Politeness Lecture 11.

Slides:



Advertisements
Similar presentations
R ESTAURANT M ANAGEMENT (HM 432) CHAPTER 3 Communicating Effectively as a Leader and a Manager.
Advertisements

Politeness Theory and Discourse Lecture 7. Objectives After this lecture, students should be able to: 1.Explain the notions of politeness and face 2.Explain.
Support For Morality As A Social Contract
Research Methods for T&I Studies I Politeness Phenomena.
Telling lies * Things to think about * What are lies?
According to George Yule (1996) in his book “Pragmatics” the traditional linguists have no real social lives whereas the modern linguists tend to consider.
1 Chapter 9 Supporting Supporting Inter-Act, 13 th Edition Inter-Act, 13 th Edition.
Self – respect and Self – assertion Ms. Jayalakshmi R.
Review Exercises 1) Do the COMPONENTIAL analysis (not the compositional one) of the following words: hen b) rooster Componential analysis 2) Does ‘A’
The Cooperative Principle
1 MODULE 2 Meaning and discourse in English COOPERATION, POLITENESS AND FACE Lecture 14.
Moral Reasoning Making appropriate use of facts and opinions to decide the right thing to do Quotations from Jacob Needleman’s The American Soul A Crucial.
Talk in Life and Literature LO: to understand the basis of the question and the differences between crafted and ‘real’ talk.
Communicating Effectively
WRITING CRITIQUE GROUP GUIDELINES Writing responses to your group members’ work and receiving responses from others is the most important step in revising.
Face and Face Management Psychology of Language John R. Baldwin School of Communication--ISU.
360 Business Ethics Chapter 4. Moral facts derived from reason Reason has three properties that have bearing on moral facts understood as the outcomes.
1 RUNNING a CLASS (2) Pertemuan Matakuliah: G0454/Class Management & Education Media Tahun: 2006.
INTERVIEWER’S ROLE The interviewer occupies the central importance in NRHM evaluation because he/she collects information from respondents. The success.
Unit 9 The use of English (II). Review What are the three aspects of a speech act, according to John Searle? Use an example to illustrate. What are the.
Divine Principles for a Healthy Relationship Healthy relationships are a vital component of health and wellbeing. There is compelling evidence that strong.
Shaping Culture and Values
Peer pressure harassment manipulation assertive refusal skills passive aggressive.
POLITENESS SITI AGRI RIYANTI ARIEN HUSNA IRRA WAHIDIYATI TUTI HASTUTI.
Interpersonal Communication Politeness Theory Chris Lewis.
Politeness in language
Consolidating Grice, Brown & Levinson, and Goffman
Politeness Starter – How might Politeness be connected to English Language and Literature? Learning Objective – to explore Brown and Levinson’s politeness.
Brown and Livenson’s Politeness Theory.
The Concept of ‘Face’ – Brown and Levinson
S OLIDARITY AND P OLITENESS Drs. Liliek Soepriatmadji, M.Pd.
Politness and Face theory
Notes on Face & Politeness. Face and Facework Goffman Face: The positive social image we seek to maintain during interaction. Why is Goffman’s perspective.
1 The Purpose of Written Communication “Think now; write later”. ● Before one can begin to plan the “How”, he or she has to understand the “Why” of business.
POLITENESS Hanifa Rahmawati Bella Stita R. Firnantia Lara L. Weni Agustiningrum Dwi Esti J.N.
PRAGMATICS AND SOCIOCUTURAL NORMS. Sociocultural norms, such as how to express politeness in a given context, guide pragmatic expression. For example,
Safety On The Internet  Usage time  Locations that may be accessed  Parental controls  What information may be shared with others Online rules should.
Introduction to linguistics II
CHAPTER 8 SOLVING PROBLEMS.
 We have been considering ways in which we interpret the meaning of an utterance in terms of what the speaker intended to convey.  However, we have.
Making Inferences and Drawing Conclusions
Communication and Transitioning: From Our Eyes By Jennifer Lindner And BJ Gallagher PhD, CCC-SLP By Jennifer Lindner And BJ Gallagher PhD, CCC-SLP.
Politeness Principle. 1.Approaches to politeness: a review.
Business Ethics Lecture Rights and Duties 1.
Politeness & Speaking Style Discourse & Dialogue CS 359 November 15, 2001.
Direct Guidance Principles
Shaping Culture and Values
Presentation about pragmatic concepts Implicatures Presuppositions
UNIT 2 - IMPLICATURE.
ADRESS FORMS AND POLITENESS Second person- used when the subject of the verb in a sentence is the same as the individual to.
Lesson 2 People use many different ways to communicate their feelings. Writing a note Facial expressions Communication is critical to healthy relationships.
ETHICS in the WORKPLACE © 2012 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. Chapter 1 Welcome to Ethics.
Randolph Clarke Florida State University. Free will – or freedom of the will – is often taken to be a power of some kind.
Ethics.
FACE. Goffman’s Face Erving Goffman was intrigued by what lay behind everyday expressions such as ‘losing face’, ‘saving face’ and ‘being shamefaced’.
PRAGMATICS 3. CH 7: POLITENESS AND INTERACTION Arrange these in order of politeness: (least polite first) Set the table! Could you please set the table?
Principles of conversation
Politeness.
1 Intimacy and Distance in Relational Communication Looking Out, Looking In 12 th Edition  Chapter Summary Intimacy in Relationships Self-Disclosure in.
Principle of coversation
POLITENESS STRATEGIES: Taken from: BROWN AND LEVINSON (1987: ) POLITENESS: Some Universals in Language Usage.
MODULE 2 Meaning and discourse in English
POLITENESS PRINCIPLE:
PRAGMATICS 3.
POLITENESS AND INTERACTION
Politeness In Language
Sociological analysis of CC misunderstanding
Nofsinger. R., Everyday Conversation, Sage, 1991
Principle of coversation
Nofsinger. R., Everyday Conversation, Sage, 1991
Presentation transcript:

Politeness Lecture 11

Politeness A central concept in linguistic pragmatics is politeness. It has been suggested ( for example, R. Lakoff 1972, 1973; Brown and Levinson 1978; Leech 1980, 1983) that politeness is another level to conversational interaction besides the rules of the cooperative principle. Robin Lakoff (1977b) sees Grice’s rules as essentially rules of clarity, and proposes that there are two prior rules of ‘pragmatic competence’. These are: ‘Make yourself clear’ and ‘Be polite’.

Politeness She takes Grice’s maxims as an approximation, at least, of how you conform to the rule ‘Make yourself clear’, and proposes her own three rules of politeness (Lakoff, 1977:88): 1. Formality: don’t impose/remain aloof; 2. Hesitancy: give the addressee his options; 3. Equality or camaraderie: act as though you and the addressee were equal/make him feel good.

Politeness Lakoff (1977b:89) elaborates the second rule as ‘Permit addressee to decide his own options.’ It is not difficult to see how the operation of this rule could lead directly to the troublesome inference in ‘Henry likes apples or bananas’. If we imagine, for example, that Henry’s wife knows her host is about to serve fruit, she might well make this utterance, conveying and intending to convey that Henry is fond of both fruits; the host may select either option without fear of making a mistake.

Politeness In such a case, Henry’s wife can felicitously give the host the option only if either option will be successful, and that can only be true if Henry likes both fruits.

Politeness Leech’s view of politeness involves a set of politeness maxims analogous to Grice’s maxims. Among these are (Leech, 1983:132): TACT MAXIM: Minimize cost to other. Maximize benefit to other. GENEROSITY MAXIM: Minimize benefit to self. Maximize cost to self. APPROBATION MAXIM: Minimize dispraise of other. Maximize praise of other. MODESTY MAXIM: Minimize praise of self. Maximize dispraise of self.

Politeness These add up to ‘an essential asymmetry in polite behavior, in that whatever is a polite belief for the speaker tends to be an impolite belief for the hearer, and vice versa’ (Leech, 1983:169) Frequently cited examples first discussed by R. Lakoff (1972) are amenable to this general kind of analysis.

Politeness Lakoff pointed out that a hostess would be seen as polite if she said, ‘You must have some of this cake’, but very impolite if she said, ‘You may have some of this cake.’ On the face of it this is strange, since ordinarily you would think telling someone what they must do removes all other options, imposes on them, and is therefore impolite. On the other hand, granting permission, if one is in a position to do it, makes it possible for the hearer to do what he or she wants to do, and would seem polite, or at least considerate.

Politeness The answer hinges on the fact that the hostess is responsible for the quality of the cake. Offering the cake by placing an obligation on the hearer conforms nicely to the modesty maxim. By implying that she cannot assume that the guest will want the cake is a way in minimizing praise to herself. If the hostess had offered the cake by saying ‘You may have some of this cake’, she would have violated modesty by appearing to assume that the cake is so good that the guest naturally wants a piece of it, and is only waiting to get permission.

Politeness Leech’s politeness principle also seems to be applicable to the disjunction example in a natural way. One way that Henry’s wife can conform to the maxim of tact, minimizing the cost to the host, is by making sure no one has to go to any special trouble to supply just the fruit Henry likes. Whichever of the two fruits can be supplied with minimum difficulty will be satisfactory. This can only be really true if Henry likes both apples and bananas.

Brown and Levinson Perhaps the most thorough treatment of the concept of politeness is that of Brown and Levinson (1978). They have set out to develop an explicit model of politeness which will have validity across cultures. The general idea is to understand various strategies for interactional behavior based on the idea that people engage in rational behavior to achieve satisfaction of certain wants.

Brown and Levinson The wants related to politeness are the wants of face, ‘something that is emotionally invested, and that can be lost, maintained, or enhanced, and must be constantly attended to in interaction. The concept is directly related to the folk-expression ‘lose face’, which is about being embarrassed or humiliated. There are two kinds of face. One is ‘negative face’, or the rights to territories, freedom of action and freedom from imposition; essentially the want that your actions be not impeded by others.

Brown and Levinson The other is ‘positive face’, the positive consistent self-image that people have and want to be appreciated and approved of by at least some other people. The rational actions people take to preserve both kinds of face for themselves and the people they interact with essentially add up to politeness.

Brown and Levinson A strength of the Brown and Levinson approach over the rule-oriented presentations of politeness by Robin Lakoff and by Leech is that Brown and Levinson are attempting to explain politeness by deriving it from more fundamental notions of what it is to be a human being (being rational and having face wants). There are two advantages of this over normative or rule-based approaches.

Brown and Levinson First, norms are discoverable and valid within a particular culture and therefore not too useful in understanding a concept like politeness cross-culturally. Second, even to posit universal (not culture-particular) rules as arbitrary primitives is ‘to invent a problem to be explained, rather than to explain it’ (Brown and Levinson, 1978:91).

Brown and Levinson In other words, if you start with a set of rules like Leech’s maxim of politeness, you can understand politeness phenomena in terms of these rules, but you do not learn very much about why there should be such rules in the first place. Granted, Brown and Levinson ask us to accept at the start that people are rational and have two kinds of face wants, but this is a much deeper starting point for explanation than starting with rules designed specifically for politeness itself.

Brown and Levinson Face wants become a problem if we assume that certain kinds of actions are intrinsically face-threatening. Such acts may threaten the hearer’s negative face, like a request which, as an attempt to get someone else to do something that you want done, means that the recipient of the request is being impeded in pursuing what he or she wants to do. Others threaten hearers’ positive face: for instance, a contradiction or expression of disagreement, which means the speaker thinks there is something wrong with an opinion held by the hearer.

Brown and Levinson Even saying something irreverent or taboo threatens the hearer’s positive face, since it reveals that the speaker does not care about the hearer’s face as well as the hearer’s. The speaker’s negative face is jeopardized when he or she makes an offer in somewhat the same way as requests threaten the hearer’s negative face since, in carrying out the offer, he or she will be pursuing the hearer’s aims, not the speaker’s own.

Brown and Levinson Confessions, admissions of guilt, and apologies threaten the speaker’s positive face since they mean the speaker has done something the proper sort of person would not have done. Such nonspeaking acts as tripping or stumbling also threaten a person’s positive face; they reveal a certain incompetence in carrying out a basic action like walking. None the less there are times when actions like this are going to occur and at times they may be desirable or necessary.

Brown and Levinson In these cases, the rational person will look for ways of doing the act while minimizing the threat to face in one way or another. Brown and Levinson (1978:65) show us five ways a person can deal with a ‘face-threatening act’ (FTA). The greater the risk, the more appropriate the higher-numbered ways of dealing with it are.

Brown and Levinson without redressive action, baldly on record 2 positive politeness Do the FTA with redressive action 4. Off record 3 negative politeness 5. Do not do the FTA

Brown and Levinson But it will not do to minimize the risk too much, because that will imply that the act is more face threatening than it actually is. For example, if there is something that only someone else can do for you, and you really need it done, and you select 5, ‘Do not do the FTA’by refraining from asking your best friend to do it for you, you will hurt your friend’s feelings. Your friend could easily say, with a pained expression, ‘Don’t you think I would have done that for you?’

Brown and Levinson The meaning of the last of the five ways of dealing with a potential FTA is self-evident; you simply do not take the action that would threaten face. Doing an FTA ‘off the record’s is essentially dropping a hint, or otherwise trying to make the FTA salient while still keeping the possibility of denying that you ever intended an FTA more-or-less open.

Brown and Levinson For example, if you say ‘Gosh, I’m out of money. I forgot to go the bank’, your companion might take it that you want a loan. But if your companion responds by saying, ‘Sorry, I’d like to help you out, but I’m a little short of cash myself’, you could still say, ‘Oh, I didn’t mean I wanted you to lend me money!’

Brown and Levinson ‘On the record’ FTAs with negative politeness redress are instances in which the FTA is undeniably made, but something else is said or done to show concern for the other person’s freedom of action and right not to be imposed upon. One of the most straightforward ways of doing this is simply to express reluctance to impose: ‘I hate to impose, but would you do something for me?’

Brown and Levinson Brown and Levinson suggest that the use in many languages of the plural form of ‘you’ as a deferential form , as we saw in chapter 1, has its origins in negative politeness redress. One possible explanation, originally Robin Lakoff’s and recapitulated by Brown and Levinson (1978:203-4) is that the plural form does not literally single out the addressee.

Brown and Levinson If we assume that what the speaker has to say, or even the sheer fact that the hearer is obliged to listen, is a potential imposition on the hearer’s freedom, than the use of the plural pronoun gives the hearer the option of thanking it as being directed to someone else associated with him or her, not specifically to that person as an individual.

To be continued