 u n  p s1 u 1 + p s2 u p s1 u n EU(A r )  EU(A s )

Some Caveats in Interpreting Utility w Utility theory is normative: It suggests what people should do to be coherent Does not describe what they actually do w In practice, people violate expected utility criterion depending on circumstances

44 Utilities do not add up w Expected utility of a sum of payoff is not equal to sum of expected utilities U(A + B)  U(A) + U(B) w Unless the decision maker is risk-neutral

45 Utility differences do not express strength of preferences w Given: Y 1 > Y 2 > Y 3 > Y 4, and U(Y 1 – Y 2 ) > U(Y 3 – Y 4 ) This does not imply moving from Y 2 to Y 1 is preferable to moving from Y 4 to Y 3. w Utility provides an “ordinal” scale, not an “interval” scale Ordinal: teacher evaluation, (7 – 6)  (9 – 8) Interval: weight in kilograms, (60 – 50) = (80 – 70)

46 Utilities are not comparable from person to person w If 2 people assign the same utility to a prospect, we cannot say it has the same worth to each w Utility values are completely subjective w Utilities of different people cannot be added to determine group preferences

Issues in the assessment of risk w Utility assessment is not a natural activity for DM w Unnatural setup may results in wrong utility values, and wrong decisions w Method of assessment must be as close as possible to real problem

48 Basic utility assessment process w Given 2 options: X  certain payoff Y  probability p of payoff G (gain) probability (1 – p) of payoff L (loss) w Four variables X, Y, G, L Fix any 3 variables, ask DM to supply the 4 th

49 4 Response modes w Certainty equivalence: DM gives X w Probability equivalence: DM gives p w Gain equivalence: DM gives G w Loss equivalence: DM gives L w First 2 methods most common

50 Level of probabilty w 4 variables: X, p, G, L w Except in probability equivalence methods, p is given w Small probabilities get distorted w p = 1 – p = 0.5 seems to be least biased

51 Levels of payoff w Initial G and L are Y max and Y min, but values inside interval are arbitrary w Moving from outside to inside creates bias to risk aversion w Adjustment bias A new assessment is made by adjusting the previous one, this adjustment is not enough w Solution: get assessments at different times

52 Assumptions or transfer of risk w If both G and L are losses, the question is: Facing either a loss of G (prob. p) or a loss of L (prob. 1 – p), how much would you pay to have it removed? Transfer uncertain (risky) loss to a certain loss w Inertia bias: Tendency to stay with current situation unless alternative is clearly better

53 Utility bias (Allais problem ) w Allais problem (Exercise 2.8) a 1 = $1M a 2 = (0.1, $5M; 0.89, $1M; 0.1, $0) a 3 = (0.1, $5M; 0.9, $0) a 4 = (0.11, $1M; 0.89, $0) w Compare a 1 to a 2, and a 3 to a 4,

54 Allais problem w Most people: a 1 > a 2, a 3 > a 4, w Incoherent based on expected utility U(0) = Y min = 0,U(5) = Y max = 1 EU(a 1 ) = U(1) EU(a 2 ) = U(1) w If a 1 > a 2, U(1) > U(1) 0.11U(1) > 0.1

55 Allais problem EU(a 3 ) = 0.1 EU(a 4 ) = 0.11U(1) w If a 3 > a 4, 0.1 > 0.11U(1) This contradicts the result for a 1 > a 2,

56 Certainty effect w Reason for inconsistency in Allais example w People overestimate a certain payoff compared to expected utility w Expected utility should not be taken for granted Consistency checks Sensitivity analysis Estimate utility to same no. of significant figures as payoff values Y